Skip to main content

Grice, Conversational Implicature and Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 1))

Abstract

The importance of Grice’s theory of conversation and in particular his account of conversational implicature (Grice in Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 22–40, 1975; 1978) in the development and current concerns of pragmatics is almost impossible to exaggerate. Whether or not they agree with the details or even the broader framework of Grice’s theory, pragmaticists generally acknowledge the significance of his attempt to give a formalised account of the differences between what our words literally mean and what we intend to communicate in using them. But Grice himself was a philosopher, not a linguist; his work was deeply rooted in the philosophical preoccupations of the mid twentieth century, and he never used the word ‘pragmatic’ in his writings as it is used in present day linguistics. This chapter will address the contrast between Grice’s philosophical motivations in developing his account of conversational implicature, and the linguistic framework in which it has subsequently generally been discussed. It will do so by considering the philosophical context in which Grice was working and some of the specific philosophical problems to which he applied his notion of conversational implicature. It will begin with a review of the dichotomy in twentieth century analytic philosophy that can be summarised as a distinction between ‘ideal language’ and ‘ordinary language’ philosophy, and will discuss Grice’s work as an attempt to demonstrate some fundamental misconceptions in both positions. In doing so, it will compare Grice’s work on conversational implicature with the near contemporary work by Austin on speech acts (Austin in How to do things with words. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1962a; Sense and sensibilia. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1962b). Austin’s work shares a number of apparent similarities with Grice’s, but reveals some significant philosophical differences, particularly with regard to the nature of ‘literal meaning’ and the role of theorising. This chapter will then offer an exegesis of Grice’s conception of conversational implicature, including the distinction which seemed necessary to him between ‘generalised’ and ‘particularised’ conversational implicatures, and some of the properties that he identified as characteristic of conversational implicatures. Following this exegesis, this chapter will consider some of the applications and extensions of the concept of conversational implicature suggested by Grice and, in some cases, developed further by his later commentators. Grice found his concept to be fruitful in addressing a range of established philosophical problems, including the viability of his own earlier work on ‘non-natural meaning’ (Grice in Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 213–223, 1957), the contrasting claims of realism and skepticism (Grice in Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 147–153, c. 1946–1950; pp. 154–170, c. 1953–1958; pp. 224–247, 1961), apparent differences between logic and natural language (Grice in Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 3–21, 1967a; pp. 58–85, 1967b) and the debate over Russell’s logical account of definite descriptions (Grice in Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Harvard, pp. 269–282, 1981). Grice introduced the technical term ‘implicature’ into his philosophy of language. It has subsequently become part of the defining terminology of present day pragmatics and is a central concept both for those working in a broadly neo-Gricean framework (Horn in A natural history of negation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1989; Pragmatics. Palgrave, Basingstoke, pp. 158–183, 2007; Levinson in Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, 2000) and for those working in relevance theory (Sperber and Wilson in Relevance. Blackwell, Oxford, 1995; Carston in Thoughts and utterances. Blackwell, Oxford, 2002). Recent interest in pragmatics has focussed on the division that Grice drew between ‘what is said’ and ‘what is implicated’, and on the viability of that distinction. This has been a focus of study in both theoretical pragmatics (Borg in Minimal semantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2004; Recanati in Literal meaning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2004; Cappelen and Lepore in Insensitive semantics: a defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Blackwell, Oxford, 2005) and experimental pragmatics (Gibbs, Brain and Language 68: 466–485, 1999; Glucksberg in Experimental pragmatics. Palgrave, Basingstoke, pp. 72–93, 2004; Breheny et al., Cognition 100: 434–463, 2006). This chapter will conclude with an assessment of the significance of Grice’s delineation of ‘what is said’ as a defining opposite of ‘what is implicated’. For Grice himself, although it was central to his original philosophical motivations, this remained one of the most troublesome and least successful aspects of his philosophy of language. For pragmaticists it has proved one of the most enduring, challenging and intriguing topics of debate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For further discussion of Grice's relationship to OLP, see Chapman (2005, 2010) and Lüthi (2006).

  2. 2.

    See, for instance, Karttunen and Peters (1979), Gazdar (1979), Levinson (1983) and Potts (2005).

  3. 3.

    In this he could be seen as being in agreement with Austin, who said of realism that: ‘This doctrine would be no less scholastic and erroneous than its antithesis' (Austin 1962b: 3–4).

  4. 4.

    Especially in Austin (1962b).

  5. 5.

    ‘The principle of conversational helpfulness' was a term used by Grice in early version of his theory of conversation. He later changed it to ‘the cooperative principle', but the earlier term has survived in the published version of this lecture.

  6. 6.

    See, for instance McCawley (1981), Levinson (1983) and Horn (1989).

  7. 7.

    In some later discussion of such examples, it has been claimed that saying this would in fact involve the speaker in a logical contradiction if the negation is interpreted logically, but not if it is interpreted as 'metalinguistic', registering an objection to the form of words used because of the problematic presupposition they introduce (see for instance Horn 1985). But Grice interprets his example as the explicit cancelation of an implicature, giving rise to no logical contradiction.

  8. 8.

    Bezuidenhout offers a useful overview of that literature and of its relationship to Grice's observations.

  9. 9.

    See, for instance, Asa Kasher's claim that Grice opened a ‘gap in the hedge', which first brought to the attention of linguists the idea that they might look for explanations of meaning that went beyond the linguistic system itself (Kasher, cited in Mey 1989: 825).

  10. 10.

    Experimental work is predominantly, but not exclusively, opposed to Gricean analysis. For an example of experimental work that concludes in favour of Grice see for instance Winer et al. (2001).

  11. 11.

    See also Martinich (2010).

  12. 12.

    Tape, 29 January 1983, Grice in conversation with Richard Warner and Judith Baker, H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library, University of California, Berkeley.

References

  • Ahlsén, Elisabeth. 1993. Conversational principles and aphasic communication. Journal of Pragmatics 19: 57–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1940. The meaning of a word. In Philosophical Papers, Austin, J.L. 1961, 23–43. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1950. Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Reprinted in Philosophical papers, Austin, J.L. 1961, 85–101. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1956. A plea for excuses. In Philosophical papers, Austin, J.L. 1961, 123–152. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1962a. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1962b. Sense and sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A.J. 1946. Language, truth and logic, 2nd edn. Harmondsworth: Pelican. (1st edn. London 1936).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 2001. You don’t say? Syntheses 128: 15–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, Anne. 2010. Grice on presupposition. In Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice, ed. Petrus Klaus, 75–102. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, Anne, and Robin Morris. 2004. Implicature, relevance and default pragmatic inference. In Experimental pragmatics, eds. Noveck Ira, and Sperber Dan, 257–282. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake, Norman. 2002. A grammar of Shakespeare’s language. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg, Emma. 2004. Minimal semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Breheny, Richard, Napoleon Katos, and John Williams. 2006. Are generalized scalar implicatures generated by default? An on-line investigation into the role of context in generating pragmatics inferences. Cognition 100: 434–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burton-Roberts, Noel. 1989. The limits to debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, Herman, and Ernie Lepore. 2005. Insensitive semantics: a defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1937. The logical syntax of language. London: Routledge and Keegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, Siobhan. 2005. Paul Grice, philosopher and linguist. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, Siobhan. 2010. Paul Grice and the philosophy of ordinary language. In Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice, ed. Petrus Klaus, 31–46. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, Gottlob. 1892. On sense and meaning. In Translations from the philosophical writings of gottlob frege, eds. Geach Peter and Black Max, 1980, 56–78. Oxford: Blackwell (1st edn. 1952).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition and logical form. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, Raymond. 1999. Interpreting what speakers say and implicate. Brain and Language 68: 466–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glucksberg, Sam. 2004. On the automaticity of pragmatic processes: A modular proposal. In Experimental pragmatics, ed. Noveck Ira, and Sperber Dan, 72–93. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. c. 1946–1950. Common sense and skepticism. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 147–153. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. c. 1953–1958. G. E. Moore and the philosopher’s paradoxes. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 154–170. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1957. Meaning. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 213–223. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1958. Postwar Oxford philosophy. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 171–180, Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1961. The causal theory of perception. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 224–247. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1967a. Prolegomena. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 3–21. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1967b. Indicative conditionals. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 58–85. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1969. Utterer’s meaning and intentions. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 86–116. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 22–40. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1978. Further notes on logic and conversation. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 41–57. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1981. Presupposition and conversational implicature. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 269–282. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1986. Reply to Richards. In Philosophical grounds of rationality, eds. Grandy Richard and Warner Richard, 45–106. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1987. Retrospective epilogue. In Studies in the way of words, Grice Paul, 1989, 339–385. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 1985. Metalinguistic negation and pragmatic ambiguity. Language 61: 121–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 2007. Neo-Gricean pragmatics: a Manichaean manifesto. In Pragmatics, ed. Burton-Roberts Noel, 158–183. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 2010. WJ-40: Issues in the investigation of implicature. In Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice, ed. Petrus Klaus, 310–339. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, Lauri, and Stanley Peters. 1979. Conventional implicature. In Syntax and semantics, vol 11: Presupposition, eds. Oh C.-K., and Dineen D., 1–56. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen. 2000. Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lüthi, David. 2006. How implicatures make Grice an unordinary ordinary language philosopher. Pragmatics 16: 247–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, Norman. 1942. Moore and ordinary language. In The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. Schilpp Paul Arthur, 345–368. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinich, Al. 2010. The total content of what a speaker means. In Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice, ed. Petrus Klaus, 252–267. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCawley, James. 1981. Everything that linguists have always wanted to know about logic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, Jacob. 1989. The end of the copper age, or: pragmatics 12½ years after. Journal of Pragmatics 13: 825–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1925. A defence of common sense. In Philosophical papers, Moore G.E., 1959, 32–59, London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1939. Proof of an external world. In Philosophical papers, Moore G.E., 1959, 127–150. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., and S. Leekam. 1986. Belief and quantity: Three year olds’ adaption to listener’s knowledge. Journal of Child Language 13: 305–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrus, Klaus. 2010. Introduction: Paul Grice, philosopher of language, but more than that. In Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice, ed. Petrus Klaus, 1–30. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Potts, Christopher. 2005. The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2004. Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard (ed.). 1967. The linguistic turn: Recent essays in philosophical method. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1905. On denoting. Mind 14: 479–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand, and Alfred Whitehead. 1910. Principia Mathematica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2002. What is said and psychological reality: Grice’s project and relevance theorists’ criticisms. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1969. Speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson. 1995. Relevance, 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1950. On referring. Mind 59: 320–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1952. Introduction to logical theory. London: Methuen and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winer, Gerald, Jane Cottrell, Tammy Mott, Matthew Cohen, and Jody Fournier. 2001. Are children more accurate than adults? Spontaneous use of metaphor by children and adults. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 50: 485–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Siobhan Chapman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chapman, S. (2013). Grice, Conversational Implicature and Philosophy. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01011-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics