Skip to main content

Holism, Emergence, and the Crucial Distinction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 372))

Abstract

One issue of dispute between methodological individualists and methodological holists is whether holist explanations are dispensable in the sense that individualist explanations are able to do their explanatory job. Methodological individualists say they are, whereas methodological holists deny this. In the first part of the paper, I discuss Elder-Vass’ version of an influential argument in support of methodological holism, the argument from emergence. I argue that methodological individualists should reject it: The argument relies on a distinction between individualist and holist explanations that they find unacceptable and Elder-Vass’ reasons in support of his way of drawing this distinction are not good ones. In the second part, I examine what, if anything, would be good reasons in support of a particular way of differentiating between individualist and holist explanations. I propose that a good reason is one which shows, in an acceptable manner, that the distinction, drawn in the same way in all contexts, is useful from the perspective of offering explanations of the social world. I show that if this criterion is adopted, it will result in a fruitful reorientation of the debate between methodological individualists and methodological holists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, e.g., Archer (1995, 2000), Bhaskar (1982, 2000[1979]), Collier (1989, 1994), Elder-Vass (2007, 2010, 2012), Lawson (1997), and Sayer (2010) for critical realist discussions of the argument from emergence. It should be stressed that, very often, critical realists do not themselves present their arguments of emergence as arguments in favor of methodological holism. This is because they use the term in a different sense than I do. In view of the definition stated above, their arguments are straightforward arguments in support of methodological holism.

  2. 2.

    For the sake of simplicity, I shall often talk about those properties which parts may have in isolation. Thus, I shall leave out the second part “or as an element in an unstructured collection of parts.”

  3. 3.

    This understanding of emergent properties is one among many. For different understandings of the notion of emergence, see, e.g. Beckermann et al. (1992), Bedau and Humphreys (2008), Bunge (2003), Corradini and O’Connor (2010), Kim (1999), and O’Connor and Wong (2012). For an overview of the appeal to emergence within sociology, see Sawyer (2005).

  4. 4.

    At one point, Elder-Vass notes that social entities may also have material things as their parts (ibid.: 157). Still, he does not make much of this insight and hence I shall also ignore this possible way of spelling out parts of social entities.

  5. 5.

    In his (2010), Elder-Vass provides a nice and detailed analysis of organizations as well as norm circles, which are another kind of social entities. He extends this analysis to further kinds of social entities in his (2012).

  6. 6.

    Note that as soon as individuals are regarded not as parts but as wholes, their non-emergent properties may instead qualify as emergent ones, that is, properties which are the result, synchronically speaking, of individuals being themselves composed of parts standing in certain relations to each other. Unless otherwise noted, I have in mind individuals’ non-emergent properties as parts when talking about these properties.

  7. 7.

    Elder-Vass works with two different notions of explanation: Explanations in the above causal sense and what may be called reductive explanations. I shall not be concerned with reductive explanations and hence I use “explanation” to refer to his causal notion of explanation only. On reductive explanations, see, e.g., Elder-Vass (2010: 24).

  8. 8.

    Perhaps there are a few exceptions this trend. However, for ease of exposition and simplicity, I shall ignore these exceptions in the following. I take current methodological individualism to cover defenses of the position going back to the 1950s at least.

  9. 9.

    For the record, King does not regard his own position as methodological individualist (see his (2007)). Still, this is irrelevant in the present context: What matters is that Sawyer takes the position to be a clear cut example of methodological individualism.

  10. 10.

    This is for instance made clear by Steven Lukes in his classic paper “Methodological Individualism Reconsidered” (Lukes 1995[1968]). Here, Lukes refers to explanations containing descriptions of individuals as voting, hiring, etc. as explanations which contain type (iv) predicates while noticing that the use of these explanations is “extremely widespread” among methodological individualists (ibid.: 455). In the paper, Lukes opposes the use of these predicates by methodological individualists. In another famous paper, Mandelbaum did the same (1973[1955]). Particularly, the latter paper sparkled a lot of debate on this issue. See, e.g., Bhargava (1992), Danto (1973[1962]), Gellner (1968), Goldstein (1973[1958], 1959), James (2009[1984]), Lesnoff (1974), Little (1991), Kincaid (1994, 1997), Martin (1972), Quinton (1975), and Zahle (2003, 2007).

  11. 11.

    Notice that it really matters to current methodological individualists whether these explanations are classified as individualist ones: It is only if they are regarded as individualist explanations that current methodological individualists maintain that it is possible to defend their position that all holist explanations are dispensable.

  12. 12.

    This sort of response, i.e. the dismissal of arguments on the grounds that the specification of individualist and holist explanations is unacceptable, is not uncommon in the debate, see, e.g., Mäki (2002) and Watkins (1973c[1955]).

  13. 13.

    Very informative discussions of levels talk may be found in, e.g., Craver (2007), Kim (2002) and Wimsatt (1994).

  14. 14.

    Thanks to Elder-Vass (personal communication) for pointing me to this reading of his view.

  15. 15.

    This point is also made by Kim in relation to distinctions into levels (Kim 2002).

  16. 16.

    Ylikoski, too, notices in relation to individualist explanations that it is assumed that they should be specified in the same manner in all relevant contexts (Ylikoski 2012: 26). He opposes this presupposition from a different perspective than I do below.

  17. 17.

    I would like to thank Dave Elder-Vass as well as Jeroen van Bouwel, Finn Collin, Tuukka Kaidesoja, Klemens Kappel, Andras Szigeti, and Petri Ylikoski for their very helpful comments. Also, I have given versions of this paper as a talk at the workshop Individualism, Holism, Emergence and Explanations, at University of Copenhagen in 2012, and at the Philosophy of Science (POS) Seminar, Finnish Centre of Excellence in the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, at University of Helsinki in 2013. In both cases, I have benefitted greatly from the questions and remarks made by the audiences. Work on this essay was supported by The Danish Council for Independent Research | Humanities (FKK).

References

  • Archer, M. S. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (2000). For structure: Its reality, properties, and powers: A reply to Anthony King. The Sociological Review, 48, 464–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckermann, A., Flohr, H., & Kim, J. (Eds.). (1992). Emergence or reduction? Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. A., & Humphreys, P. (Eds.). (2008). Emergence. Contemporary readings in philosophy and science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of psychology. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhargava, R. (1992). Individualism in social science. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1982). Emergence, explanation, and emancipation. In P. F. Secord (Ed.), Explaining human behavior (pp. 275–310). Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2000[1979]). The possibility of naturalism (3rd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Emergence and convergence. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, A. (1989). Scientific realism and socialist thought. Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, A. (1994). Critical realism. An introduction to Roy Bhaskar’s philosophy. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corradini, A., & O’Connor, T. (Eds.). (2010). Emergence in science and philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Danto, A. C. (1973[1962]). Methodological individualism and methodological socialism. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 312–338). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2007). For emergence: Refining Archer’s account of social structure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(1), 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The causal power of social structures. Emergence, structure and agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2012). The reality of social construction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gellner, E. (1968). Holism versus individualism. In M. Brodbeck (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of the social sciences (pp. 254–268). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. J. (1959). Mr. Watkins on the two theses. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 10(39), 240–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. J. (1973[1958]). Two theses of methodological individualism. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 277–286). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2007). Meanings of methodological individualism. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(2), 211–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, S. J. (2009[1984]). The content of social explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95, 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2002). The layered model: Metaphysical considerations. Philosophical Explorations, V(1), 2–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1994). Reduction, explanation and individualism. In M. Martin & L. C. McIntyre (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of social science (pp. 497–513). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1997). Individualism and the unity of science. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, A. (1999). The impossibility of naturalism: The antinomies of Bhaskar's realism. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 29, 267–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, A. (2007). Why I am not an individualist. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(2), 211–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lesnoff, M. H. (1974). The structure of social science: A philosophical introduction. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1991). Varieties of social explanation. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukes, S. (1995[1968]). Methodological individualism reconsidered. In M. Martin & L. C. McIntyre (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of social science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2002). Explanatory ecumenism and economics imperialism. Economics and Philosophy, 18, 235–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, M. (1973[1955]). Societal facts. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 221–234). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1972). Explanation in social science: Some recent work. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 2(1), 61–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Y., & Wong, H. Y. (2012). Emergent properties. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/properties-emergent/

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science II (pp. 3–36). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinton, A. (1975). Social objects. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 75, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2005). Social emergence. Societies as complex systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, A. (2010). Method in social science. A realist approach. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2002). The changing face of methodological individualism. Annual Review of Sociology, 28, 479–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1973a[1952]). Ideal types and historical explanation. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 143–165). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1973b[1957]). Historical explanation in the social sciences. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 166–178). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1973c[1955]). Methodological individualism: A reply. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 179–184). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 20(Suppl.), 207–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2012). Micro, macro, and mechanisms. In H. Kincaid (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of social science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2003). The individualism-holism debate on intertheoretic reduction and the argument from multiple realization. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 33(1), 77–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2007). Holism and supervenience. In S. P. Turner & M. Risjord (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science. Philosophy of anthropology and sociology (pp. 311–341). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Julie Zahle .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zahle, J. (2014). Holism, Emergence, and the Crucial Distinction. In: Zahle, J., Collin, F. (eds) Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. Synthese Library, vol 372. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05344-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics