Skip to main content

The Importance of Phronesis to Corporate Social Responsibility

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Corporate Social Responsibility and Governance

Part of the book series: CSR, Sustainability, Ethics & Governance ((CSEG))

  • 4326 Accesses

Abstract

Accepting that corporate social responsibility (CSR) demands that when deliberating about business any economic agent ought to take into account the interests of all stakeholders, i.e. clients, consumers, suppliers, employees, among others, CSR challenges economic rationality, understood as a maximization of individual utilities. CSR is best described under the Aristotelian conception of rationality, i.e. phronesis. Actually, phronesis is the practical wisdom that relates individual interest with the collective. From this conception of rationality the main claim of CRS – to consider others’ interests in economic deliberation – not only follows necessarily the reasoning of any business agent, but also coheres easily with moral theory if this is defined from an Aristotelian perspective rather than from a utilitarian or deontological perspective.

Roughly, if utilitarianism implies the maximization of well-being of the majority, it is ethically acceptable to discriminate some stakeholders in order to increase the well-being of the majority (e.g. employees vs. clients). On the other hand, besides the well-known issue of the possibility of comparison utilities, utilitarianism does not offer a rule to choose utilities of equal value. From a deontological perspective not only is it hardly acceptable to link corporate social responsibility with profit – ethical claims are not compatible either with the consideration of consequences of our practices or non moral considerations – but also Kantian deontology does not offer a rule to decide about competing duties. From moral deontology corporate agents can face the dilemma whether to increase profit and neglect CRS or to be socially responsible and to ignore profit.

Facing these difficulties, I argue in my paper that not only does CSR cohere better with the Aristotelian conception of morality, grounded in phronesis, than with others normative ethical theories, mainly utilitarianism or Kantian deontology, but also that under Aristotelian ethics CSR is at the heart of an agent’s practice in corporations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “A primary stakeholder group is one without whose continuing participation the corporation cannot survive as a going concern” (Clarkson 1995: 106).

  2. 2.

    Secondary stakeholders are “those who influence or affect, or are influenced or affected by, the corporation but they are not engaged in transactions with the organization and are not essential for its survival” (Clarkson 1995: 107).

  3. 3.

    Levitt (1958) clearly acknowledged that challenge when, against the idea that under corporate social responsibility “(…) profits must be merely adequate, not maximum” (Levitt 1958: 42), he proclaimed that “the business of business is profits” (Levitt 1958: 42).

  4. 4.

    www.theguardian.com/…/ikea-apologises-removing-women-saudi-arabia-catalogue (accessed on 23 November, 2013).

  5. 5.

    www.wsws.org/en/articles/2003/05/kade-m16.html

  6. 6.

    www.nytimes.com/…/report-on-Bangladesh-building-collapse-finds-widespread-blame.html

  7. 7.

    http://wordsmith.org/words/buridans_ass.html

References

  • Akerloff, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. (2010). Identity economics: How our identities shape our work, wages, and well-being. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Altman, M. (2007). The decomposition of corporate body. What Kant cannot contribute to business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 74, 253–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1999). Nicomachean ethics. (trans: Irwin, T., with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary). Indianapolis Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D., & Bowie, N. E. (2008). Sweatshops and respect for persons. In T. Beauchamp, N. Bowie, & D. Arnold (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (8th ed., pp. 608–624). Upper Saddle River: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Athanassoulis, N., & Ross, A. (2010). A virtue ethical account of making decisions about risk. Journal of Risk Research, 13(2), 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aubenque, P. (1963). La Prudence chez Aristote. France: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beabout, G. R. (2012). Management as a domain-relative practice that requires and develops practical wisdom. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(2), 405–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T., Bowie, N., & Arnold, D. (Eds.). (2008). Ethical theory and business (8th ed.). New Jersey: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1789). In J. H. Burns & H. L. A. Hart (Eds.), An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. London: The Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhuyan, N. (2007). The role of character in ethical decision-making. Journal of Value Inquiry, 41(1), 45–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bollier, D., & Weiss, S. (1991). Merck & Co. Inc. The Business Enterprise Trust.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, N. (1991). New directions in corporate social responsibility. Business Horizons, 34(4), 56–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, N., & Arnold, D. (Eds.). (2008). Ethical theory in business. Upper Saddle River: Pearson Education International: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowmen, H. R. (1953). Social responsibilities of the businessman. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R., & Sowden, L. (Eds.). (1985). Paradoxes of rationality and cooperation: Prisoner’s dilemma and Newcomb’s problem. Vancouver: The University of British Columbia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, A. B. (1979). A three-dimensional conceptual model for corporate performance. Academy of Management Review, 4(4), 497–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarkson, M. B. E. (1995). A stakeholder framework for analyzing and evaluating corporate social performance. Academy of Management Review, 20(1), 92–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, D. (2006). Behaving badly. Ethical lessons from Enron. Indianapolis: Dog Ear Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, J. (1991). The ethics of self-concern. Ethics, 191(4), 798–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R., & Slote, M. (Eds.). (1997). Virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De George, R. T. (2010). Business ethics. Boston: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, L. C. (2010). From rational to wise action: Recasting our theories of entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Ethics, 92(4), 513–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, L., McVea, J., & Freeman, R. E. (2008). Entrepreneurial wisdom: Incorporating the ethical and strategic dimensions of entrepreneurial decision-making. International Journal of Entrepreneurship and Small Business, 6(1), 8–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. (1993). A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In T. Beauchamp, N. Bowie, & D. Arnold (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (4th ed., pp. 75–84). Upper Saddle River: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fadiman, J. (2010). Foreign corrupt practices: How to deal with Foreign forms of Bribery. In W. Shaw & V. Barry (Eds.), Moral issues in business (pp. 587–597). Belmont: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics, 4(4), 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (2008). Managing for stakeholders. In T. Beauchamp, N. Bowie, & D. Arnold (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (8th ed., pp. 56–68). Upper Saddle River: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E., Harrison, J., & Wicks, A. C. (2007). Managing for stakeholders: Survival, reputation and success. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1970, September 13). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garriga, E., & Melé, D. (2004). Corporate social responsibility. Mapping the territory. Journal of Business Ethics, 53, 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1985). Maximization constrained: The rationality of cooperation. In R. Campbell & L. Sowden (Eds.), Paradoxes of rationality and cooperation: Prisoner’s dilemma and Newcomb’s problem (pp. 75–93). Vancouver: The University of British Columbia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giovanola, B., & Fermani, A. (2012). Ethics, economic organizations, and human flourishing: Lessons from Plato and Aristotle. In G. P. Prastacos, F. Wang, & K. E. Soderquist (Eds.), Leadership through the classics (pp. 273–388). Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1977). Morality and prisoners’ dilemma: Comments on Baier’s paper. Erkenntnis, 11, 441–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. M. (2001). Character and leadership. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 20, 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. (2008). Socratic questions and Aristotelian answers: A virtue-based approach to business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 78(3), 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. (2009). Teaching business ethics with Aristotle. In S. Gregg & J. Stoner (Eds.), Profit prudence and virtue: Essays in ethics business and management (pp. 155–173). Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2006). Business ethics without stakeholders. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16(3), 533–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N. (2007). Maximization, incomparability, and managerial choice. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 497–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. (1976). Theory of the firm: Managerial behaviour, agency cost, and capital structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3, 305–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, J., & Patapan, H. (2006). In search of prudence: The hidden problem of managerial reform. Public Administration Review, 66(5), 711–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1785/1968). Grundlegund zur Metaphysik der Sitten. In: W. Weischedel (Ed.), Immanuel Kant werksausgabe. Band VI. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knippenberg, L., & Jong, E. B. P. (2010). Moralising the market by moralising the firm: Towards a firm-oriented perspective of corporate social responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics, 96, 17–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lager, F. (1994). Ben & Jerry’s: The inside scoop. New York: Crown Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lantos, G. P. (2002). The ethicality of altruistic corporate social responsibility. Journal of Consumer Marketing, 19(3), 205–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt, T. (1958). The dangers of social responsibility. Harvard Business Review, September–October, 41–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockett, A., Moon, J., & Visser, W. (2006). Corporate social responsibility in management research: Focus, nature and sources of influence. Journal of Management Studies, 43(1), 115–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A., Baden, D., & Guidi, M. (2012). Can an ethical revival of prudence within prudential regulation tackle corporate psychopathy? Journal of Business Ethics, SSN 0167-4544. doi:10.1007/s10551-012-1547-4.

  • McKenna, B. (2005). Wisdom, ethics and the postmodern organization. In D. Rooney, G. Hearn, & A. Ninan (Eds.), Handbook on the knowledge economy (pp. 37–53). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, B., & Rooney, D. (2012). Wise face of organizations. In M. A. Sarlak (Ed.), The new faces of organizations in the 21st century: A management and business reference book (pp. 243–272). Toronto: NAISIT Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1863/1998). In R. Crisp (Ed.), Utilitarianism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirrlees, J. A. (1982). The economic issues of utilitarianism. In A. Sen & B. Williams (Eds.), Utilitarianism and beyond (pp. 63–84). Cambridge: Press Syndicate of the University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moberg, D. (2007). Practical wisdom and business ethics. Presidential address to the society of business ethics Atlanta, August 2006. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 535–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moberg, D. J. (2008). Mentoring and practical wisdom: Are mentors wise or just more politically skilled? Journal of Business Ethics, 83(4), 835–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, J. V., & Morgenstern, O. (1953). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyberg, D. (2008). The morality of everyday activities: Not the right, but the good thing to do. Journal of Business Ethics, 81(3), 587–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinkston, T. S., & Carrol, A. B. (1996). A retrospective examination of CSR orientations: Have they changed? Journal of Business Ethics, 15, 199–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queiroz, R. (2012). The importance of phronesis as communal business ethics reasoning principle. Philosophy of Management, 11(2), 49–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rego, A., & Cunha, M. P. (2008). Perceptions of authentizotic climates and employee happiness: Pathways to individual performance? Journal of Business Research, 61, 739–752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Renouard, C. (2011). Corporate social responsibility, utilitarianism, and the capabilities approach. Journal of Business Ethics, 98, 85–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. (1945). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, D., & McKenna, B. (2006). Should the knowledge-based economy be a savant or a sage? Wisdom and socially intelligent innovation. Prometheus: Critical Studies in Innovation, 23(3), 307–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, D., & McKenna, B. (2007). Wisdom in organizations: Whence and Whither. Social Epistemology, 21(2), 113–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossouw, D. (2008). Practicing applied ethics with philosophical integrity: The case of business ethics. Business Ethics: A European Review, 17(2), 161–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, M. S., & Carroll, A. B. (2003). Corporate social responsibility: A three domain approach. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(4), 503–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1977). Rationality and morality: A reply. Erkenntnis, 11, 225–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1987). On ethics and economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1990). Individual freedom as a social commitment. New York Review of Books, 37(10), 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1997). Maximization and the act of choice. Econometrica, 65(4), 745–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The ideal of justice. England: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1983). Reason in human affairs. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations, 2 Vols., London: W. Strahan and T. Cadell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sollars, G., & Englander, F. G. (2007). Sweatshops: Kant and consequences. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(1), 115–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1993). Ethics and excellence: Cooperation and integrity in business. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staler, M., Roos, J., & Victor, B. (2006). Illustrating the need for practical wisdom. International Journal of Management Concepts and Philosophy, 2(1), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staveren, I. V. (2007). Beyond utilitarianism and deontology: Ethics in economics. Review of Political Economy, 19(1), 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taneja, S. S., Taneja, P. K., & Gupta, R. K. (2011). Research in corporate social responsibility: A review of shifting focus, paradigms, and methodologies. Journal of Business Ethics, 101, 343–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H., & Cummings, S. (1997). Marginalization and recovery: The emergence of Aristotelian themes in organizations studies. Organization Studies, 18, 655–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varley, P. (1998). The sweatshop quandary: Corporate responsibility on the global frontier. Washington, DC: Investor Responsibility Research Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. G. (1992). Business ethics: Concepts and cases (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. G. (2000). Globalization and the failure of ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 343–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vos, J. F. J. (2003). Corporate social responsibility and the identification of stakeholders. Corporate Social Responsibility and Environmental Management, 10(3), 141–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weirich, P. (2004). Economic rationality. In A. Mele & P. Rawling (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of rationality (pp. 380–398). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. H. (2008). Exporting mental models: Global capitalism in the twenty-first century. In T. Beauchamp, N. Bowie, & D. Arnold (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (8th ed., pp. 590–596). Upper Saddle River: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, D. (2013). Corporate social responsibility and irresponsibility: A positive theory approach. Journal of Business Research, 66, 1937–1944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Regina Queiroz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Queiroz, R. (2015). The Importance of Phronesis to Corporate Social Responsibility. In: Idowu, S., Frederiksen, C., Mermod, A., Nielsen, M. (eds) Corporate Social Responsibility and Governance. CSR, Sustainability, Ethics & Governance. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10909-1_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics