Skip to main content

Unsharp Humean Chances in Statistical Physics: A Reply to Beisbart

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover New Directions in the Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective ((PSEP,volume 5))

Abstract

In an illuminating paper, Beisbart (Beisbart C, Good just isn’t good enough – Humean chances and Boltzmannian statistical physics. In: Galavotti MC, Dieks D (eds) New directions in the philosophy of science. Springer, Dordrecht, 2014) argues that the recently-popular thesis that the probabilities of statistical mechanics (SM) can function as Best System chances runs into a serious obstacle: there is no one axiomatization of SM that is robustly best, as judged by the theoretical virtues of simplicity, strength, and fit. Beisbart takes this “no clear winner” result to imply that the probabilities yielded by the competing axiomatizations simply fail to count as Best System chances. In this reply, we express sympathy for the “no clear winner” thesis, however we argue that an importantly different moral should be drawn from this. We contend that the implication for Humean chances of there being no uniquely best axiomatization of SM is not that there are no SM chances, but rather that SM chances fail to be sharp.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 219.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Or alternatively a Renyi-Popper measure Ch(p|q) that maps proposition pairs 〈p, q〉 onto the reals in the [0, 1] interval. (Plausibly, if one takes conditional chance as basic in this way, then it is redundant to include a “time” index to the chance function; see Hoefer 2007, pp. 562–565; Glynn 2010, pp. 78–79.)

  2. 2.

    This notion of fit applies only if there are finitely many chance events. See Elga (2004) for an extension to infinite cases. In addition, if one wants to allow the possibility of statistical mechanical probabilities counting as chances, then one needs a notion of fit according to which one way a system may fit better is if its probability function assigns a relatively high probability to the macro-history of the world conditional upon a coarse-graining of its initial conditions (as well as assigning a relatively high probability to the micro-history conditional upon a fine graining of the initial conditions).

  3. 3.

    In the quantum case, the uniform probability distribution is not over classical phase space, but over the set of quantum states compatible with the PH.

  4. 4.

    Though see Winsberg (2004) and Earman (2006) for criticisms of this line or argument.

  5. 5.

    This proposal requires that initial conditions, such as PH, are potential axioms of the best system. The BSA has not always been construed as allowing for this. However, Lewis (1983, p. 367) himself seems sympathetic to the view that they may be.

  6. 6.

    Callender (2011) calls attempts to derive the SM probabilities from a probability distribution over the initial conditions of the universe as a whole “Globalist” approaches to axiomatizing SM. The Mentaculus is one example of a Globalist approach. Beisbart points out that there are rivals. In contrast to Globalist approaches, “Localist” approaches (see Callender op cit.) attempt to derive the SM probabilities from probability distributions over the initial states of the various approximately isolated subsystems of the universe. Beisbart observes that there is a range of competing Localist approaches to axiomatizing SM. While, for reasons of space, we will here focus upon the competing Globalist approaches, many of our points will carry across to the competition between Localist axiomatizations, if one thinks that the Localist approaches are more promising (see Glynn unpublished).

  7. 7.

    Indeed, as Beisbart points out, it is not clear precisely how low initial entropy is specified to be by the PH. Different precisifications of the PH yield different sized regions of phase space to which the uniform distribution is to be applied. So it seems that the number of competing systems may be larger still.

  8. 8.

    At least this might be so if, with Frigg and Hoefer (2013), we exclude information about the precise micro-state of the world as inadmissable, since “chance rules operate at a specific level and evidence pertaining to more fundamental levels is inadmissible.” See Maudlin (2007) for a discussion of how one can derive typical thermodynamic behavior without committing to precise assumptions either about the initial probability distribution or the size of the initial phase space region.

  9. 9.

    As we saw, Lewis claims that if there was not a unique best system, there would be nothing deserving of the name law, though he earlier (Lewis 1983, p. 367) said theorems entailed by all of the tied systems would count as laws. We’re sympathetic to his earlier position. If, for instance, the fundamental dynamics are the same in all the tied systems (this is not something that is disputed by Beisbart and others who have examined rivals to the Mentaculus), then they will come out as laws.

  10. 10.

    Frigg and Hoefer (2013) themselves find it plausible that there may not be a unique best system for our world.

  11. 11.

    Elga (2010) argues that unsharp credences are incompatible with perfect rationality. If this were correct, then perhaps any player of the chance role in guiding rational credence must itself be sharp. However, we find Joyce’s (2010) defense of unsharp credences against Elga’s argument compelling.

  12. 12.

    Also it’s not clear to us that an axiom system specifying that the universe was initially in a larger region of phase space than Γ0 is simpler than one specifying that the universe was in Γ0. As is well known (e.g. Lewis 1983, p. 367), simplicity is vocabulary-relative and, in order to avoid trivializing the desideratum of simplicity, we must take simplicity-when-formulated-with-unnatural-predicates to be less desirable than simplicity-when-formulated-with-reasonably-natural-predicates (and perhaps simplicity-when-formulated-with-perfectly-natural-predicates to be more desirable than both). In our not-too-unnatural macro-vocabulary, we may be able to formulate simple axioms that pick out moderately large regions of phase space like Γ0. Picking out smaller regions will often require employing complex microphysical predicates, thus increasing fit (and perhaps naturalness of predicates) at the expense of simplicity. But picking out larger regions than Γ0 may require disjunctions of reasonably natural macrophysical predicates. The resulting axiom systems will be both worse fitting and less simple (or worse fitting and formulated in less natural language). If so, they would be clearly inferior to an axiom system specifying that the universe was initially in Γ0.

References

  • Albert, D. 2000. Time and chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. 2012. Physics and chance. In Probability in physics, ed. Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo, 17–40. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C. 2014. Good just isn’t good enough – Humean chances and Boltzmannian statistical physics. In New directions in the philosophy of science, ed. M.C. Galavotti and D. Dieks. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. 2011. The past histories of molecules. In Probabilities in physics, ed. C. Beisbart and S. Hartmann, 83–113. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. 2006. The ‘past hypothesis’: Not even false. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37: 399–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. 2004. Infinitesimal chances and the laws of nature. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. 2010. Subjective probabilities should be sharp. Philosopher’ Imprint 10: 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenton-Glynn, L. unpublished. Unsharp best system chances. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/10239/

  • Frigg, R., and C. Hoefer. 2013. The best humean system for statistical mechanics. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-013-9541-5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., and C. Hoefer. 2010. Determinism and chance from a humean perspective. In The present situation in the philosophy of science, ed. D. Dieks, W.J. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, M. Weber, F. Stadler, and T. Uebel, 351–371. Berlin/New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. 2011. From Boltzmann to Arbuthnot: Higher-level laws and the best system. Philosophy of Science 78: 1001–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. forthcoming. Physical fundamentalism in a Lewisian best system. In Asymmetries of chance and time, ed. Alastair Wilson. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glynn, L. 2010. Deterministic chance. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61: 51–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. 2007. The third way on objective chance: A sceptic’s guide to objective chance. Mind 116: 549–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. 2010. A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives 24: 281–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. Postscripts to ‘a subjectivist’s guide to objective chance’. In his Philosophical papers, vol. 2, 114–132. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1994. Humean supervenience debugged. Mind 103: 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2001. Determinism and chance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32: 609–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2004. David Lewis’s humean theory of objective chance. Philosophy of Science 71: 1115–1125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2007. Counterfactuals and the second law. In Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited, ed. H. Price and R. Corry, 293–326. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2008. Why there is anything except physics. In Being reduced: New essays on reduction, explanation and causation, ed. J. Hohwy and J. Kallestrup, 149–163. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2012a. Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies 160: 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 2012b. The emergence of time’s arrows and special science laws from physics. Interface Focus 2: 13–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. 2007. What could be objective about probabilities? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38: 275–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2007. Deterministic chance? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58: 113–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. 2004. Can conditioning on the ‘past hypothesis’ militate against the reversibility objections? Philosophy of Science 71: 489–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

The authors would like to thank Claus Beisbart, Seamus Bradley and Leszek Wroński for helpful comments. We would also like to acknowledge the support of the Alexander von Humboldt-Foundation and the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Radin Dardashti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dardashti, R., Glynn, L., Thébault, K., Frisch, M. (2014). Unsharp Humean Chances in Statistical Physics: A Reply to Beisbart. In: Galavotti, M., Dieks, D., Gonzalez, W., Hartmann, S., Uebel, T., Weber, M. (eds) New Directions in the Philosophy of Science. The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04382-1_37

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics