Skip to main content

Semi-Formal Calculi and Their Applications

  • Chapter

Abstract

By a semi-formal system we understand a proof system which includes infinitary inference rules. The use of inference rules with infinitely many premises was already suggested by David Hilbert in his paper “Die Grundlegung der elementaren Zahlentheorie” [6] and was later systematically used by Kurt Schütte in his work on proof theory. The heigths of proof trees in a semi-formal system are canonically measured by ordinals. Therefore, in contrast to Gentzen’s original approach, ordinals enter proof theoretic research via semi-formal systems in a completely canonical way.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Observe, however, that atomic formulas may well belong to a type. Cf., e.g., Definition 2.10 below.

  2. 2.

    That is, languages that comprise a complete set of Boolean operations, first order variables and the first order quantifiers \(\forall \) and \(\exists \) (either explicitly or by definition) together with a set of non-logical symbols and—possibly—a set of free predicate variables.

  3. 3.

    This ensures that the semantics defined in Definition 2.4 coincides with the usual semantics for first order languages.

  4. 4.

    We write \(F \simeq \bigwedge \mbox{ $\left \langle { G_{\iota }\vert \,\iota \in I}\right \rangle $}\) to indicate that F is in \({\bigwedge-\mathsf{type}}\) and \(\mbox{ CS}(F) = \mbox{ $\left \langle { G_{\iota }\vert \,\iota \in I}\right \rangle $}\). Similarly we use \(F \simeq \bigvee \mbox{ $\left \langle { G_{\iota }\vert \,\iota \in I}\right \rangle $}\).

  5. 5.

    It only says that every \(\mathfrak{M}\)-assignment \(\Phi \) that satisfies all formulas in T also satisfies F in \(\mathfrak{M}\).

  6. 6.

    Which means that there are many term-models according to the interpretation of the relation constants.

  7. 7.

    Cf. [1, III, Proposition 1.4].

  8. 8.

    For full generality we need a domain \(\mathsf{S}^{k} \subseteq \mbox{ Pow}\big(\vert \mathfrak{M}\vert \big)^{k}\) for every quantifier on k-ary predicate variables. The restriction to unary predicate variables is in fact only a matter of simplifying notations.

  9. 9.

    This is of course not surprising because weak first order logic is in fact nothing but a two sorted first order logic.

  10. 10.

    \(\mbox{ rnk}(t \in \mathsf{M}) = \mbox{ rnk}(t\notin \mathsf{M}) = 1\) will work in most cases, especially in the case that the basis language is the first order language of \(\mathfrak{M}\).

  11. 11.

    According to this extension M and \(\mathsf{M}^{c}\) are interpreted by the definition of CS(t ∈ M) and CS(tM), respectively.

  12. 12.

    Observe the peculiarity that for \(m \in \vert \mathfrak{M}\vert \) we have a constant \(\underline{m}\) in \(\mathbf{L}_{\mathfrak{M}}^{+}\) and thus a constant \(\underline{\underline{m}}\) in \(\mathbf{L}_{\mathfrak{T}}^{\mathfrak{M}}\). The interpretation of \(\underline{\underline{m}}\) in the extended model \((\mathfrak{T}_{\mathbf{L}_{\mathfrak{M}}})_{\mathfrak{T}_{\mathbf{L}_{ \mathfrak{M}}}}\) is \(\underline{m}\) and the interpretation of \(\underline{m}\) in \(\mathfrak{T}_{\mathbf{L}_{\mathfrak{M}}}\) is m. Thus \((R\underline{\underline{m}}_{1},\ldots,\underline{\underline{m}}_{k})\) belongs to the diagram of \((\mathfrak{T}_{\mathbf{L}_{\mathfrak{M}}})_{\mathfrak{T}_{\mathbf{L}_{ \mathfrak{M}}}}\) iff \((R\underline{m}_{1},\ldots,\underline{m}_{k})\) belongs to the diagram of \(\mathfrak{T}_{\mathfrak{M}}\) iff \((Rm_{1},\ldots,m_{k})\) belongs to the diagram of \(\mathfrak{M}\).

  13. 13.

    Cf. [1, II Sect. 5].

  14. 14.

    An L-formula is X positive if the dual variable \(X^{c}\) does not occur in the Tait version of L.

  15. 15.

    Cf. [10, Sect. 11.9] for the definition of a semi-decorated language for the constructible hierarchy L α .

  16. 16.

    Cf. [1] for the use of extended first order- and extended \(\Pi _{1}^{1}\)-formulas.

  17. 17.

    Since we are working with the first order logic \(\mathsf{L}(\mathfrak{M})\) of \(\mathfrak{M}\) as basis language we denote from now on truth complexity briefly by \(\mbox{ tc}_{\mathfrak{M}}(F)\) instead of \(\mbox{ tc}_{\mathsf{L}(\mathfrak{M})_{\mathfrak{M}}}(F)\).

  18. 18.

    Cf. Remark  5.23.

References

  1. J. Barwise, Admissible Sets and Structures. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic (Springer, Berlin, 1975)

    Google Scholar 

  2. A. Beckmann, W. Pohlers, Application of cut–free infinitary derivations to generalized recursion theory. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 94, 1–19 (1998)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. G. Gentzen, Beweisbarkeit und Unbeweisbarkeit von Anfangsfällen der transfiniten Induktion in der reinen Zahlentheorie Math. Ann. 119, 140–161 (1943)

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. J.-Y. Girard, Une extension de l’interpretation de Gödel a l’analyse et son application a l’elimination des coupures dans l’analyse et la theorie des types, in Proceedings of the 2nd Scandinavian Logic Symposium, ed. by J.E. Fenstad. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 63 (North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1971), pp. 63–92

    Google Scholar 

  5. L. Henkin, A generalization of the notion of ω-consistency. J. Symb. Log. 19, 183–196 (1954)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. D. Hilbert, Die Grundlegung der elementaren Zahlenlehre. Math. Ann. 104, 485–494 (1931)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. M. Möllerfeld, Systems of inductive definitions. Ph.D. thesis, Münster, 2003

    Google Scholar 

  8. Y.N. Moschovakis, Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 77 (North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1974)

    Google Scholar 

  9. S. Orey, On ω-consistency and related properties. J. Symb. Log. 21, 246–252 (1956)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  10. W. Pohlers, Proof Theory. The First Step into Impredicativity. Universitext (Springer, Berlin, 2009)

    Google Scholar 

  11. M. Rathjen, An ordinal analyis of stability. Arch. Math. Log. 48/2, 1–62 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  12. K. Schütte, Syntactical and semantical properties of simple type theory. J. Symb. Log. 25, 305–326 (1960)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. W.W. Tait, A non constructive proof of Gentzen’s Hauptsatz for second order predicate logic. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 72, 980–983 (1966)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. G. Takeuti, On a generalized logic calculus. Jpn. J. Math. 24, 149–156 (1953)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wolfram Pohlers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pohlers, W. (2015). Semi-Formal Calculi and Their Applications. In: Kahle, R., Rathjen, M. (eds) Gentzen's Centenary. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10103-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics