Advertisement

Licensing NPIs: Some Negative (and Positive) Results

  • Laurence R. HornEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Language, Cognition, and Mind book series (LCAM, volume 1)

Abstract

Leading formal approaches to the “licensor question” for NPIs, invoking properties of downward entailment and nonveridicality, cannot do justice to the full empirical domain. The inadequacy of entailment- and implicature-based theories emerges once we extend the database to cases in which NPIs are awkward or ill-formed despite the availability of a discourse-salient but non-asserted negative proposition, indicating that NPI licensing often depends not on what is entailed or what is implicated but on what is asserted or at issue, and more generally on the speaker’s intended illocutionary point of the utterance. In cases involving sarcasm, polar questions, or pseudo-conditionals, an NPI can only occur after the intended force has been overtly signaled. Thus licensing reflects not only what is at issue but the speaker’s expectations about the hearer’s dynamically constructed discourse model.

Keywords

Assertive (at-issue) content Clefts Downward entailment Flaubert licensing Hyponegation Implicature (Non-)veridicality Sarcasm Pseudo-conditionals Rescuing 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Barbara Abbott, Patricia Amaral, Jay Atlas, Johan Brandtler, Chris Barker, Liz Camp, Ashwini Deo, Kai von Fintel, Anastasia Giannakidou, Chris Gunlogson, Stephanie Harves, Elena Herburger, Jack Hoeksema, Sabine Iatridou, Michael Israel, Sarah Murray, Paul Postal, Chris Potts, William Salmon, Anna Szabolcsi, and those commenting on presentations of related material at Stanford, CUNY, Rutgers, Harvard, Yale, Santa Cruz, Lund, Göteborg, Brussels, Utrecht, and of course Geneva for feedback and suggestions, too many of which I have obstinately ignored. I am also indebted to the late Victor Sánchez Valencia for calling my attention to the relevant medieval manuscripts and to Pierre Larrivée and an anonymous referee for valuable comments on an earlier draft.

References

  1. Amaral, P. (2007). The meaning of approximative adverbs: Evidence from European Portuguese. Ph.D. dissertation, Ohio State University.Google Scholar
  2. Amaral, P. (2010). Entailment, assertion, and textual coherence: the case of almost and barely. Linguistics, 43, 525–545.Google Scholar
  3. Atlas, J. D. (1993). The importance of being ‘only’: Testing the neo-Gricean versus neo-entailment paradigms. Journal of Semantics, 10, 301–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Atlas, J. D. (1996). “Only” noun phrases, pseudo-negative generalized quantifiers, negative polarity items, and monotonicity. Journal of Semantics, 13, 265–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Baker, C. L. (1970). Double negatives. Linguistic Inquiry, 1, 169–186.Google Scholar
  6. Beaver, D., & Clark, B. (2008). Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bellert, I. (1977). On the semantic and distributional properties of sentential adverbs. Linguistic Inquiry, 8, 337–351.Google Scholar
  8. Bender, E., & Kathol, A. (2001). Constructional effects of just because…doesn’t mean. BLS 27.Google Scholar
  9. Bolinger, D. (1968). Postposed main phrases: An English rule for the Romance subjunctive. Canadian Journal of Linguistics, 14, 3–30.Google Scholar
  10. Brandtler, J. (2010). The evaluability hypothesis: The syntax and semantics of polarity item licensing in Swedish. Lund: Centre for Languages and Literature.Google Scholar
  11. Camp, E. (2012). Sarcasm, pretense, and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Noûs, 46, 587–634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Camp, E., & Hawthorne, J. (2008). Sarcastic “like”: A case study in the interface of syntax and semantics. Philosophical Perspectives, 22, 1–21 (Philosophy of Language).Google Scholar
  13. Chemla, E., Homer, V., & Rothschild, D. (2011). Modularity and intuitions in formal semantics: The case of polarity items. Linguistics and Philosophy, 34, 537–570.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Chierchia, G. (2004). Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface. In A. Belletti (Ed.), Structures and beyond (pp. 39–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Chierchia, G. (2013). Logic in grammar: Polarity, free choice, and intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Chierchia, G., Fox, D., & Spector, B. (2013). The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In C. Maienborn et al. (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook (Vol. 2, pp. 2297–2332). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  17. Clark, B. (1993). Relevance and ‘pseudo-imperatives’. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16, 79–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Clifton, C., & Frazier, L. (2010). When are downward-entailing contexts identified? The case of the domain widener even. Linguistic Inquiry, 41, 681–689.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Cutler, A. (1974). On saying what you mean without meaning what you say. CLS, 10, 117–127.Google Scholar
  20. Davies, E. (1986). The English imperative. London: Croom Helm.Google Scholar
  21. De Decker, P., Larsson, E., & Martin, A. (2005). Polarity judgments: An empirical view. Poster presented at the “Polarity from Different Perspectives” Workshop, New York University.Google Scholar
  22. de Rijk, L. M. (Ed.). (1982). Some 14th century tracts on the probationes terminorum. Nijmegen: Ingenium.Google Scholar
  23. Drenhaus, H., Blaszczak, J., & Schütte, J. (2007). Some psycholinguistic comments on NPI licensing. Sinn und Bedeutung, 11, 180–193.Google Scholar
  24. Ducrot, O. (1973). La preuve et le dire. Paris: Mame.Google Scholar
  25. Dundes, A. (2002). Much ado about “sweet bugger all”: Getting to the bottom of a puzzle in British folk speech. Folklore, 113, 35–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. É. Kiss, K. (1998). Identificational focus versus information focus. Language, 74, 245–273.Google Scholar
  27. Fauconnier, G. (1975). Pragmatic scales and logical structure. Linguistic Inquiry, 6, 353–375.Google Scholar
  28. Fox, D. (2006). Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. Ms., MIT.Google Scholar
  29. García-Álvarez, I. (2011). Generality and exception: A study in the semantics of exceptives. Ph.D. dissertation, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  30. Gajewski, J. (2011). Licensing strong NPIs. Natural Language Semantics, 19, 109–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Gajewski, J. (2016, this volume). Another look at NPIs in definite descriptions: An experimental approach. In P. Laurel & C. Lee (Eds.), Negation and polarity: experimental perspectives (pp. 307–327). Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  32. Geurts, B., & Nouwen, R. (2007). ‘At least’ et al.: The semantics of scalar modifiers. Language, 83, 533–559.Google Scholar
  33. Giannakidou, A. (1998). Polarity sensitivity as (non-)veridical dependency. Amsterdam: Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Giannakidou, A. (2006). Only, emotive factives, and the dual nature of polarity dependency. Language, 82, 575–603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Giannakidou, A. (2011). Negative and positive polarity items: Variation, licensing, and compositionality. In C. Maienborn, et al. (Eds.), Semantics: An inter-national handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 2, pp. 1660–1712). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  36. Gunlogson, C. (2003). True to form: rising and falling declaratives as questions in English. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  37. Gunlogson, C. (2008). A question of commitment. Belgian Journal of Linguistics, 22, 101–136.Google Scholar
  38. Gutzmann, D., & Gärtner, H.-M. (Eds.). (2013). Beyond expressives: Explorations in use-conditional meaning. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  39. Haiman, J. (1998). Talk is cheap. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Hedberg, N. (1990). Discourse pragmatics and cleft sentences in English. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Minnesota.Google Scholar
  41. Heim, I. (1984). A note on negative polarity and downward entailingness. NELS, 14, 98–107.Google Scholar
  42. Hirst, G. (1983). Interpreting intonation: A modular approach. Journal of Semantics, 2, 171–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Hitzeman, J. (1992). The selectional properties and entailments of ‘almost’. CLS, 28, 225–238.Google Scholar
  44. Hoeksema, J. (2000). Negative polarity items: Triggering, scope, and C-command. In L. Horn & Y. Kato (Eds.), Negation and polarity: Syntactic and semantic perspectives (pp. 115–146). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Hoeksema, J. (2010). Negative and positive polarity items: An investigation of the interplay of lexical meaning and global conditions on expression. In L. Horn (Ed.), The expression of negation (pp. 187–224). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  46. Horn, L. (1969). A presuppositional analysis of only and even. CLS, 5, 97–108.Google Scholar
  47. Horn, L. (1972). On the semantic properties of logical operators in English. Ph.D. dissertation, UCLA.Google Scholar
  48. Horn, L. (1978). Some aspects of negation. In J. Greenberg, et al. (Eds.), Universals of human language (Vol. 4, pp. 127–210). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Horn, L. (1981). Exhaustiveness and the semantics of clefts. NELS, 11, 125–142.Google Scholar
  50. Horn, L. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  51. Horn, L. (1992). The said and the unsaid. SALT, II, 163–92.Google Scholar
  52. Horn, L. (1996). Exclusive company: Only and the dynamics of vertical inference. Journal of Semantics, 13, 1–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Horn, L. (2001). Flaubert triggers, squatitive negation and other quirks of grammar. In Hoeksema et al. (Eds.), Perspectives on negation and polarity items (pp. 173–202). Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
  54. Horn, L. (2002). Assertoric inertia and NPI licensing. CLS, 38(Part 2), 55–82.Google Scholar
  55. Horn, L. (2009a). Hypernegation, hyponegation, and parole violations. BLS, 35, 403–423.Google Scholar
  56. Horn, L. (2009b). ONLY XL: The assertoric asymmetry of exponibles. SALT, 19, 198–221.Google Scholar
  57. Horn, L. (2011). Almost forever. In E. Yuasa, et al. (Eds.), Pragmatics and autolexical grammar in honor of Jerry Sadock (pp. 3–21). Amsterdam: Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Horn, L. (2013a). Focus and exhaustivity revisited. Paper presented at DGfS, Potsdam.Google Scholar
  59. Horn, L. (2013b). I love me some datives: Expressive meaning, free datives, and F-implicature. In D. Gutzmann & H.-M.Gärtner (Eds.), Beyond expressives: Explorations in use-conditional meaning (pp. 151–201).Google Scholar
  60. Horn, L. (in press). Information structure and the landscape of (non-)at-issue meaning. In C. Féry & S. Ishihara (Eds.), Oxford handbook of information structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  61. Horn, L., & Abbott, B. (2012). <the, a>: (In)definiteness and implicature. In W. Kabasenche et al. (Eds.), Reference and referring: Topics in contemporary philosophy (Vol. 10, pp. 325–355). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  62. Huddleston, R. (1994). The contrast between interrogatives and questions. Journal of Linguistics, 30, 411–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Israel, M. (1996). Polarity sensitivity as lexical semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 19, 619–666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Israel, M. (2011). The grammar of polarity: Pragmatics, sensitivity, and the logic of scales. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Kadmon, N. & Landman, F. (1993). Any. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16, 353–422.Google Scholar
  66. Karttunen, Lauri, & Peters, Stanley. (1979). Conventional implicature. In C.-K. Oh & D. A. Dinneen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 11: Presupposition (pp. 1–56). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  67. Klima, E. (1964). Negation in English. In J. A. Fodor & J. J. Katz (Eds.), The structure of language (pp. 246–323). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  68. Krifka, M. (1995). The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items. Linguistic Analysis, 25, 1–49.Google Scholar
  69. Krifka, M. (2008). Basic notions of information structure. Acta Linguistica Hungarica, 55, 243–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Lawler, J. (1974). Ample negatives. CLS, 10, 357–377.Google Scholar
  71. Ladusaw, W. (1979). Polarity sensitivity as inherent scope relations. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Texas, Austin.Google Scholar
  72. Ladusaw, W. (1983). Logical form and conditions on grammaticality. Linguistics and Philosophy, 6, 389–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Ladusaw, W. (1996). Negation and polarity items. In S. Lappin (Ed.), Handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 299–319). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  74. Larrivée, P. (2007). Du tout au rien: Libre-choix et polarité negative. Paris: Champion.Google Scholar
  75. Lee, Y.-S. & Horn, L. (1994). Any as indefinite plus even. Ms., Yale University.Google Scholar
  76. Linebarger, M. (1980). The grammar of negative polarity as linguistic evidence. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  77. Linebarger, M. (1987). Negative polarity and grammatical representation. Linguistics and Philosophy, 10, 325–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Linebarger, M. (1991). Negative polarity as linguistic evidence. CLS 27, 2, 165–188.Google Scholar
  79. McCawley, James. (1981). Everything that linguists always wanted to know about logic but were ashamed to ask. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  80. Montague, R. (1969). On the nature of certain philosophical entities. The Monist, 53, 159–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Napoli, D. J., & Hoeksema, J. (2009). The grammatical versatility of taboo terms. Studies in Language, 33, 612–643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Ockham, W. (1980). Ockham’s theory of propositions: Part II of the Summa Logicae (A. J. Freddoso Ed., H. Schuurman, Trans.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  83. O’Donnell, J. R. (1941). The Syncategoremata of William of Sherwood. Mediæval Studies, 3, 46–93.Google Scholar
  84. Onea, E., & Beaver, D. (2009). Hungarian focus is not exhausted. SALT, 19, 342–359.Google Scholar
  85. Postal, P. (2004). The structure of one type of American English vulgar minimizer. In Skeptical Linguistic Essays (pp. 159–172). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  86. Postma, G. (2001). Negative polarity and the syntax of taboo. In J. Hoeksema et al. (Eds.), Perspectives on negation and polarity items (pp. 283–330). Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
  87. Potts, C. (2007). The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics, 33, 165–198.Google Scholar
  88. Potts, C. (in press). Presupposition and implicature. In S. Lappin & C. Fox (Eds.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory (2nd edn.) Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  89. Progovac, L. (1994). Negative and positive polarity: A binding approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Rapp, I., & von Stechow, A. (2000). Fast ‘almost’ and the visibility parameter for functional adverbs. Journal of Semantics, 16, 149–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Ross, J. R. (1973). Slifting. In M. Gross et al. (Eds.), The formal analysis of natural languages (pp. 133–169). The Hague: Mouton.Google Scholar
  92. Rothschild, D. (2006). Non-monotonic NPI-licensing, definite descriptions and grammaticalized implicatures. SALT, 16, 228–240.Google Scholar
  93. Sadock, J. (1981). Almost. In P. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp. 257–271). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  94. Sánchez Valencia, V. (1994). Monotonicity in medieval logic. Language and Cognition, 4, 161–174.Google Scholar
  95. Schwenter, S. (2002). Discourse context and polysemy: Spanish casi. In C. Wiltshire & J. Camps (Eds.), Romance philology and variation: selected papers from the 30th linguistic symposium on romance languages (pp. 161–175). Amsterdam: Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Sevi, A. (1998). A semantics for almost and barely. M.A. dissertation, Tel Aviv University.Google Scholar
  97. Sheidlower, J., & Lighter, J. E. (1993). A recent coinage (not!). American Speech, 68, 213–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  98. Simons, M. (2007). Observations on embedding verbs, evidentiality, and presupposition. Lingua, 117, 1034–1056.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  99. Szabolcsi, A. (1981). The semantics of topic-focus articulation. In J. Groenendijk et al. (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 513–540). Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum.Google Scholar
  100. Szabolcsi, A., Bott, L., & McElree, B. (2008). The effect of negative polarity items on inference verification. Journal of Semantics, 25, 411–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  101. Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., Roberts, C., & Simons, M. (2013). Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language, 89, 66–109.Google Scholar
  102. Urmson, J. O. (1952). Parenthetical verbs. Mind, 61, 480–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  103. Vallduví, E. (1992). The informational component. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
  104. van Dongen, W. A., Sr. (1918). At all. Neophilologus, 3, 62–64.Google Scholar
  105. van Rooij, R., & Schulz, K. (2007). Only: meaning and implicature. In M. Aloni, et al. (Eds.), Questions in dynamic semantics (pp. 193–223). London: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  106. Wagner, M. (2008). And, or, and Ø. Snippets, 17, 11.Google Scholar
  107. van der Wouden, T. (1997). Negative contexts: collocation, polarity, and multiple negation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  108. von Fintel, K. (1993). Exceptive constructions. Natural Language Semantics, 1, 123–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  109. von Fintel, K. (1999). NPI-licensing, Strawson-entailment, and context-dependency. Journal of Semantics, 16, 97–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  110. Xiang, M., Dillon, B., & Phillips, C. (2009). Illusory licensing effects across dependency types: ERP evidence. Brain and Language, 108, 40–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  111. Ziegeler, D. (2000). What almost can reveal about counterfactual inferences. Journal of Pragmatics, 32, 1743–1776.Google Scholar
  112. Zimmermann, M., & Onea, E. (2011). Focus marking and focus interpretation. Lingua, 121, 1651–1670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  113. Zwarts, F. (1995). Nonveridical contexts. Linguistic Analysis, 25, 286–312.Google Scholar
  114. Zwarts, F. (1998). Three types of polarity items. In F. Hamm & E. Hinrichs (Eds.), Plurality and quantification (pp. 177–238). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  115. Zwicky, A. (1970). Usually and unusually. Linguistic Inquiry, 1, 145.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of LinguisticsYale UniversityNew HavenUSA

Personalised recommendations