Skip to main content

The Political Pursuit of Happiness: A Popperian Perspective on Layard’s Happiness Policy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1743 Accesses

Part of the book series: Happiness Studies Book Series ((HAPS))

Abstract

For Richard Layard, happiness should constitute the guiding principle of public policy. However, it remains unclear whether there is a convincing justification for such kinds of happiness policies. To shed some light on this issue, Layard’s battle against status competition for enhancing happiness is evaluated by applying a Popperian perspective. That is, we apply Popper’s evaluation scheme by determining whether Layard’s position meets four criteria derived from Karl Popper’s philosophy. At the normative level, status competition cannot be considered only a social vice, but also a social virtue. At the epistemological level, Layard’s policy advice seems problematic, as it is based on the assumption that the government is able to differentiate between positive and negative incentives arising from status competition. Regarding the political level, Layard argues that counteracting the effects of the status race is a major objective of public policy. Layard is optimistic that the issue of consensus among citizens can be solved, but it remains unclear whether this optimism is justified. He is also confident that the problems of implementation can be overcome. However, there may be a general incompatibility between the level of coercion and status competition, since the latter is deeply rooted in human nature. To sum up, there is neither a convincing argument for stricter measures to combat status competition, nor does political enforcement seem feasible with voters who presumably suffer from ‘false’ preferences. Moreover, there is no clear-cut normative argument to combat status competition from a Popperian perspective. As a more general result, a reorientation of public policy towards happiness, as recommended by Layard, does not seem advisable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an overview of Gross National Happiness in Bhutan, see Burns (2010) and Shrotryia (2006); that not all is well “in the land of the happy” is emphasized by Duncan (2007, 97).

  2. 2.

    In Bünger and Prinz (2010), Popper’s and Layard’s position with respect to smoking is investigated. Since, in that context, Karl Popper’s and Richard Layard’s general approaches to happiness and public policy were described and analyzed comparatively to a certain extent, we restrict ourselves in this paper to remarks on their respective general positions.

  3. 3.

    Similar approaches are developed by Kahneman and Krueger (2006) and Lelkes (2013). Kahneman and Krueger (2006) propose a U-index which contains the time spent in unpleasant states. While their primary reason for focusing on negative aspects seems to be some desirable psychological and statistical properties (Kahneman and Krueger 2006, 19 ff.), they also note political acceptability as an advantage of misery or unhappiness indicators (Kahneman and Krueger 2006, 22). Lelkes (2013, 17) shows that misery as measured by ratings from 0 to 3 on a ten-step life satisfaction/happiness scale, can be better predicted by observable personal characteristics than by happiness.

  4. 4.

    This corresponds to Sidgwick’s “hedonistic zero” (Mayerfeld 1999, 15 and 60), even though we do not wish to restrict Popper to a purely hedonistic interpretation.

  5. 5.

    The position of the zero-line depends on the situation of the society. This is even the case where physiological basic needs are concerned; the same amount of food may feel like starvation in New Zealand and the USA, while seen as abundance in Post-WWII Austria and India (Popper 2012, 119).

  6. 6.

    It seems reasonable to assume that some modes of coercion respect private autonomy, while others do not.

  7. 7.

    Consumption that is relevant to status can take place in various forms, such as owning real estate, driving luxury cars, and also through possessing the “right” cell phones, watches, TV sets, etc.

  8. 8.

    Or maybe even negative savings, i.e., personal debt.

  9. 9.

    Interested voting means that people vote on political proposals according their own preferences. Because people know that it is very unlikely that their own vote will be decisive, there is almost no incentive to vote with respect to outcomes (Shughart 2004); this is called the ‘paradox of voting’. However, moral or ideological motivations may nevertheless induce many if not most people to vote, maybe because they know that they are voting behind the ‘veil of insignificance’ (Kliemt 1986; see also Aidt 2000); this is termed expressive voting (Shughart 2004; Sobel and Wagner 2004).

  10. 10.

    We thank an anonymous referee for asking about these conditions.

  11. 11.

    There may be exceptions where a workaholic neglects his family, but this would not appear to be relevant for public policy (except, perhaps, for blatant cases of neglecting one's children or physical abuse).

  12. 12.

    The other side of the coin is that under this interpersonal aggregation rule, it could be a moral obligation to actively sacrifice the lives of some innocent individuals to increase the total happiness in society as a whole.

  13. 13.

    “Toleration is the necessary consequence of realizing our human fallibility: to err is human, and we do it all the time. So let us pardon each other’s follies. This is the first principle of natural right” (Popper, translating an argument of Voltaire in favor of ‘toleration’ (or tolerance); Popper 1994, p. 190, emphasis in the original text). See also Harsanyi (1997, 134).

  14. 14.

    Of course, there might also be reference groups which are not deliberately chosen, but more coincidental (like one’s family) or where access to the groups is free.

  15. 15.

    Individuals can simultaneously have myopic tendencies in some domains of life and hyperopic characteristics in others. For a more detailed discussion of hyperopia and myopia in the context of public finance, see Fennell (2006).

  16. 16.

    For instance, Bünger (2010) did not find empirical evidence in Europe of patterns of time use that would harm relationships.

  17. 17.

    This procedure, of course, requires individuals to be aware of the comparison processes they apply.

  18. 18.

    Depending on how the gains from the status race are distributed among the population, up to half of the electorate would vote against the proposal. If one assumes that those who benefit from status are more likely to vote, their impact in the election could even be higher.

  19. 19.

    In this respect, he is neither the first nor the only author to suggest such methods. See, for instance, Miller (1975), Konrad (1990), Corneo (2002), Jaeger (2004) and Griffith (2005).

  20. 20.

    Layard advocates a second welfare economics arguments in favor of these measures. Because of the decreasing marginal utility of income, redistribution from the ‘rich’ to the ‘poor’ should lead to an increase in total or average welfare in a society, even if only individual evaluations are taken into account and the welfare losses (caused by the disincentives of progressive taxation) are considered (Layard 2009, 102). This is of course the standard argument of classical utilitarianism in favor of progressive taxation.

  21. 21.

    It might be more appropriate to call this approach ‘pedagogical’.

  22. 22.

    A similar caveat is given by Layard (2006, C27).

  23. 23.

    The level of coercion considered acceptable depends on different dimensions like the maturity of the recipients and their autonomy: Some educational measures which are mostly deemed acceptable when considering educating children are assessed as unacceptable when directed towards adults.

References

  • Aidt, T. S. (2000). Economic voting and information. Electoral Studies, 19, 349–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, D. J. & Laibson, D. I. (2003). Good policies for bad governments: behavioral political economy. Draft paper May 27, 2003. http://199.169.205.158/economic/conf/conf48/papers/benjamin_laibson.pdf. Accessed 25 Sep 2013.

  • Bok, D. (2010). The politics of happiness—what governments can learn from the new research on well-being. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L., & Porta, P. L. (Eds.). (2007). Handbook on the economics of happiness. Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bünger, B. (2010). The demand for relational goods: Empirical evidence from the European Social Survey. International Review of Economics, 57, 177–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bünger, B., & Prinz, A. (2010). Staatliche Glücksförderung? Karl Popper, Richard Layard und das Rauchen. Ordo. Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 61, 169–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, G. W. (2010). Gross national happiness—a gift from Bhutan to the world. In R. Biswas-Diener (Ed.), Positive psychology as social change (pp. 73–87). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C., Issacharoff, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donohue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Regulation for conservatives: Behavioral economics and the case for “asymmetric paternalism”. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151, 101–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (1989). Efficient status seeking: Externalities, and the evolution of status games. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 11, 175–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corneo, G. (2002). The efficient side of progressive income taxation.European Economic Review, 46, 1359-1368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. A., Anna, A. L. D., Lau, D. M., & Stokes, M. A. (2009). Encouraging governments to enhance the happiness of their nation: Step 1: Understand subjective wellbeing. Social Indicators Research, 91, 23–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Prycker, V. (2010). Happiness on the political agenda? Pros and cons. Journal of Happiness Studies, 11, 585–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, G. (2005). What do we mean by “happiness”? The relevance of subjective wellbeing to social policy. Social Policy Journal of New Zealand, 25, 16–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, G. (2007). After happiness. Journal of Political Ideologies, 12, 85–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, G. (2010). Should happiness-maximization be the goal of government? Journal of Happiness Studies, 11, 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. (2002). Happiness in economics. Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fennell, L. A. (2006). Hyperopia in public finance. In E. L. McCaffery & J. Slemrod (Eds.), Behavioral public finance (pp. 141–171). New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H. (1985). Choosing the right pond. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H. (2005). Positional externalities cause large and preventable welfare losses. The American Economic Review, 95, 137–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H. (2008). Should public policy respond to positional externalities? Journal of Public Economics, 92, 1777–1786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, S. (2012). Original position. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/original-position/. Accessed 28 Sept 2013.

  • Frey, B. S. (2010). Happiness. A revolution in economics. Cambridge, Massachusetts; London, England: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., & Stutzer, A. (2000). Maximizing happiness? German Economic Review, 1, 145–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., & Stutzer, A. (2009). Should national happiness be maximized? In A. K. Dutt & B. Radcliff (Eds.), Happiness, economics and politics—towards a multi-disciplinary approach (pp. 301–323). Cheltenham, Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffith, T.D. (2005). Progressive taxation and happiness.Boston College Law Review,45,1-36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. (1997). Utilities, preferences, and substantive goods. Social Choice and Welfare, 14, 129–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, W. K. (2004). Status seeking and social welfare: Is there virtue in vanity? Social Science Quarterly,85,361-379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerome, J. K. (1994 [1889]). Three man in a boat (to say nothing of the dog). London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Krueger, A. B. (2006). Developments in the measurement of subjective well-being. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 20, 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Krueger, A. B., Schkade, D., Schwarz, N., & Stone, A. (2004). Toward national well-being accounts. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 94, 429–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (1986). The veil of insignificance. European Journal of Political Economy, 2(3), 333–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K. (1990). Statuspräferenzen: soziobiologische Ursachen, Statuswettrüsten und seine Besteuerung. Kyklos, 43, 249–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (1980). Human satisfaction and public policy. Economic Journal, 90, 737–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2005). Happiness—lessons from a new science. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2006). Happiness and public policy: A challenge to the profession. The Economic Journal, 116, C24–C33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2009). The greatest happiness principle: It’s time has come. In S. Griffiths & R. Reeves (Eds.), Well-being. How to lead the good life and what government should do to help (pp. 92–106). London: The Social Market Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lelkes, O. (2013). Minimising misery: A new strategy for public policies instead of maximising happiness? MPRA paper no. 45435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Haisley, E. C. (2007). The economist as therapist: Methodological ramifications of ‘light’ paternalism. http://ssrn.com/abstract=962472. Accessed 18 March 2010.

  • Mayerfeld, J. (1999). Suffering and moral responsibility. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, E. (1975). Status goods and luxury taxes.American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 34, 141-154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ng, Y.-K., & Ho, L. S. (2006). Happiness and public policy—theory, case studies and implications. Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ott, J. (2006). Call for policy shift to happiness: Review of Richard Layard’s “Happiness; Lessons from a new science”. Journal of Happiness Studies, 7, 118–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ott, J. (2010). Greater happiness for a greater number: Some non-controversial options for governments. Journal of Happiness Studies, 11, 631–647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1966). The Open Society and its enemies I: The spell of Plato (5th ed., revised), Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1969). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge (3rd ed., revised), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1974). The Open Society and its enemies II: The high tide of prophecy: Hegel, Marx, and the aftermath. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1994). Toleration and intellectual responsibility (Stolen from Xenophanes and from Voltaire). In In search of a better world. Lectures and essays from thirty years (K. R. Popper, Ed., L. J. Bennett, Trans., pp. 188–203). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2012). Public and private values. In J. Shearmur & P. N. Turner (Eds.), Karl Popper: After the Open Society: Selected social and political writings (pp. 118–131). London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, A. (2013). Should the state care for the happiness of its citizens? In H. Brockmann & J. Delhey (Eds.), Human happiness and the pursuit of maximization . (pp. 177–190). doi:10.1007/978-94-007-6609-9_13. Springer: Dordrecht.

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrotryia, V. K. (2006). Happiness and development—Public policy initiatives in the Kingdom of Bhutan. In Y.-K. Ng & L. S. Ho (Eds.), Happiness and public policy—theory, case studies and implications (pp. 193–208). Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shughart, W. F, I. I. (2004). Is voting rational? In C. K. Rowley & F. Schneider (Eds.), The encyclopedia of public choice (Vol. II, pp. 326–329). Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kulwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, R. S., & Wagner, G. A. (2004). Expressive voting and redistribution. In C. K. Rowley & F. Schneider (Eds.), The encyclopedia of public choice (Vol. II, pp. 245–247). Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kulwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1989). Maximizing Social Welfare: Is it the government’s business? In A. Hamlin & P. Pettit (Eds.), The good polity—normative analysis of the state (pp. 69–86). Oxford, New York: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2004). The opportunity criterion: Consumer sovereignty without the assumption of coherent preferences. American Economic Review, 94, 1014–1033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2008). Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 226–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 93, 175–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge—improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven, London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Praag, B. M. S., & Ferrer-i-Carbonell, A. (2008). Happiness quantified—a satisfaction calculus approach (revised ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors thank Johnny Søraker for his most instructive and concise comments on this paper. A previous version of this paper was presented at the Meeting of the European Public Choice Society 2011 in Rennes and at the conference ‘Well-Being in Contemporary Society’ (wics 2012), University of Twente, 2012. The authors also wish to thank the participants at their respective conference sessions and especially Martin Rode and two anonymous referees. The authors are additionally grateful to Brian Bloch for his comprehensive editing of the manuscript. The usual disclaimer applies with regard to the content.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aloys Prinz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Prinz, A., Bünger, B. (2015). The Political Pursuit of Happiness: A Popperian Perspective on Layard’s Happiness Policy. In: Søraker, J., Van der Rijt, JW., de Boer, J., Wong, PH., Brey, P. (eds) Well-Being in Contemporary Society. Happiness Studies Book Series. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06459-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics