Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 370))

  • 2408 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter discusses in detail the idea that mathematical beauty should be reinterpreted to preserve mathematics’ stand among the sciences. Three reasons to reinterpret mathematical beauty are examined; the two cultures split, the epistemic character of mathematics, and its rational character. It shall be argued that the reasons for endorsing a non literal interpretation of mathematical beauty are rather weak. The discussion also examines the conceptions of mathematical beauty by Shaftesbury, Hutchenson and Gian-Carlo Rota.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I must emphasize that the notation was not what made the proof hard to understand. The proof was hard to understand primarily because of its ideas were novel and it involved intricate and very abstract machinery that was alien to the field. That resulted in a notation that appeared obscure even to the specialist. But this simple need of having to learn a new notation makes technical subjects very opaque to the non-specialist. This is true not only for the lay person, but also for mathematicians themselves.

  2. 2.

    Rota does not mention it explicitly, but he is referring to G. H. Hardy’s view [33] that the unexpectedness and inevitability of a theorem or proof are the sources of mathematical beauty.

  3. 3.

    In a proof by contradiction, or reductio ad absurdum, one assumes the negation of the statement to be proven and shows that it leads to a contradiction.

  4. 4.

    It must be noted that intuitionism does not reject all proofs by reductio ad absurdum, but only those that intend to establish an existential claim, or those that intend to move from not-not-A to A. At any rate, the kind of proofs rejected by intuitionism can be considered characteristically non-enlightening.

  5. 5.

    Discussing the rationality of science or mathematics is beyond the scope of this book; here I address solely the issues relevant to the interpretation of beauty.

Bibliography

  1. Aaboe, A. (1963). Episodes from the early history of mathematics. New York: MAA.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aigner, M., & Ziegler, G. M. (2004). Proofs from the book. Berlin/New York, Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Alperson, P., & Kivy, P. (2004). The philosophy of music: Formalism and beyond. In P. Kivy (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to aesthetics (pp. 254–275). Malden: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  4. Appel, K., & Haken, W. (1976). Every planar map is four colorable. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 82(5), 711–713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Appel, K., & Haken, W. (1977). Every planar map is four colorable. Part I: Discharging. Illinois Journal of Mathematics, 21(3), 429–490.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Appel, K., & Haken, W. (1986). The four color proof suffices. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 8(1), 10–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Appel, K., Haken, W., & Koch, J. (1977). Every planar map is four colorable. Part II: Reducibility. Illinois Journal of Mathematics, 21(3), 491–567.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ax, A. F. (1953). The physiological differentiation between fear and anger in humans. Psychosomatic Medicine, 15(5), 433–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Balaguer, M. (2001). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(19), 661–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Brady, E., & Levinson, J. (2001). Aesthetic concepts: Essays after Sibley. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Budd, M. (1992). Music and the emotions: The philosophical theories. Psychology Press. London: Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cohen, T. (1973). Aesthetic/non-aesthetic and the concept of taste: A critique of Sibley’s position. Theoria, 39(1–3), 113–152.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Colyvan, M. (2003). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cooper, A. A. (1964). Third earl of shaftesbury. Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, 1711, 397–400.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Damasio, A. (2005). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. London/New York: Penguin (Non-Classics).

    Google Scholar 

  17. De Clercq, R. (2005). Aesthetic terms, metaphor, and the nature of aesthetic properties. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63(1), 27–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. de Villiers, M. (2004). The role and function of quasi-empirical methods in mathematics. Canadian Journal of Math, Science & Technology Education, 4(3), 397–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Dirac, P. (1980). Why we believe in the Einstein theory? In B. Gruber & R. S. Millman (Eds.), Symmetries in science. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Dreyfus, H. L., & Wrathall, M. A. (2006). A companion to phenomenology and existentialism (Vol. 35). Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Ekman, P., & Davidson, R. J. (Eds.). (1994). The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (1st ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Feigl, H. (1970). Beyond peaceful coexistence. In R. H. Stuewer (Ed.), Historical and philosophical perspectives of science (Number 5 in Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, pp. 3–11). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Feynman, R. P., & Weinberg, S. (1999). Elementary particles and the laws of physics: The 1986 Dirac memorial lectures. New York/Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands, M. (2011). The Feynman lectures on physics, Vol. I: The new millennium edition: mainly mechanics, radiation, and heat. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Field, H. H. (1980). Science without numbers: A defence of nominalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Franks, J. (2010). Cantor’s other proofs that R is uncountable. Mathematics Magazine, 83(4), 283–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Frege, G. (1980). Frege against the formalists. In M. Black & P. Geach (Eds.), Philosophical writings: Translations (3rd ed., pp. 162–213; 2nd ed., 1970, 1969, 1966, 1960; 1st ed. 1952). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Goldman, A. (1995). Aesthetic value (Focus series). Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Gow, J. (2010). A short history of Greek mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. Guyer, P. (2004). The origins of modern aesthetics: 1711–35. In P. Kivy (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to aesthetics (pp. 15–44). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Hardy, G. H. (1992). A mathematician’s apology. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Hillman, D. J. (1962). The measurement of simplicity. Philosophy of Science, 29, 225–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Hungerland, I. C. (1962). The logic of aesthetic concepts. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 36, 43–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Hutcheson, F. (1973). Francis Hutchenson: An inquiry concerning beauty, order, harmony, design (Vol. 9). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Kaku, M., & Thompson, J. T. (1997). Beyond Einstein: The cosmic quest for the theory of the universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Kivy, P. (1975). What makes “Aesthetic” terms aesthetic? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36(2), 197–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Kivy, P. (1980). The corded shell: Reflections on musical expression. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Kivy, P. (1989). Sound sentiment: An essay on the musical emotions, including the complete text of the corded shell. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Kivy, P. (1991). Music alone: Philosophical reflections on the purely musical experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Kivy, P. (1993). The fine art of repetition: Essays in the philosophy of music. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Kivy, P. (1997). Philosophies of arts: An essay in differences. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kivy, P. (2002). Introduction to a philosophy of music. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Kline, M. (1990). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times, Vol. 1 (1st ptg. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kline, M. (1990). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times, Vol. 2. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Kline, M. (1990). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times, Vol. 3. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Kuipers, T. A. F. (2000). From instrumentalism to constructive realism: On some relations between confirmation, empirical progress, and truth approximation. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  49. Kuipers, T. A. F. (2002). Beauty, a road to the truth. Synthese, 131(3), 291–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Lakatos, I., Worrall, J., & Zahar, E. (Eds.). (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Langer, S. K. K. (1957). Philosophy in a new key: A study in the symbolism of reason, rite, and art (Vol. 17). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Laudan, L. (1978). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  54. LeDoux, J. (1996). Emotional networks and motor control: A fearful view. Progress in Brain Research, 107, 437–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. LeDoux, J. E. (1998). The emotional brain: The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  56. LeDoux, J., & Bemporad, J. R. (1997). The emotional brain. Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis, 25(3), 525–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Le Lionnais, F. (1971). Les grands courants de la pensée mathématique. Marseille: Cahiers du Sud.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Le Lionnais, F. (2004). Great currents of mathematical thought: Mathematics: Concepts and development (Vol. 1). Mineola: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Levenson, R. W. (1994). The search for autonomic specificity. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 252–257). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Livio, M., & Grunwald, E. (2006). The equation that couldn’t be solved: How mathematical genius discovered the language of symmetry. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 28(4), 63–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Marenbon, J. (2003). Boethius. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  62. McAllister, J. (1996). Beauty and revolution in science. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. McAllister, J. (1998). Is beauty a sign of truth in scientific theories? American Scientist, 86(2), 174–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. McAllister, J. W. (2005). Mathematical beauty and the evolution of the standards of mathematical proof. In M. Emmer (Ed.), The visual mind II (Vol. 2). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  65. McWeeny, R. (2002). Symmetry: An introduction to group theory and its applications. Mineola: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Montano, U. (2010). Beauty in mathematics. PhD thesis, [s.n.], S.l. University of Groningen, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Montano, U. (2012). Ugly mathematics: Why do mathematicians dislike computer-assisted proofs? The Mathematical Intelligencer, 34(4), 21–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Nahin, P. J. (1998). An imaginary tale: The Story of i [the square root of minus one]. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Nahin, P. J. (2006). Dr. Euler’s fabulous formula: Cures many mathematical ills. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Nahin, P. J. (2011). Dr. Euler’s fabulous formula: Cures many mathematical ills. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  71. Newton, I. (2003). Newton’s philosophy of nature selections from his writings. Whitefish, Mont. Kessinger Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Newton-Smith, W. (1981). The rationality of science. Boston: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  73. Ortony, A. (1991). Value and emotion. In G. Mandler, W. Kessen, A. Ortony, & F. I. M. Craik (Eds.), Memories, thoughts, and emotions: Essays in the honor of George Mandler (pp. 337–353). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1990). The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Popper, K. R. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Robinson, J. (2005). Deeper than reason: Emotion and its role in literature, music, and art. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  77. Robinson, J. (2005). Deeper than reason: Emotion and its role in music literature and art. London: Claredon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  78. Rota, G. (1997). The phenomenology of mathematical proof. Synthese, 111(2), 183–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Rota, G.-C. (1997). The phenomenology of mathematical beauty. Synthese, 111(2), 171–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Rota, G. C. (2005). The phenomenology of mathematical beauty. In M. Emmer (Ed.), The visual mind II (pp. 2–13). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Russell, B. (2004). Mysticism and logic. Mineola: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Sibley, F. (1959). Aesthetic concepts. The Philosophical Review, 68(4), 421–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Snow, C. P. (2012). The two cultures. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  84. Solomon, R. C. (2005). Subjectivity. In T. Honderich (Ed.), The Oxford companion to philosophy new edition (2nd ed.). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Stuewer, R. H. (Ed.). (1970). Historical and philosophical perspectives of science (Volume 5 of Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Swinnerton-Dyer, P. (2005). The justification of mathematical statements. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 363(1835), 2437–2447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Thagard, P. (2005). Why is beauty a road to the truth? Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 84(1), 365–370.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Thomas, R. S. D. (2007). The comparison of mathematics with narrative. In B. Kerkhove & J. P. Bendegem (Eds.), Perspectives on mathematical practices (Volume 5 of Logic, epistemology, and the unity of science, pp. 43–59). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Tymoczko, T. (1979). The four-color problem and its philosophical significance. The Journal of Philosophy, 76(2), 57–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  90. Weber, K. (2009). How syntactic reasoners can develop understanding, evaluate conjectures, and generate counterexamples in advanced mathematics. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 28(2), 200–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  91. Weber, K., & Alcock, L. (2004). Semantic and syntactic proof productions. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 56(2), 209–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  92. Weinberg, S. (1994). Dreams of a final theory. New York: Vintage Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  93. Wells, D. (1988). Which is the most beautiful? The Mathematical Intelligencer, 10(4), 30–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  94. Wells, D. (1990). Are these the most beautiful? The Mathematical Intelligencer, 12(3), 37–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  95. Wright, C. (1994). Truth and objectivity. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Zajonc, R. B. (1984). On the primacy of affect. American Psychologist, 39(2), 117–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  97. Zajonc, R. B. (1998). Emotions. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 591–632). Boston: McGraw-Hill

    Google Scholar 

  98. Zajonc, R. B. (2001). Mere exposure: A gateway to the subliminal. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 10(6), 224–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  99. Zangwill, N. (2003). Beauty. In J. Levinson (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of aesthetics. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Zangwill, N. (2010). Aesthetic judgment. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2010 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/aesthetic-judgment/.

  101. Zangwill, N. (2011). Music, essential metaphor, and private language. American Philosophical Quarterly, 48(1), 1.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Montano, U. (2014). On Non-literal Approaches. In: Explaining Beauty in Mathematics: An Aesthetic Theory of Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol 370. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-03452-2_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics