Skip to main content

Towards a Widely Acceptable Framework for the Study of Personal Well-Being

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Well-Being in Contemporary Society

Part of the book series: Happiness Studies Book Series ((HAPS))

Abstract

Findings from the burgeoning study of personal well-being (PWB) are both interesting and important. The study of PWB is beginning to attract the attention of the media, laypersons and public policy practitioners. However, the ways in which PWB findings are prudentially relevant (i.e. related to well-being) are unclear and controversial. This is not a good situation for the study of PWB; in order for such findings to be used effectively and justifiably, we need a prudential framework that is widely acceptable. In this paper, I argue that a widely acceptable account of the prudential relevance of PWB must (at least for the time being) be theory-neutral with regards to the nature of well-being. Theories of well-being are controversial, and thereby not widely acceptable. I provide an account of the prudential relevance of PWB that does not rely on a particular theory of well-being. The theory-neutral account maintains that PWB tends to be (a) an indicator of well-being, (b) a value, and (c) a benefit. This account can provide us with widely acceptable (albeit limited) interpretations of findings from the study of PWB.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This use of terminology is in-line with the UK’s National Well-being Programme, which refers to subjective measures of well-being (which includes measures of SWB and EWB) as measures of “personal well-being” (Oguz et al. 2013).

  2. 2.

    PWB researchers may also aim to measure certain mental states that can be viewed as non-evaluative, such as chronic pleasures and pains. Such mental states may not consist in their subject having some kind of evaluative attitude towards their own well-being. Nonetheless, I think we can make the general claim that PWB researchers aim to measure a subject’s (affective and cognitive) evaluations of their own well-being.

  3. 3.

    Affect balance measures and life and domain satisfaction measures are typically referred to as measures of “subjective well-being” (Deiner & Biswas-Diener 2008). Eudaimonic measures are typically referred to as measures of “eudaimonic well-being” or “psychological well-being” (Ryff 1989; Keyes et al. 2002; Ryan and Deci 2001). As mentioned above, I will refer to all subjective measures of well-being as measures of “personal well-being”.

  4. 4.

    Measures of “flow”—the mental state associated with “optimal functioning”—can be viewed as a measure of eudaimonic well-being in this sense. States of flow are positive affective states related to successful performance in activities that are challenging, yet not too difficult. It is a particular sense of mastery that arises from the skillful exercise of one’s capacities (Csikszentmihalyi and Csikszentmihalyi 1992).

  5. 5.

    For instance, when measuring a subject’s general well-being, both affect balance and life satisfaction measures tend to be highly correlated. But, measures of affect balance are not significantly correlated with measures of religiosity, and measures of life satisfaction are not significantly correlated with measures of personality and locus of control (Chen et al. 2012).

  6. 6.

    See also Deaton (2010), Veenhoven and Hagerty (2006) and Stevenson and Wolfers (2008) for further critiques of the Easterlin Paradox.

  7. 7.

    Though Diener et al. (2006) show that individuals differ in the extent to which certain life conditions caused lasting changes in subjective well-being.

  8. 8.

    See, for instance, Haybron (2008) on the limits of self-reports in measuring happiness.

  9. 9.

    Of course, PWB may be normatively relevant in certain ways other than its relationship to well-being. For instance, increases in positive affect have been shown to make people more altruistic (Carlson et al. 1988). However, for the purposes of this paper, I restrict my focus just towards the prudential relevance of PWB, that is, the relationship between PWB and well-being.

  10. 10.

    See http://www.actionforhappiness.og.

  11. 11.

    See http://www.happycity.org.

  12. 12.

    See http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons/guide-method/user-guidance/well-being/index.html.

  13. 13.

    This is not to say that we necessarily care about our well-being, or that the promotion of our well-being provides us with reasons to act in certain ways. For example, Scanlon explains that, “If you ask me why I listen to music, I may reply that I do so because I enjoy it. If you asked me why that is a reason, the reply “A life that includes enjoyment is a better life” would not be false, but it would be rather strange.” (Scanlon 1998: 126) The things we care about (such as enjoyments, success in one’s main aims, and substantive goods such as friendship) are not necessarily desirable because they promote our well-being. These things all contribute towards well-being, but the idea of well-being plays little role in explaining why they are good. Thus, Scanlon labels well-being an “inclusive good”—one that is made up of other things that are good in their own right, not made good by their contributions to it (Scanlon 1998: 127).

  14. 14.

    I will follow recent work by well-being theorists (e.g. Woodard 2013; Fletcher forthcoming) in classify philosophical theories of well-being in relation to these two major disagreements. Note that this differs from the traditional method of classification—the tri-partite division of theories of well-being into mental state theories, preference-satisfaction theories and objective list theories—influentially outlined by Derek Parfit (1984).

  15. 15.

    These are the kinds of arguments offered by proponents of PWB in interpreting PWB findings such as the Easterlin paradox (Nussbaum 2000; Sen 1999).

  16. 16.

    For an excellent overview of the benefits of positive affect see Haybron (forthcoming).

  17. 17.

    See also Carver (2003).

References

  • Angner, E. (2010). Commentary: Valerie Tiberius on well-being for philosophers. Wellbeing: A Cure-All for the Social Sciences? Blackwell-Wiley Online Conference. http://wileyblackwellwellbeing.wordpress.com/2010/11/16/conference-paper-well-being-psychological-research-for-philosophers/#more-451.

  • Booth, P. (Ed.) 2012. …and the Pursuit of Happiness: Wellbeing and the Role of Government. London: Institute of Economic Affairs http://www.iea.org.uk/sites/default/files/publications/files/IEA%20Pursuit%20of%20Happiness%20web.pdf.

  • Campbell, S. (2013). An Analysis of Prudential Value. Utilitas, 25 (3), 334–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, M., Charlin, V., & Miller, N. (1988). Positive mood and helping behaviour: A test of six hypotheses. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55(2), 211–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carver, C. (2003). Pleasures as a sign you can attend to something else: Placing positive feelings within a general model of affect. Cognitive & Emotion, 17(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, F., Jing, Y., Hayes, A., & Lee, J. (2012). Two concepts or two approaches? A bifactor analysis of psychological and subjective well-being. Journal of Happiness Studies, 14(3), 1033–1068.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. E., Diener, E., Georgellis, Y., & Lucas, R. E. (2008). Lags and leads in life satisfaction: A test of the baseline hypothesis. Economic Journal, 118, 222–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi, M., & Csikszentmihalyi, I. (Eds.). (1992). Optimal Experience: Psychological Studies of Flow in Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deaton, A. (2010). Income, aging, health and well-being around the world: Evidence from the Gallup world poll. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Emmons, R. A., Larsen, R. J., & Griffin, S. (1985). The satisfaction with life scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49, 71–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Suh, E. (Eds.). (2000). Culture and Subjective Well-being. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Lucas, R., & Scollon, C. (2006). Beyond the hedonic treadmill: Revising the adaptation theory of well-being. American Psychologist, 61(4), 305–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E. & Biswas-Diener, R. (2008). Happiness: Unlocking the Mysteries of Psychological Wealth. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E. R., Lucas, U. Schimmack, & Helliwell, J. (2008). Well-being for Public Policy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. (1974). Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence. Nations and households in economic growth, 89, 89–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. (2001). Income and happiness: Towards a unified theory. The Economic Journal, 111(473), 465–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R., McVey, L., Switek, M., Sawangfa, O., & Zweig, J. (2010). The happiness–income paradox revisited. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(52), 22463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G., (2013). A Fresh Start for the Objective-List Theory of Well-Being. Utilitas, 25(2), 206–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. 2001. Luxury fever: Why money fails to satisfy in an era of excess. New York City: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L., & Losada, M. F. (2005). Positive affect and the complex dynamics of human flourishing. American Psychologist, 60, 678–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. (2006). Unpacking positive emotions: Investigating the seeds of human flourishing. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 1(2), 57–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, J. (2010). The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. (1986). Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. (2007). What do happiness studies study? Journal of Happiness Studies, 8, 139–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J., Mauss, I., & Tamir, M. (2011). A dark side of happiness? How, when, and why happiness is not always good. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6(3), 222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. (2012). Why satisfy preferences? Papers on economics and evolution. Available at http://ideas.repec.org/s/esi/evopap.html.

  • Hawkins, J. (2008). Well-Being, Autonomy, and the Horizon Problem. Utilitas, 20(02), 143–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, J. (2010). A new theory of well-being. Unpublished paper presented at the annual conference of the British Society for Ethical Theory, University of Nottingham, 9 July 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. 2008. The pursuit of unhappiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. (forthcoming). The Value of Positive Emotion: Philosophical Doubts and Reassurances. In J. Gruber, & J. Mosokowitz (Eds.), The Dark and Light Sides of Positive Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heady, B., & Wearing, A. (1989). Personality, life events and subjective well-being. Towards a dynamic equilibrium model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 22, 327–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heady, B., Muffels, R., & Wagner, G. (2012). Choices which change life satisfaction: Similar results for Australia. Britain and Germany. Social Indicators Research, 112(3), 725–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. (2009). Emotions and motivation: Reconsidering Neo-Jamesian accounts. In P. Goldie (Ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huppert, F., & So, T. (2013). Flourishing across Europe: Application of a new conceptual framework for defining well-being. Social Indicators Research, 110(3), 837–861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inglehart, R., Foa, R., Peterson, C., & Welzel, C. (2008). Development, freedom, and rising happiness: A global perspective (1981–2007). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(4), 264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johns, H., P. Ormerod, and Institute of Economic Affairs. (2007). Happiness, economics and public policy. (Vol. 62). London: Institute of Economic Affairs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jugureanu, A., & Hughes, J. (2010). Lay Theories and the Cultural Contingency of Happiness. ESA Research Network Sociology of Culture Midterm Conference: Culture & the Making of Worlds.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, Shelly. (1992). The limits of well-being. Social Philosophy and Policy, 9(2), 169–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Krueger A., Schkade, D., Schwartz, N., & Stone, A. (2004) Toward National Well-Being Accounts. American Economic Review May, 429–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (1999). Objective happiness. In D. Kahneman, E. Diener & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Well-Being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, (pp. 3–25). New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking Fast and Slow. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kashdan, T., Biswas-Diener, R., & King, L. (2008). Reconsidering happiness: The costs of distinguishing between hedonics and eudaimonia. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 3(4), 219–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C., Shmotkin, D., & Ryff, C. (2002). Optimizing well-being: The empirical encounter of two traditions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82(6), 1007–1022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. (2002). The mental health continuum: From languishing to flourishing in life. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 43, 207–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2011). Happiness: Lessons from a new science. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, M., Hofmann, W., Eid, M., & Lucas, R. (2012). Subjective well-being and adaptation to life events: A meta-analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102(3), 592–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lykken, D. (1999). Happiness: What studies on twins show us about nature, nurture and the happiness set-point. New York: Golden Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyubomirsky, S., King, L., & Diener, E. (2005). The benefits of frequent positive affect: Does happiness lead to success? Psychological Bulletin, 131(6), 803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, E. (2000). What’s the use of utility? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29(2), 113–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 2000. Women and human development: The capabilities approach. (Vol. 3). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oguz, S., Merad, S., & Snape, D. (2013). Measuring national well-being—what matters most to personal well-being? http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons/rel/wellbeing/measuring-national-well-being/what-matters-most-to-personal-well-being-in-the-uk-/index.html.

  • Oishi, S., Diener, E., & Lucas, R. (2007). The optimum level of well-being: Can people be too happy? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 2(4), 346–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oswald, A. (2006). The Hippies were right all along about happiness. Financial Times, 19 Jan 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (2004). The science of self-control. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raibley, J. (2012). Happiness is not well-being. Journal of Happiness Studies, 13(6), 1105–1129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (2008). The problem of well-being: respect, equality and the self. Tenth Conference of the International Society for Utilitarian Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (2004). The role of well-being. Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 269–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. (1996). Internalism and good for a person. Ethics, 106(2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R., & Deci, E. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52(1), 141–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations in the meaning of psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57(6), 1069–1081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, D., Stevenson, B., & Wolfers, J. (2012). The new stylized facts about income and subjective well-being. Emotion, 12(6), 1181–1187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, T. (2001). Pleasure, displeasure and representation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31(4), 507–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1999. Development as freedom. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinhababu, N. (Manuscript) The Epistemic Argument for Hedonism. Available at http://philpapers.org/archive/SINTEA-3.pdf.

  • Stevenson, B., & Wolfers., J. (2008). Economic growth and subjective well-being: Reassessing the Easterlin Paradox. National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No. 14282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J., Sen, A., & Fitoussi, J-P. (2009). Mis-measuring our lives: Why GDP doesn’t add up. Report by the Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2007). Substance and procedure in theories of prudential value. Australian Journal of Philosophy, 85(3), 373–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. 2008. The reflective life: Living wisely within our limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turton, D. (2009). The real dirt on happiness studies. Real-World Economics Review, 49, 83–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R., & Hagerty, M. (2006). Rising happiness in nations 1946–2004: A reply to Easterlin. Social Indicators Research, 79(3), 421–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T., & Gilbert, D. (2008). Explaining away: A model of affective adaptation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 370–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodard, C. (2013). Classifying theories of welfare. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 787–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wren-Lewis, S. (2013). Well-being as a Primary Good: Towards a Legitimate Role for Well-being in Public Policy. Philosophy and Public Policy Quarterly, 31(2).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sam Wren-Lewis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wren-Lewis, S. (2015). Towards a Widely Acceptable Framework for the Study of Personal Well-Being. In: Søraker, J., Van der Rijt, JW., de Boer, J., Wong, PH., Brey, P. (eds) Well-Being in Contemporary Society. Happiness Studies Book Series. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06459-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics