Advertisement

Context as Assumptions

Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 369)

Abstract

The article provides an overview of linguistic context dependence and seeks to lay out some adequacy criteria that a theory of linguistic context dependence has to fulfill. Indexicals in the narrow sense are distinguished from the much more common contextuals. While indexicals proper semantically depend on a possibly shifted deictic center given by the context of a possible utterance, the broader class of contextuals are marked for and subject to additional interpretation depending on the doxastic context of a discourse participant. The interpretation of contextuals is sometimes mandatory and sometimes optional and using parametrized modal logics for these expressions as if they were pure indexicals is of limited use only. Instead, it is suggested to stipulate open argument places in the lexicon entries of contextuals and consider their interpretation a form of abductive inference to a narrowed down semantic content that is most plausible to an agent in a given context.Such a representation is desirable, because it hooks up the notion of interpretation with representations of graded belief from Formal Epistemology. An example of how to implement such an inference mechanism in a type theory with inner negation is given.

Keywords

Context-dependence Assumptions Indexicality Contextuals Graded belief 

References

  1. Allen, J. F. (1983). Maintaining knowledge about temporal intervals. Communications of the ACM, 26(11), 832–843.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bach, K. (2004). Minding the gap. In C. Bianchi (Ed.), The semantics/pragmatics distinction (pp. 27–43). Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  3. Bach, K. (2005). Context ex machina. In Z. G. Szabó (Ed.), Semantics versus pragmatics (pp. 16–44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bach, K. (2006). The excluded middle: Semantic minimalism without minimal propositions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 435–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bach, K. (2007a). From the strange to the bizarre: Another reply to Cappelen and Lepore. Department of Philosophy, University of San Fransisco. Retrieved in may 2008 from http://userwww.sfsu.edu/~kbach/.
  6. Bach, K. (2007b). Minimal semantics. Philosophical Review, 116, 303–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bach, K. (2007c). Minimalism for Dummies: Reply to Cappelen and Lepore. Department of Philosophy, University of San Francisco. Retrieved in may 2008 from http://userwww.sfsu.edu/~kbach/.
  8. Bach, K. (2009). Why speaker intentions aren’t part of context. Technical report, San Francisco State University. Compilation of arguments from earlier papers, published online at http://userwww.sfsu.edu/~kbach/Bach.Intentions&Context.pdf.
  9. Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2006). Conditional doxastic models: A qualitative approach to dynamic belief revision. Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 165, 5–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2011). Keep changing your beliefs and aiming for the truth. Erkenntnis, 75(2), 255–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Bar-Hillel, Y. (1954). Indexical expressions. MIND, 63, 359–376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Borg, E. (2004). Minimal semantics. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Borg, E. (2007). Minimalism versus contextualism in semantics. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context sensitivity and semantic minimalism: Essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 546–571). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Borg, E. (2010). Minimalism and the content of the lexicon. In L. Baptista & E. H. Rast (Eds.), Meaning and context (pp. 51–78). Bern/New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
  15. Borg, E. (2012a). Pursuing meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Borg, E. (2012b). Semantics without pragmatics (chap.  25). In K. Allen & K. M. Jaszczolt (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of pragmatics (pp. 513–528). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Bühler, K. (1934). Sprachtheorie. Stuttgart/Jena: Fischer.Google Scholar
  18. Burks, A. (1949). Icon, index and symbol. Philosophical and Phenomenological Research, 9(4), 673–689.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Buvač, S. (1995). Formalizing context. Technical report FS-95-02, AAAI.Google Scholar
  20. Buvač, S. (1996). Quantificational logic of context. In Proceedings of the thirteenth national conference on artificial intelligence, Portland.Google Scholar
  21. Buvač, S., Buvač, V., & Mason, I. A. (1995). Metamathematics of contexts. Fundamenta Informaticae, 23(3), 263–301.Google Scholar
  22. Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2004). Insensitive semantics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005). A tall tale: In defence of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth (pp. 197–220). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2006). Shared content. In E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of language (pp. 1020–1055). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Cohen, S. (1990). Skepticism and everyday knowledge attributions. In M. D. Roth & G. Ross (Eds.), Doubting (pp. 161–169). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Comrie, B. (1985). Tense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. DeRose, K. (1996). Relevant alternatives and the content of knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56, 193–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Fillmore, Ch. J. (1972). Ansätze zu einer Theorie der Deixis. In F. Kiefer (Ed.), Semantik und generative Grammatik I (pp. 147–174). Frankfurt a.M.: Athenäum.Google Scholar
  30. Frege, G. (1986). Der Gedanke. In G. Patzig (Ed.), Logische Untersuchungen (pp. 30–53). Göttingen: Vandenhoeck. First published in: Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus 2, 58–77 (1918).Google Scholar
  31. Giunchiglia, F. (1993). Contextual reasoning. Epistemologia, XVI, 345–364.Google Scholar
  32. Heim, I. (1983). File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (pp. 164–189). Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  33. Hobbs, J. R., Stickel, M., Appelt, D., & Martin, P. (1993). Interpretation as abduction. Artificial Intelligence, 63(1–2), 69–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Jespersen, O. (1922). Language: Its nature, development and origin. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
  35. Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  36. Kaplan, D. (1988). On the logic of demonstratives. In N. Salmon & S. Soames (Eds.), Propositions and attitudes (pp. 66–82). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Ladkin, P. B. (1987). The logic of time representation. PhD thesis, University of California, Berkeley. Reference http://wwwlib.umi.com/dissertations/fullcit/8813947.
  38. Lang, J., & van der Torre, L. (2007). From belief change to preference change. In G. Bonanno, J. Delgrande, J. Lang, & H. Rott (Eds.), Formal models of belief change in rational agents: Number 07351 in Dagstuhl seminar proceedings, Internationales Begegnungs- und Forschungszentrum für Informatik (IBFI), Schloss Dagstuhl.Google Scholar
  39. Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 643–686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Lasersohn, P. (2008). Quantification and perspective in relativist semantics. Philosophical Perspectives, 22(1), 305–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Liu, F. (2008). Changing for the better. Number DS-2008-02 in ILLC dissertation series. Institute for Logic, Language, and Computation, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  42. MacFarlane, J. (2005a). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 197–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. MacFarlane, J. (2005b). Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105, 321–339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. MacFarlane, J. (2007a). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166(2), 231–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. MacFarlane, J. (2007b). Relativism and disagreement. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 17–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. MacFarlane, J. (2008). Truth in the garden of forking paths. In M. Carcía-Carpintero & M. Kölbel (Eds.), Relative truth (pp. 81–102). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. MacFarlane, J. (2009). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166, 231–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. McCarthy, J. (1993). Notes on formalizing context. In R. Bajcsy (Ed.), Proceedings of IJCAI, Chambéry (Number 13, pp. 555–562). Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  49. Mount, A. (2008). The impurity of “pure” indexicals. Philosophical Studies, 138, 193–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Muskens, R. (1995). Meaning and partiality. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  51. Perry, J. (1977). Frege on demonstratives. Philosophical Review, 86, 474–497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Perry, J. (1997). Indexicals and demonstratives. In R. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), Companion to the philosophy of language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  54. Perry, J. (1998). Indexicals, contexts and unarticulated constituents. In Proceedings of the 1995 CSLI Amsterdam logic, language and computation conference. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, 1–16.Google Scholar
  55. Perry, J. (2003). Predelli’s threatening note: Contexts, utterances, and tokens in the philosophy of language. Journal of Pragmatics, 35, 373–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Perry, J. (2005). Using indexicals. In M. Devitt (Ed.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of language (pp. 314–334). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  57. Rast, E. H. (2007). Reference and indexicality. Berlin: Logos Verlag.Google Scholar
  58. Rast, E. H. (2009). Context and interpretation. In J. M. Larrazabal & L. Zubeldia (Eds.), Meaning, content, and argument. Proceedings of the ILCLI international workshop on semantics, pragmatics, and rhetoric (pp. 515–534). San Sebastian: University of the Basque Country Press.Google Scholar
  59. Rast, E. H. (2010). Plausibility revision in higher-order logic with an application in two-dimensional semantics. In X. Arrazola & M. Ponte (Eds.), Proceedings of the logKCA-10 – proceedings of the second ILCLI international workshop on logic and philosophy of knowledge, communication and action, Donostia/San Sebastián (pp. 387–403). ILCLI/University of the Basque Country Press.Google Scholar
  60. Rast, E. H. (2011). Non-indexical context dependence and the interpretation as abduction approach. Lodz Papers in Pragmatics, 7(2), 259–279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Récanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  62. Récanati, F. (2010). Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Macmillian.Google Scholar
  64. Richard, M. (2004). Contextualism and relativism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 215–242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Russell, B. (1966). An inquiry into meaning and truth. London: George Allen and Unwin LTD.Google Scholar
  66. Serafini, L., & Bouquet, P. (2004). Comparing formal theories of context in AI. Artifical Intelligence Journal, 155(1), 41–67. ITC-IRST technical report 0201-02.Google Scholar
  67. Sinowjew, A. A. (1970). Komplexe logik. Berlin/Braunschweig: VEB Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften/Vieweg Verlag/C. F. Winter’sche Verlagshandlung Berlin.Google Scholar
  68. Sinowjew, A. A., & Wessel, H. (1975). Logische Sprachregeln. Berlin/Braunschweig/Basel: Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
  69. Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  70. Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (2006). Relevance theory (chap.  27). In L. R. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), Handbook of pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  71. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics: Vol. 9. Syntax and semantics (pp. 315–332). New York: Academic.Google Scholar
  72. Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(5–6), 701–721.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Stanley, J. (2000). Context and logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23(4), 391–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Stanley, J. (2002). Nominal restriction (chap.  12). In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Logical form and language (pp. 365–388). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  75. Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind & Language, 15(2–3), 219–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Stojanovic, I. (2008). The scope and the subtleties of the contextualism/literalism/relativism debate. Language and Linguistics Compass, 2, 1171–1188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Stokhof, M., & Groenendijk, J. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(1), 39–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Stone, M., & Thomason, R. H. (2002). Context in abductive interpretation. In EDILOG 2002: Proceedings of the sixth workshop on the semantics and pragmatics of dialogue, Edinburgh (pp. 169–176).Google Scholar
  79. Thomason, R. H. (2003). Dynamic contextual intensional logic: Logical foundations and an application. In P. Blackburn, C. Ghidini, R. M. Turner, & F. Giunchiglia (Eds.), Modeling and using context: Fourth international and interdisciplinary conference CONTEXT 2003, Stanford (pp. 328–341). Springer.Google Scholar
  80. Travis, C. (2008). Occasion-sensitivity. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. van Benthem, J. (1991). The logic of time (2nd ed.). Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer. (first ed. publ. 1983).Google Scholar
  82. van Benthem, J. (2006). Dynamic logic of belief revision. ILLC tech report, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  83. van Benthem, J., & Liu, F. (2005). Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. ILLC tech report PP-2005-29, Institute for Logic, Language & Computation, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  84. van Benthem, J., van Eijck, J., & Kooi, B. (2006). Logics of communication and change. Information and Computation, 204(11), 1620–1662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Wessel, H. (1989). Logik. Berlin: Logos Verlag.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e Humanas, Instituto de Filosofia da LinguagemUniversidade Nova de LisboaLisboaPortugal

Personalised recommendations