Advertisement

Challenges to Virtue Perspectivism

  • Michael G. Harvey
Chapter
Part of the SpringerBriefs in Electrical and Computer Engineering book series (BRIEFSELECTRIC)

Abstract

A 2-level basic knowledge structure is based on a distinction between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and a corresponding distinction between competences that are not reason-based such as basic trust and competences that are reason-based such as intellectual virtues. Whereas the first type of competence aims to stop the infinite regress of sources or bases for our beliefs, the second type of competence aims to avoid vicious circularity through having an endorsing perspective on our animal competences. To avoid the infinite regress and vicious circularity, this perspective must be comprised of explicit beliefs that are better justified than the implicit beliefs from which they are derived, and the implicit beliefs must be formed non-rationally. These problems remain, however, because there is no clear distinction between animal or unreflective knowledge and reflective knowledge. A 3-level basic knowledge structure is based on an additional distinction between pre-reflective epistemic states (reactions) and unreflective epistemic states (implicit beliefs) at the level of animal knowledge. This distinction allows us to interpret basic trust as a source rather than basis for knowledge that is rooted in pre-reflective reactions that are part of our first nature.

Keywords

Virtue Ethic Natural Reaction Intellectual Virtue Animal Knowledge Infinite Regress 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. 1.
    Sosa E (2009) Apt belief and reflective knowledge. Vol. 2: Reflective knowledge. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Rescher N (1992) A system of pragmatic idealism. Vol. 1: Human knowledge in idealistic perspective, Chaps 2, 4, 10. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Wolterstorff N (2003) Review of Virtue epistemology: essays on epistemic virtue and responsibility. Ethics 113(4):876–879CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Sosa E (2007) Apt belief and reflective knowledge. Vol. 1: A virtue epistemology. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Strawson PF (1985) Skepticism, naturalism and transcendental arguments. In: Skepticism and naturalism: some varieties. Methuen, London, pp 1–25Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Wittgenstein L (1969) Anscombe GEM, von Wright GH (eds) On certainty (trans: Paul D, Anscombe, GEM). Harper Torchbooks, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Hegel GWF (1975) Hegel’s logic: being part one of the encyclopaedia of the philosophical sciences (trans: Wallace W), 3rd edn. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Wittgenstein L (1958) Philosophical investigations (trans: Anscombe, GEM), 3rd edn. Macmillan, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Reid T (1983) Beanblossom RE, Lehrer K (eds) Thomas Reid’s inquiry and essays. Hackett, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Wittgenstein L (1980) Von Wright GH, Nyman H (eds) Culture and value (trans: Winch P). University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Johns Hopkins UniversityPittsburghUSA

Personalised recommendations