Advertisement

Context-Dependent Anomalies and Strategies for Resolving Disagreement

A Case in Empirical Philosophy of Science
  • Douglas AllchinEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics book series (SAPERE, volume 21)

Abstract

The interpretation and analysis of anomalies is itself theory-dependent, as illustrated in the case of the ox phos debate in biochemistry in the 1960s. Here, the perceived threat of six anomalies to an existing research lineage depended on perspective, or Kuhnian paradigm. The ambiguous status of anomalies sharpens the problem of Kuhnian incommensurability. But analysis of the details of the historical case—one way to pursue an empirical philosophy of science—also indicate a possible solution. The asymmetric organization of multiple anomalies strongly indicated that disagreement had shifted from an intraparadigm to an interparadigm level, where modes of effective argument and use of evidence differ. This diagnostic awareness of the type of disagreement can orient discourse and allow investigators to develop and present evidence appropriately. I briefly extend the results of this historical case analysis to Darwin’s synthesis and to gendered bias in craniology, to indicate the prospective generality of the analysis of anomaly asymmetry.

Keywords

Empirical philosophy of science Anomalies Kuhn Incommensurability Error types Strategies 

References

  1. Allchin, D.: Paradigms, populations and problem fields: approaches to disagreement. PSA 1990(1), 53–66 (1990)Google Scholar
  2. Allchin, D.: Resolving disagreement in science. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago, Chicago (1991)Google Scholar
  3. Allchin, D.: How do you falsify a question? Crucial tests versus crucial demonstrations. PSA 1992(1), 74–88 (1992)Google Scholar
  4. Allchin, D.: The super-bowl and the ox-phos controversy: winner-take-all competition in philosophy of science. PSA 1994(1), 22–33 (1994)Google Scholar
  5. Allchin, D.: Cellular and theoretical chimeras: piecing together how cells process energy. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 27, 31–41 (1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Allchin, D.: A 20th-century phlogiston: constructing error and differentiating domains. Perspect. Sci. 5, 81–127 (1997)Google Scholar
  7. Allchin, D.: Error types. Perspect. Sci. 9, 38–59 (2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bechtel, W., Richardson, R.: Discovering Complexity. IT Press, Cambridge (2010)Google Scholar
  9. Brush, S.G.: Suggestions for the study of science. In: Gavroglu, K., Renn, J. (eds.) Positioning the History of Science [essays in honor of S. S. Schweber]. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 248, pp. 13–25 (2007)Google Scholar
  10. Brush, S.G.: Making 20th Century Science: How Theories Became Knowledge. Oxford Unviersity Press, New York (2015)Google Scholar
  11. Callebaut, W.: Taking the Naturalistic Turn: How the Real Philosophy of Science is Done. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1993)Google Scholar
  12. Darden, L.: Theory Change in Science: Strategies form Mendelian Genetics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1991)Google Scholar
  13. Donovan, A., Laudan, L., Laudan, R.: Scrutinizing Science: Empirical Studies of Scientific Change. Springer, Berlin (1988)Google Scholar
  14. Gilbert, G.N., Mulkay, M.: Opening Pandora’s Box: A Sociological Analysis of Scientists’ Discourse. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1984)Google Scholar
  15. Glymour, C.: Theory and Evidence. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1980)Google Scholar
  16. Hoyningen-Heune, P.: Restructuring Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1993)Google Scholar
  17. Hull, D.: Science as a Process. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hull, D. Testing philosophical claims about science. In PSA 1992, vol. 2, D. Hull, M. Forbes and K. Okruhlik (eds.), East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 468-475 (1993)Google Scholar
  19. Janssen, M.: COI stories. Perspect. Sci. 10, 457–522 (2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Latour, B.: Science in Action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1987)Google Scholar
  21. Lehninger, A.L.: Oxidative phosphorylation in submitochondrial systems. Fed. Proc. 19, 952–962 (1960)Google Scholar
  22. Lightman, A., Gingerich, O.: When do anomalies begin? Science 55, 690–695 (1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Longino, H.: Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ (1990)Google Scholar
  24. Losee, J.: A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1972)Google Scholar
  25. Losee, J.: Philosophy of Science and Historical Enquiry. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1987)Google Scholar
  26. Losee, J.: Theories on the Scrap Heap: Scientists and Philosophers on the Falsification, Rejection and Replacement of Theories. Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh (2005)Google Scholar
  27. Merton, R.K.: The normative structure of science. In: The Sociology of Science, pp. 267–78. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1973)Google Scholar
  28. Mitchell, P.: Coupling of phosphorylation to electron and hydrogen transfer by a chemi-osmotic type of mechanism. Nature 191, 144–148 (1961)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Nickles, T.: Philosophy of science and history of science. Osiris 10, 139–163 (1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Robinson, J.D.: The chemiosmotic hypothesis of energy coupling and the path of scientific opportunity. Perspect. Biol. Med. 27, 367–383 (1984)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Weber, B.: Glynn and the conceptual development of the chemiosmotic theory: a retrospective and prospective view. Biosci. Rep. 11, 577–617 (1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Weber, M.: Incommensurability and theory comparison in experimental biology. Biol. Philos. 17, 155–169 (2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Wimsatt, W.C.: Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2007)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Minnesota Center for the Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of MinnesotaMinneapolisUSA
  2. 2.Science Studies ProgramÅrhus UniversityAarhusDenmark

Personalised recommendations