Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory ((SNLT,volume 91))

  • 749 Accesses

Abstract

The paper has proposed a theory of structural focus which analyzes focus movement as the establishment of a syntactic predicate–subject structure, expressing specificational predication. The subject of the specificational construction, an open sentence, determines a set, which the predicate (the focus-moved constituent) identifies referentially. The subject of predication is associated with an existential presupposition (only an existing set can be referentially identified). The referential identification of a set consists in the exhaustive listing of its members—hence the exhaustivity of focus. It is claimed that this analysis also accounts for properties of focus movement constructions that current alternative theories cannot explain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also Kiss (1998, 2009), and Horvath (2005, 2006). For a somewhat different view, treating the exhaustivity of focus as an implicature, see Wedgwood (2005).

  2. 2.

    For previous formulations of this proposal, see Kiss (2006a, b). For an extension of Higgins’ (1973) analysis to English truncated clefts, see Mikkelsen (2004).

  3. 3.

    Mikkelsen (2004) argues that the predicate of a specificational construction is, nevertheless, more referential than its subject.

  4. 4.

    Although in subsequent stages of the derivation, Q-raising and topicalization can remove certain constituents of the postfocus unit (the subject of predication), they remain represented by their copies in postverbal position.

  5. 5.

    NNP stands for Non-Neutral Phrase; it is a term of Olsvay (2000).

  6. 6.

    The postverbal section of the Hungarian sentence, i.e., the vP in (14), and the PredP in (15), can be freely linearized. The optimal postverbal order is that observing Behaghel’s (1932) Law of Growing Constituents—see Kiss (2008).

  7. 7.

    According to Geurts and van der Sandt (2004), the background is associated with an existential presupposition in all types of focus constructions. They call the following rule ‘the null hypothesis’

    (i) The Background-Presupposition Rule

    Whenever focusing gives rise to a background λx.φ(x), there is a presupposition to the effect that λx.φ(x) holds of some individual.

  8. 8.

    Delin and Oberlander (1995) make a similar claim about the subordinate clause of cleft sentences: they count as presuppositional also when they convey information that is expected to be known.

  9. 9.

    The English equivalents of (7b) and (16b) are called comment-clause clefts by Delin and Oberlander (1995).

  10. 10.

    Puskas (2000:342) claims that this does not hold in Hungarian, on the basis of examples like.According to Surányi (2002), the constraint formulated by Giannakidou and Quer (1995) does not apply to all-type universal quantifiers. However, in Hungarian, every and all-type quantifiers do not seem to differ in the relevant respect (neither of them can be focussed). In my analysis, Emőke is the predicate nominal in (i), and minden örömem is the subject. If minden örömem were a predicate nominal, it ought to be able to precede the verb volt (occupying first Spec, PredP, and then Q-raised into a PredP-adjoined position). Furthermore, if Emőke were the subject, it ought to be able to undergo topicalization, i.e., to occupy an unstressed clause-initial position. Both of these moves are impossibleCf. A reviewer mentions that if Emőke is the predicate of this sentence, it will reject a nonrestrictive relative clause. This is, indeed, the case:The reviewer also mentions that in the English She is my every dream, where the quantifier occurs inside (rather than on the edge of) the predicate nominal, the noun phrase my every dream is not outwardly quantificational: Someone made my every dream come true does not support a distributive reading. This does not hold for Hungarian; in example (vi), the noun phrase is Q-raised, and is interpreted distributively

  11. 11.

    In fact, a semantically incorporated theme or goal argument occupying Spec, PredP, the position of secondary predicates, can be represented by a bare nominal.

  12. 12.

    Hungarian verbs of (coming into) being and creation also have particle verb counterparts, which denote the change of their theme, whose existence is presupposed. These particle verbs, as opposed to their bare V equivalents, select a [+specific] theme

References

  • Behaghel, Otto. 1932. Deutsche Syntax IV. Heidelberg: Carl Winters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delin, Judy J., Jon, Oberlander. 1995. Syntactic constraints on discourse structure: the case of it-clefts. Linguistics 33/3.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 1995. Definiteness effect revisited. In: Levels and structures. Approaches to Hungarian, ed. István Kenesei, Vol. 5, 65–88. Szeged: JATE.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 1998. Identificational focus versus information focus. Language 74: 245–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 2006a. Apparent or real? On the complementary distribution of identificational focus and the verbal particle. In: Event structure and the left periphery. Studies on Hungarian, ed. É. Kiss, Katalin, 201–224. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 2006. Focussing as predication. In The architecture of focus, ed. Valéria Molnár, and Susanne Winkler, 169–193. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 2008. Free word order, (non–)configurationality, and phases. Linguistic Inquiry 39: 441–475.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Kiss, Katalin. 2009. Structural focus and exhanstivity. In Information structure: theoretical, typological, and experimental perspectives, ed. Caroline Féry, and Malte Zimmermann. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fanselow, Gisbert. 2006. On pure syntax. In Form, structure and grammar, ed. P. Brandt, and E. Fuss. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, Bart, and Rob Sandt. 2004. Interpreting focus. Theoretical Linguistics 30: 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, Roger F. 1973. The pseudo-cleft construction in English. PhD diss., MIT

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence R. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators in English. Ph.D. diss., UCLA

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, Julia. 2005. Is “Focus Movement” driven by stress? In: Approaches to Hungarian 9. Papers from the Düsseldorf Conference, eds. Christopher Piñón and Péter Siptár, 131–158. Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, Julia. 2006. Separating “Focus Movement” from focus. In Clever and Right: A Festschrift for Joe Emonds, ed. V.S.S. Karimi, et al. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, Stefan. 2000. Es-Clefts und det-Clefts. Stockholm: Almquist and Wiksell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadmon, N. 2001. Formal pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S.C. 2000. Presumptive meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, Line H. L. 2004. Specifying who: on the structure, meaning, and use of specificational copular clauses. PhD diss., University of California Santa Cruz

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsvay, Csaba. 2000. Formális jegyek egyeztetése a magyar nemsemleges mondatokban. In A mai magyar nyelv leírásának újabb módszerei IV, ed. László Büky, and Márta Maleczki, 119–151. Szeged: SZTE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, Barbara. 1987. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In: Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers, GRASS 8, eds. J. Groenendijk, D. de Jongh, and M. Stokhof, 115–143. Dordrecht: Foris

    Google Scholar 

  • Peredy, Márta. 2009. Obligatory adjuncts licensing definiteness effect constructions. In: Adverbs and adverbial adjuncts at the interfaces, ed. Katalin É. Kiss, 197–230. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter

    Google Scholar 

  • Piñón, Christopher. 2006a. Definiteness effect verbs. In: Event structure and the left periphery, ed. Katalin É. Kiss, 75–90. Dordrecht: Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Piñón, Christopher. 2006b. Weak and strong accomplishments. In: Event structure and the left periphery, ed. Katalin É. Kiss, 91–106. Dordrecht: Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Puskás, Genovéva. 2000. Word order in Hungarian: the syntax of A–bar positions. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, Tanya. 1995. Interface strategies. OTS Working Papers (TL-95-002).

    Google Scholar 

  • Surányi, Balázs. 2002. Multiple operator movements in Hungarian. Utrecht: LOT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, Anna. l981. The semantics of topic–focus articulation. In: Formal methods in the study of language, eds. J. Groenendijk et al., 513–540. Amsterdam: Matematisch Centrum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, Anna. 1986. From the definiteness effect to lexical integrity. In Topic, focus, and configurationality, ed. Werner Abraham, and Sjaak de Meij, 321–348. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Szendrői, Kriszta. 2003. A stress-based approach to the syntax of Hungarian focus. The Linguistic Review 20: 37–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, Daniel. 2005. Shifting the focus. From static structures to the dynamics of interpretation. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zubizarreta, Maria. 1998. Prosody, focus, and word order. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katalin É. Kiss .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kiss, K.É. (2017). Deriving the Properties of Structural Focus. In: Lee, C., Kiefer, F., Krifka, M. (eds) Contrastiveness in Information Structure, Alternatives and Scalar Implicatures. Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol 91. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10106-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10106-4_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-10105-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-10106-4

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics