Skip to main content

Collective Responsibility and Group-Control

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 372))

Abstract

Collectives are more or less structured groups of human beings. Responsibility-collectivism is the view that the moral responsibility of at least some such collectives is something over and above the combined moral responsibility of individual group members. This paper focuses on one of the key conditions of responsibility: the requirement of control. It is plausible that this requirement also applies to collective agents and so collective responsibility presupposes group-control. Responsibility-collectivists have often tried to unpack the idea of group-control as non-causal control. I argue that non-causal control is not an admissible basis for attributing responsibility. Only causal group-control is. This is because non-causal group control does not provide the right kind of information regarding the ancestry of a certain outcome. In the second half of the paper, I discuss the difficulties which arise for responsibility-collectivism if one understands group-control as causal group-control. One of these difficulties is whether causal group-control is consistent with ontological individualism. The second concerns the relationship of group-control and individual control. I argue that the first difficulty is manageable, but only at the price of having to accept a solution to the second difficulty which runs counter to the original aim of the responsibility-collectivist of characterizing irreducible collective responsibility as compatible with individual responsibility. Worse still, responsibility-collectivists may have to choose sides in other areas of social ontology as well. This further raises the price of this position.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The version of responsibility-collectivism I will focus on holds that it is the same kind of moral responsibility we attribute to collectives as to individuals. That is, roughly, retrospective desert-based responsibility implying blameworthiness and praiseworthiness and justifying certain normative responses such as punishment and Strawsonian reactive attitudes such as resentment and guilt. Pettit (2007a) and Shockley (2007) explicitly accept this condition.

  2. 2.

    One feasible strategy available to the responsibility-individualist is to accept the first claim, but reject the second. Perhaps we just have to resign ourselves to the fact that collectively brought about harms can also sometimes be of a kind for which nobody is responsible, comparable to harms inflicted by nature, even though they are in some sense “man-made” (see Szigeti 2014).

  3. 3.

    Responsibility for what, i.e., actions or outcomes of actions? When necessary to specify, I will focus on responsibility for outcomes for simplicity’s sake. Elsewhere I will follow Pettit (2007a) who does not distinguish between responsibility for actions and responsibility for outcomes. The distinction may be relevant to the requirement of control insofar as the necessity of causal control is widely held for outcome-responsibility (actions causing outcomes). By contrast, some libertarians (simple indeterminists) do not accept that agents need to cause the actions for which they are responsible (see Goetz 1988).

  4. 4.

    Naturally, one can also argue against the collectivist position using the dependence of responsibility on agency as one’s point of departure. If no groups of human beings can be agents and moral responsibility presupposes agency, then individualism about responsibility would follow (for such responsibility-individualist arguments, see Miller and Mäkelä 2005; Haji 2006; McKenna 2006). Shockley (2007) denies that collective moral responsibility presupposes collective agency, but accepts the control-requirement.

  5. 5.

    In this chapter, the unadorned term “collectivist” or “collectivism” is always to be read as short for responsibility-collectivism or responsibility-collectivist as I defined the position in the first paragraph.

  6. 6.

    I say “at the very minimum” in order to accommodate the semi-compatibilist argument that control as defined above is all that is required in terms of control for the agent to be morally responsible, whereas regulative control associated with the ability to do otherwise is not (see Fischer and Ravizza 1998). Note that both kinds of control are described by semi-compatibilists as causal.

  7. 7.

    I will define causal control in Sect. 6.5 below.

  8. 8.

    More precisely, the physical realizations (which are property-instantiations) of the individual actions. I ignore that complication here.

  9. 9.

    In addition, the responsibility-collectivist also needs to show that group-control is not just control by some other individual or aggregate of individuals. This task involves, among others, showing that when the group is in control the relevant individual actions implement some autonomous group attitude held by the group qua group. I will not discuss the difficulties associated with this issue in this paper (but see Szigeti (2014) and footnote 18 below).

  10. 10.

    Having said that, it should be noted that, despite their insistence that “programming” is a strictly non-causal process, the language used by advocates of this theory is worryingly causal at times. They talk about the program or arrangement as “ensuring” or “making it probable” (Jackson and Pettit 1990, 114) that basic, causally efficacious factors will bring about the pertaining effect (for the same causal language, see also Jackson and Pettit 1992a, b).

  11. 11.

    In the following, I will mostly talk about higher-order/lower-order properties, not events. It will be assumed that the problem and possible solutions would be about the same for higher-order/lower-order events as well.

  12. 12.

    A possible alternative is to deny (i). See Woodward 2008; Menzies 2008; List and Menzies 2010; Shapiro 2012. More on this alternative in Sect. 6.6.

  13. 13.

    Furthermore, the collectivist argues that there are good reasons why the group should exercise such control over its members. Group-control may be required to ensure both the diachronic and synchronic rationality of collective behaviour (List and Pettit 2002, 2011; Pettit 2003, 2007b; List 2006). Of course, collectivists also acknowledge that groups can also fail to perform their functions or can even fall apart completely.

  14. 14.

    Note that collectivists themselves write that in the case of the cracking flask, for example, the higher-order property of boiling is an “abstract statistic” (Jackson and Pettit 1992b, 117; the term used in the same context in Jackson and Pettit 1990, 110 is “aggregate statistic”).

  15. 15.

    Some responsibility-collectivists also emphasize the importance of other, less formal ways of adopting a “program” such as via a shared culture or common norms or goals or feelings of solidarity (May 1991; Shockley 2007).

  16. 16.

    In general, the collectivist is to avoid circularity. It cannot be argued that what distinguishes a collective profile as in the above example from genuine group-control is that group-control is exercised by the collective as an agent (pace Pettit 2007b). Collectivists themselves accept that for a collective to qualify as an agent it already has to possess group-control.

  17. 17.

    It is worth noting as well that the “program” does not even make a counterfactual contribution in the sense of making sure that a Frankfurtian back-up plan would be executed. It is not the case that should this individual fail to comply, the program would ensure that the program is nevertheless implemented by making someone else do it. So if individual agent I1 fails to perform her task and some other individual agent I2 steps in and performs the action instead, then that will be once again I2’s choice given that program is causally inefficacious.

  18. 18.

    Including the condition, extensively discussed by responsibility-collectivists (see esp. List and Pettit 2011), that the group has to be able to hold autonomous judgments which can come apart from judgments of individual members. I have argued elsewhere (Szigeti 2014) that it does not follow from the possibility of group judgments being autonomous in this sense that the group qua group is responsible for them. This because either some individual or nobody is responsible for these collective judgments. By contrast, my point here is that even if group judgments can be autonomous in this sense, this does not mean that the group controls individual actions when individuals implement those judgments.

  19. 19.

    As noted earlier, simple indeterminist libertarians question the requirement of causal control for the agent-action as opposed to the action-outcome relationship. However, it seems that they too would accept the requirement of causal control for the action-outcome relationship.

  20. 20.

    Admittedly, Sartorio denies that moral responsibility entails causal responsibility. I am not sure whether she would also deny the requirement of causal control as defined above.

  21. 21.

    Which is not surprising since, as noted above, the “programming account” is a general proposal for distinguishing the causal relevance of higher-level properties from the causal efficacy of lower-level ones.

  22. 22.

    Note that libertarian agent causationists have argued that attributing causal efficacy to certain emergent properties does not even require repudiating the conception of causation as generation or production (see esp. O’Connor 1994, 1995).

  23. 23.

    Note that in terms of this definition the causal relata for Lewis are events, whereas in the rest of the paper I talk about properties, or better property-instantiations, as causal relata. I believe we can ignore this difference for the purposes of this paper.

  24. 24.

    Whereby C and E are propositions referring to the occurrence of the corresponding events or the instantiations of properties.

  25. 25.

    Whereby the truth of counterfactuals is interpreted, as is standard practice, in terms of a similarity relation between possible worlds.

  26. 26.

    Many have argued that the exclusion principle should not be treated as an a priori claim (see esp. List and Menzies 2009), and that whether exclusion holds or not is to be determined by empirical characteristics of the relevant systems.

  27. 27.

    But not because they overdetermine the effect. Overdetermination presupposes fully independent property instantiations or events as causes. The underlying rationale of the “non-competition scenario”, as we will see shortly, is that supervenient properties are not wholly distinct from their realizers.

  28. 28.

    Whereby PH and EH are propositions referring to the instantiations of higher-level properties, while PL and EL are propositions referring to the instantiations of lower-level properties.

  29. 29.

    Diverging from this approach, Woodward (2008) and Shapiro and Sober (2012) argue that even in cases of multiple realizability causal claims involving subvenient lower-level properties need not be false or even less informative.

  30. 30.

    In addition, Pettit (1996) and List and Pettit (2008) also worry that without individual control it is unlikely that the collective can display rational patterns of behaviour.

  31. 31.

    This is also admitted by those who think that multiple realizability entails downward exclusion. See, for example, List and Spiekermann (2012, 17): “[…] realization-sensitive causal relations are fully reducible to a lower level of description”.

  32. 32.

    The position Pettit and Schweikard call individualism is to be distinguished from responsibility-individualism. The latter view says that only individuals can be the addressees of ascription of responsibility. It is thus opposed to responsibility-collectivism. This section explores the relationship between individualism in Pettit’s and Schweikard’s sense and responsibility-individualism.

References

  • Braham, M., & van Hees, M. (2011). Responsibility voids. Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 6–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2006). On the agency of certain collective entities: An argument from normative autonomy. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXX, 194–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2008). Causation, and determinable properties: On the efficacy of colour, shape and size. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced. New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation (pp. 176–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. (2009). Ontological individualism reconsidered. Synthese, 166, 187–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control. A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 207–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1984). Collective and corporate responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2002). Collective wrongdoing: Moral and legal responses. Social Theory and Practice, 28, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, S. C. (1988). A noncausal theory of agency. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 49, 303–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2006). On the ultimate responsibility of collectives. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXX, 292–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Held, V. (1970). Can a random collection of individuals be morally responsible? In L. May & S. Hoffman (Eds.), Collective responsibility (pp. 89–100). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990). Program explanation: A general perspective. Analysis, 50, 107–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992a). In defense of explanatory ecumenism. Economics and Philosophy, 8, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992b). Structural explanation in social theory. In D. Charles & K. Lennon (Eds.), Reduction, explanation, and realism (pp. 97–132). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1986). Reduction, explanation, and individualism. Philosophy of Science, 53, 492–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutz, C. (2000). Complicity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, B. (2012). Individual complicity in collective wrongdoing. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16(2), 227–243. Online first.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation (Philosophical papers, Vol. II, pp. 159–171). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C. (2006). The discursive dilemma and public reason. Ethics, 116, 362–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). Non-reductive physicalism and the limits of the exclusion principle. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 475–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Menzies, P. (2010). The causal autonomy of the special sciences. In C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald (Eds.), Emergence in mind (pp. 108–128). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2002). The aggregation of sets of judgments: An impossibility result. Economics and Philosophy, 18, 89–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2008). Group agency and supervenience. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced. New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation (pp. 75–92). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Spiekermann, K. (2012). Methodological individualism and holism in political science: A reconciliation (Unpublished Working Paper). http://personal.lse.ac.uk/list/

  • May, L. (1991). Metaphysical guilt and moral taint. In M. Larry & H. Stacey (Eds.), Collective responsibility (pp. 239–254). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, L., & Hoffman, S. (Eds.). (1991). Collective responsibility. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2006). Collective responsibility and an agent meaning theory. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXX, 16–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2008). The exclusion problem, the determination relation, and contrastive causation. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced. New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation (pp. 196–218). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S., & Mäkelä, P. (2005). The collectivist approach to collective moral responsibility. Metaphilosophy, 36, 634–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, S. M. (2009). Causation and responsibility: An essay in law, morals, and metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. (1994). Emergent properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31, 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. (1995). Agent causation. In T. O’Connor (Ed.), Agents, causes, and events: Essays on indeterminism and free will (pp. 173–200). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1996 [1993]). The collective mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2003). Groups with minds of their own. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics (pp. 167–193). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2007a). Responsibility incorporated. Ethics, 117, 171–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2007b). Rationality, reasoning and group agency. Dialectica, 61, 495–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P., & Schweikard, D. (2006). Joint actions and group agents. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36, 18–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2004). How to be responsible for something without causing it. Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 315–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2012). Mental manipulations and the problem of causal exclusion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 507–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A., & Sober, E. (2012). Against proportionality. Analysis, 72, 89–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shockley, K. (2007). Programming collective control. Journal of Social Philosophy, 38, 442–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szigeti, A. (2014). Are individualist accounts of collective responsibility morally deficient? In A. Konzelmann-Ziv & H. B. Schmid (Eds.), Institutions, emotions, and group agents. Contributions to social ontology (pp. 329–342). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2007). Causation with a human face. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality (pp. 66–105). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2008). Mental causation and neural mechanisms. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced. New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation (pp. 218–262). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2012). Micro, macro, and mechanisms. In H. Kincaid (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of social science (pp. 21–45). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2003). The individualism-holism debate on intertheoretic reduction and the argument from multiple realization. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 33, 77–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2007). Holism and supervenience. In S. P. Turner & M. W. Risjord (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science (pp. 311–341). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to András Szigeti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Szigeti, A. (2014). Collective Responsibility and Group-Control. In: Zahle, J., Collin, F. (eds) Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. Synthese Library, vol 372. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05344-8_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics