Advertisement

The Epistemological Objection

  • Eva Schmidt
Chapter
  • 394 Downloads
Part of the Studies in Brain and Mind book series (SIBM, volume 8)

Abstract

In this chapter, I rebut three incarnations of the epistemological objection put forth by McDowell (Mind and World, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1994a) and Brewer (Perception and Reason, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1999). According to them, only the assumption that perceptual experiences have conceptual content can account for the fact that perception plays a crucial role in justifying belief about the external world. I begin by providing some context to the objections, viz. by presenting the myth of the given that threatens the foundationalist (Sellars, 1:253–329, 1956). Next, I respond to the objection from the logical space of reasons. I argue that nonconceptual content and nonconceptual mental states are themselves elements of the normative space of reasons and thus fit to enter normative justificatory relations with belief. In response to the second objection, the objection from the inferential nature of justification, I argue that nonconceptual and non-propositional scenario contents can be involved in justification, for experiences with such contents can be the starting points of content-sensitive correctness-truth transitions that have beliefs with Fregean propositional contents as their endpoints. In this Modest Nonconceptualist account of perceptual justification, I rely on the external content of perception and belief, which consists in the states of affairs represented. I defend the account against several conceptualist objections. In my defense against the third objection, an objection from cognitive access, I show that nonconceptual states and their contents can be the subject’s own reasons on a mentalism-inspired picture of perceptual justification. Modest Nonconceptualism can thus respect some of the internalist motivations of the conceptualist.

Keywords

Perceptual Experience Basic Belief Perceptual Justification Perceptual Belief Perceptual Content 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Bibliography

  1. Alston, W. (1989). An internalist externalism. In W. Alston (Ed.), Epistemic justification: essays in the theory of knowledge (pp. 227–245). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. (2009). Questions about states of affairs. In M. Reicher (Ed.), States of affairs (pp. 39–50). Frankfurt: Ontos.Google Scholar
  3. Ayers, M. (2004). Sense experience, concepts and content: objections to Davidson and McDowell. In R. Schumacher (Ed.), Perception and reality: from Descartes to the present (pp. 239–262). Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  4. Bermúdez, J. (2005). Philosophy of psychology: a contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  6. BonJour, L. (1999). The dialectic of foundationalism and coherentism. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 117–144). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. BonJour, L. (2001). Toward a defense of empirical foundationalism. In M. DePaul (Ed.), Resurrecting old-fashioned foundationalism (pp. 21–38). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  8. BonJour, L. (2010a). Epistemological self-profile. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (pp. 114–118). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  9. BonJour, L. (2010b). Recent work on the internalism-externalism controversy. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (pp. 33–43). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  10. Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  11. Brewer, B. (2005). Perceptual experience has conceptual content. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 217–230). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 165–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 503–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Byrne, A. (2005). Perception and conceptual content. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 231–250). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  16. Chisholm, R. M. (1977). Theory of knowledge. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  17. Chuard, P. (n.d.). Perceptual reasons. http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/people-defaults/philippe/perceptual_reasons.pdf. Accessed 27 Oct 2010.
  18. Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Internalism defended. In E. Conee & R. Feldman (Eds.), Evidentialism: essays in epistemology (pp. 53–82). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind: an introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Davidson, D. (1980). Mental events. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Essays on actions and events (pp. 207–225). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  21. Davidson, D. (1986/2008). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In E. Sosa, J. Kim, & M. McGrath (Eds.), Epistemology: an anthology. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  22. Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  23. Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  24. Egan, A. (2006). Appearance properties? Noûs, 40, 495–521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Feldman, R. (2004). In search of internalism and externalism. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge (pp. 143–156). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  26. Firth, R. (1978). Are epistemic concepts reducible to ethical concepts?. In A. Goldman & J. Kim (Eds.), Values and morals (pp. 215–229). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gennaro, R. (2012). The consciousness paradox: consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  28. Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘space of reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109, 483–523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Hopp, W. (2011). Perception and knowledge: a phenomenological account. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  33. Lerman, H. (2010). Non-conceptual experiential content and reason-giving. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Markie, P. (2005). The mystery of direct perceptual justification. Philosophical Studies, 126, 347–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Martin, M. (2001). Epistemic openness and perceptual defeasibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, 441–448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. McDowell, J. (1982/2009c). Criteria, defeasibility and knowledge. In A. Byrne & H. Logue (Eds.), Disjunctivism: contemporary readings (pp. 75–85). Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  37. McDowell, J. (1994a). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  38. McDowell, J. (1994b). The content of perceptual experience. The Philosophical Quarterly, 175, 190–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. McDowell, J. (1998). Reply to commentators. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 403–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. McDowell, J. (2007). What myth? Inquiry, 50, 338–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. McDowell, J. (2009b). Conceptual capacities in perception. In J. McDowell (Ed.), Having the world in view: essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars (pp. 127–144). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  43. Peacocke, C. (2001a). Does perception have a nonconceptual content?. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 239–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Peacocke, C. (2015). Perception and the first person. In M. Matthen (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of perception. Oxford University Press. Manuscript.Google Scholar
  45. Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34, 517–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Pryor, J. (2005). There is immediate justification. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 181–201). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  47. Russell, B. (1959). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 253–329.Google Scholar
  49. Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception?. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne, (Eds.), Perceptual experience (481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Wright, C. (2002a). Human nature? In N. Smith (Ed.), Reading McDowell: on mind and world, (pp. 140–159). London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  • Eva Schmidt
    • 1
  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentSaarland UniversitySaarbrückenGermany

Personalised recommendations