Advertisement

The Interrogative Model of Inquiry and Inquiry Learning

Part of the Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning book series (LARI, volume 8)

Abstract

Hakkarainen and Sintonen (Sci Educ 11(1):25–43, 2002) praise the descriptive adequacy of Hintikka’s Interrogative Model of Inquiry (imi) to describe children’s practices in an inquiry-based learning context. They further propose to use the imi as a starting point for developing new pedagogical methods and designing new didactic tools. We assess this proposal in the light of the formal results that in the imi characterize interrogative learning strategies. We find that these results actually reveal a deep methodological issue for inquiry-based learning, namely that educators cannot guarantee that learners will successfully acquire a content, without limiting learner’s autonomy, and that a trade-off between success and autonomy is unavoidable. As a by-product of our argument, we obtain a logical characterization of serendipity.

Keywords

Interrogative model of inquiry Inquiry learning Strategy theorem Logic of discovery Sherlock Holmes 

References

  1. Barber, E., & Merton, R. K. (2004). The travels and adventures of serendipity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Conan Doyle, A. (1986). Sherlock Holmes: The complete novel and stories (Vol. 1). New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
  3. Genot, E. J. (2009). The game of inquiry. The interrogative approach to inquiry and belief revision theory. Synthese, 171, 271–289.Google Scholar
  4. Genot, E. J., & Jacot, J. (2012). How can yes-or-no questions be informative before they are answered? Episteme, 9(2), 189–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Hakkarainen, K., & Sintonen, M. (2002). The interrogative model of inquiry and computer-supported collaborative learning. Science & Education, 11(1), 25–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hintikka, J. (1986). Reasoning about knowledge in philosophy: The paradigm of epistemic logic. In TARK ’86: Proceedings of the 1986 conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge (pp. 63–80). Monterey: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  7. Hintikka, J. (1987). The interrogative approach to inquiry and probabilistic inference. Erkenntnis, 26(3), 429–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Hintikka, J. (1988). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34, 503–533.Google Scholar
  9. Hintikka, J. (1992). The concept of induction in the light of the interrogative approach to inquiry. In J. Earman (Ed.), Inference, explanation, and other philosophical frustrations (pp. 23–43). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  10. Hintikka, J. (2007). Socratic epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hintikka, J., & Halonen, I. (1997). Semantics and pragmatics for why-questions. The Journal of Philosophy, 92, 636–657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hintikka, J., Halonen, I., & Mutanen, A. (2002). Interrogative logic as a general theory of reasoning. In D. M. Gabbay, R. H. Johnson, H. J. Ohlbach, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the logic of argument and inference (Vol. 1, pp. 295–337). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  13. Kelly, K. T. (2004). Uncomputability: The problem of induction internalized. Theoretical Computer Science, 317(1–3), 227–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Martin, E., & Osherson, D. (1998). Elements of scientific inquiry. Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.PhilosophyLund University–LUXLundSweden
  2. 2.Cognitive ScienceLund University–LUXLundSweden

Personalised recommendations