Skip to main content

Towards the Proof-Theoretic Unification of Dung’s Argumentation Framework: An Adaptive Logic Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Adaptive Logics for Defeasible Reasoning

Part of the book series: Trends in Logic ((TREN,volume 38))

  • 880 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter presents a unifying adaptive logic framework for abstract argumentation. It consists of a core system for abstract argumentation and various adaptive logics based on it. These logics represent in an accurate sense all standard extensions defined within Dung?s abstract argumentation framework with respect to skeptical and credulous acceptance. The models of our logics correspond exactly to specific extensions of given argumentation frameworks. Additionally, the dynamics of adaptive proofs mirror the argumentative reasoning of a rational agent. In particular, the presented logics allow for external dynamics, i.e., they are able to deal with the arrival of new arguments and are therefore apt to model open-ended argumentations by providing provisional conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A former version of the content of this chapter has been published under the name “Towards the Proof-Theoretic Unification of Dung’s Argumentation Framework: An Adaptive Logic Approach” in the “Journal of Logic and Computation”, 2010, [1]. The paper is co-authored by Dunja Šešelja.

  2. 2.

    We restrict the discussion in this chapter to the finite case, i.e., to argumentation frameworks with a finite number of propositional letters.

  3. 3.

    Semi-stable semantics were defined by Caminada in [22] and are equivalent to Verhijs’ admissible stage extensions in [29].

  4. 4.

    Our notion of defeat differs from the way defeat is defined in various preference or value based enhancements of Dung’s abstract argumentation framework. Defeat is there usually defined as a binary relation between arguments which is a subset of the attack relation: \(a_1\) defeats \(a_2\) iff \(a_1\) attacks \(a_2\) and \(a_2\) is not ‘preferable’ to \(a_1\). The preferability of one argument over another is modeled in different ways: in terms of a preference relation between arguments in [30], by allowing for arguments to attack an attack in [31], or in terms of mapping arguments into partially ordered values in [19].

  5. 5.

    The following fact offers an alternative definition of semi-stable extensions in terms of admissible sets \(S\) for which \(S \cup S^+\) is maximal: Let \({\mathsf {A}} = \langle {\mathcal {A}}, \rightarrow \rangle \) be an AF and \(S \subseteq {\mathcal {A}}\). \(S\) is a semi-stable extension iff \(S\) is an admissible set of arguments for which there is no admissible set of arguments \(T \subseteq {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(T \cup T^+ \supset S \cup S^+\). The statement is proven in Appendix F, Fact F.3.1.

  6. 6.

    We also allow for \(\bot \) on the left hand side of \(\twoheadrightarrow \). We will comment on this in a moment.

  7. 7.

    More precisely we would have to express this by “as many propositional letters as possible that represent arguments of the given AF”.

  8. 8.

    Actually, as we will see in Sect. 8.3.5, the \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-models of \(\varGamma ^n_{\mathsf {A}}\) are a superset of the models corresponding to the admissible extensions of \({\mathsf {A}}\). Due to this we will perform a pre-selection on the \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-models before selecting the \(\varOmega _P\)-minimally abnormal models (see Sect. 8.3.6).

  9. 9.

    See Chap. 3 for a detailed discussion of their meta-theory.

  10. 10.

    The reader should not be confused by the fact that for both strategies, simple strategy resp. minimal abnormality, we apply the same semantic selection, namely the selection of minimally abnormal \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-models with respect to the abnormalities in \(\varOmega _\twoheadrightarrow \) resp. \(\varOmega _P\). The reason for this is that the simple strategy is equivalent to the minimal abnormality strategy for a lower limit logic \({\mathbf {LLL}}\), abnormalities \(\varOmega \) and a class of premise sets \(\varvec{\varGamma }\) if the following fact holds:

    (\(F\star \)): For all \(\varGamma \in \varvec{\varGamma }\) and all finite and non-empty \(\varDelta \subseteq \varOmega \), \(\varGamma \vdash _\mathbf{LLL}\;\mathsf{Dab}(\varDelta )\), then there is a \(\varphi \in \varDelta \) such that \(\varGamma \vdash _\mathbf{LLL} \varphi \).

    This is the case for our \({\mathbf {L_A}}\), \(\varOmega _\twoheadrightarrow \) and premise sets defined by \(\varGamma ^n_{\mathsf {A}}\) (as shown in Appendix F). Hence, in this case the simple strategy, as we will see, allows for a simplified marking strategy (see Definition 8.3.3) compared to the one for minimal abnormality (which is defined in Sect. 8.3.8, Definition 8.3.4). Of course, due to (\(F\star \)) the semantic selection for the simple strategy can also be characterized as follows: selected are all \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-models of \(\varGamma ^n_{{\mathsf {A}}}\) that validate only those abnormalities in \(\varOmega _\twoheadrightarrow \) that are \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-derivable from \(\varGamma ^n_{{\mathsf {A}}}\) (or equivalently, that are validated by all other \({\mathbf {L_A}}\)-models of \(\varGamma ^n_{{\mathsf {A}}}\)). Note, that in the case that fact (\(F\star \)) does not hold, such models are not guaranteed to exist. See also the discussion in Sect. 2.4.3.

  11. 11.

    The representational results are stated in Sect. 8.4 (see Theorem 8.4.1 and Corollary 8.4.1) and proven in Appendix F.

  12. 12.

    Let for instance \(\varSigma = \bigl \{\{1,2\},\{1,3\}\bigr \}\). Choice sets are \(\{1\}, \{1,2\}, \{1,3\}\), \(\{2,3\}\) and \(\{1,2,3\}\). Minimal are \(\{1\}\) and \(\{2,3\}\).

  13. 13.

    \({\mathsf {F}}\) is considered to be \({\mathbf {LLL}}\)-contingent, i.e., neither \(\vdash \) LLL F nor \(\vdash \) LLL \(\lnot \) F.

  14. 14.

    We have not characterized the marking conditions for minimal abnormality for logics that employ the minimal abnormality strategy for the flat case such as \({\mathbf {AL_2'}}\). They are a straightforward specification of our Definition 8.3.4. See also the characterization of sequential ALs in Chap. 3 where the proof theory is presented in generic terms.

  15. 15.

    As is well-known in the adaptive logic research, in case all minimally abnormal models validate the same set of abnormalities, the minimal abnormality strategy and the simple strategy are equivalent (cf. Footnote 10). See Sect. 2.4.3.

  16. 16.

    In view of our discussion it is straightforward to define the marking conditions for the simple strategy for \(\varOmega _G\) in \({\mathbf {AL_G}}\): A line with condition \(\varDelta \) is marked at stage s if a \(p_i \in \varDelta \cap \varOmega _G\) has been derived at an unmarked line on a condition \(\varDelta ' \subseteq \varOmega _\twoheadrightarrow \).

  17. 17.

    In accordance with Footnote 5, \({\mathbf {AL_S}}\) can easily be shown to be equivalent to \(\langle {\mathbf {L_A}}, [\varOmega _\twoheadrightarrow , \varOmega _S]\), \([\)simple strategy, minimal abnormality strategy\(]\rangle \).

  18. 18.

    The normal selections strategy was first introduced in [37]. See also [38] and Sect. 2.8 for a more elaborated representation. In Sect. 3.4 normal selections are introduced in sequential combinations of ALs and in Sect. 5.7 normal selections are presented in a more general way.

  19. 19.

    Usually the semantic consequence relation has to be defined in terms of equivalence classes of \(\varOmega \)-minimally abnormal \({\mathbf {AL_X}}\)-models. For two \({\mathbf {AL_X}}\)-models \(M \sim N\) iff \(\mathrm Ab ^{{\mathbf {L_X}}}_\varOmega (M) = \mathrm Ab ^{{\mathbf {L_X}}}_\varOmega (N)\). The semantic consequence relation is then defined by \(\varGamma \Vdash _{{\mathbf {AL^n}}} \varphi \) iff there is an \(\varOmega \)-minimally abnormal \({\mathbf {AL_X}}\)-model \(M\) of \(\varGamma \) such that for all \(\varOmega \)-minimally abnormal \({\mathbf {AL_X}}\)-models \(N\) of \(\varGamma \) for which \(N \sim M\), \(N \models _{{\mathbf {L_X}}} \varphi \) (see Definition 2.8.1). However, the nature of our abnormalities and of our premise sets allows for the simplification in Definition 8.5.1 since it can easily be shown that for all AFs \({\mathsf {A}}\) and for all \(\varOmega \)-minimally abnormal \({\mathbf {AL_X}}\)-models of \(\varGamma ^n_{\mathsf {A}}\), \(M\) and \(N\),

    $$\begin{aligned} (M \sim N)\,\text {iff}\,(\text {for all}\,\varphi \in {\mathcal {W}}_n, M\models _{{\mathbf {L_X}}}\varphi \,\text {iff}\,N\models _{{\mathbf {L_X}}}\varphi ) \end{aligned}$$

    The simplification is explicated in a more detailed way in Appendix F.4.

  20. 20.

    In particular they lack e.g. the following properties which hold for ALs in the standard format:

    1. (i)

      fixed-point property – \( Cn _{\mathbf {LLL}}( Cn _{\mathbf {AL}}(\varGamma )) = Cn _{\mathbf {AL}}(\varGamma )\),

    2. (ii)

      closure of the consequence set with respect to the \({\mathbf {LLL}}\)  – \( Cn _{\mathbf {LLL}}( Cn _{\mathbf {AL}}(\varGamma )) = Cn _{\mathbf {AL}}(\varGamma )\),

  21. 21.

    A different meta-level approach is [41]. Here, arguments are presented by propositions and extensions are presented by primitives. The authors in [39] offer, besides the modal systems, also a classical logic meta-level approach (using circumscription).

  22. 22.

    Note that neither of the following is derivable: \(p_1, p_2, \mathop {\mathsf {def}}p_1, \mathop {\mathsf {def}}p_2\).

  23. 23.

    See [42] for different variants of argumentation games proposed for ALs, and for instance [24] for the interpretation of abstract argumentation in form of games.

  24. 24.

    We will present the technical details in a future paper.

References

  1. Straßer, C., Šešelja, D.: Towards the proof-theoretic unification of Dung’s argumentation framework: an adaptive logic approach. J. Logic Comput. 21, 133–156 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Dung, P.M.: On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning and logic programming. In: International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Proceedings, pp. 852–859 (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Dung, P.M.: On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games. Artif. Intell. 77, 321–358 (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bench-Capon, T.J.M., Dunne, P.E.: Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Artif. Intell. 171(10–15), 619–641 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Chesevar, C.I., Maguitman, A.G., Loui, R.P.: Logical models of argument. ACM Comput. Surv. 32(4), 337–383 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Dung, P.M., Son, T.C.: An argumentation-theoretic approach to reasoning with specificity. In: Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR’96). Morgan Kaufmann Publischers, Inc., Cambridge, MA (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kakas, A.C., Toni, F.: Computing argumentation in logic programming. J. Logic Comput. 9(4), 515–562 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Dung, P.M.: An argumentation-theoretic foundation for logic programming. J. Logic Program. 22(2), 151–171 (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Atkinson, K., Bench-Capon, T.J.M.: Legal case-based reasoning as practical reasoning. Artif. Intell. Law 13, 93–131 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Bench-Capon, T.J.M., Atkinson, K., Chorley, A.: Persuasion and value in legal argument. J. Logic Comput. 15, 1075–1097 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Vreeswijk, G.A.W.: Abstract argumentation systems. Artif. Intell. 90, 225–279 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Amgoud, L., Cayrol, C.: On the acceptability of arguments in preference-based argumentation. In: Cooper, G.F., Moral, S. (eds.) UAI, pp. 1–7. Morgan Kaufmann (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bench-Capon, T.J.M.: Value based argumentation frameworks. CoRR cs.AI/0207059 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bench-Capon, T.J.M., Doutre, S., Dunne, P.E.: Audiences in argumentation frameworks. Artif. Intell. 171(1), 42–71 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Perelman, C., Olbrechts-Tyteca, L.: The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation. University of Notre Dame Press, Indiana (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Nielsen, S.H., Parsons, S.: A generalization of Dung’s abstract framework for argumentation: arguing with sets of attacking arguments. In: Maudet, N., Parsons, S., Rahwan, I. (eds.) Argumentation in Multi-Agent Systems. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 4766, pp. 54–73. Springer (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Bondarenko, A., Dung, P.M., Kowalski, R.A., Toni, F.: An abstract, argumentation-theoretic approach to default reasoning. Artif. Intell. 93, 63–101 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Coste-Marquis, S., Devred, C., Konieczny, S., Lagasquie-Schiex, M.C., Marquis, P.: On the merging of dung’s argumentation systems. Artif. Intell. 171, 730–753 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Bench-Capon, T.J.M.: Persuasion in practical argument using value-based argumentation frameworks. J. Logic Comput. 13, 429–448 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Šešelja, D., Straßer, C.: Abstract argumentation and explanation applied to scientific debates. Synthese 190(12), 2195–2217 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Dung, P.M., Mancarella, P., Toni, F.: Computing ideal sceptical argumentation. Artif. Intell. 171, 642–674 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Caminada, M.: Semi-stable semantics. In: Computational Models of Argument, pp. 121–132. IOS Press (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Dunne, P.E., Bench-Capon, T.J.M.: Two party immediate response disputes: properties and efficiency. Artif. Intell. 149(2), 221–250 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Vreeswijk, G.A.W., Prakken, H.: Credulous and Sceptical Argument Games for Preferred Semantics. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 1919, pp. 239–253 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cayrol, C., Doutre, S., Mengin, J.: On decision problems related to the preferred semantics for argumentation frameworks. J. Logic Comput. 13(3), 377–403 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Dung, P.M., Mancarella, P., Toni, F.: Argumentation-based proof procedures for credulous and sceptical non-monotonic reasoning. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol. 2408, pp. 289–310 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Batens, D.: Aspects of the dynamics of discussions and logics handling them. Informal Publication. (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Batens, D., Straßer, C., Verdée, P.: On the transparency of defeasible logics: equivalent premise sets, equivalence of their extensions, and maximality of the lower limit. Logique at Analyse 52(207), 281–304 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Verheij, B.: Two approaches to dialectical argumentation: admissible sets and argumentation stages. In: Proceedings of the Biannual International Conference on Formal and Applied Practical Reasoning (FAPR) Workshop, pp. 357–368 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Amgoud, L., Cayrol, C.: A reasoning model based on the production of acceptable arguments. Ann. Math. Artif. Intell. 34, 197–215 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Modgil, S.: Reasoning about preference in argumentation frameworks. Artif. Intell. 173(9–10), 901–934 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Možina, M., Žabkar, J., Bratko, I.: Argument based machine learning. Artif. Intell. 171(10–15), 922–937 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Falappa, M.A., Kern-Isberner, G., Simari, G.R.: Belief revision and argumentation theory. In: Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence, Chap. 17, pp. 341–360. Springer US (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Amgoud, L., Vesic, S.: On revising argumentation-based decision systems. In: Sossai, C., Chemello, G. (eds.) Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning with Uncertainty, vol. 5590, Chap. 8, pp. 71–82. Springer, Berlin, (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cayrol, C., de Saint-Cyr, F.D., Lagasquie-Schiex, M.C.: Revision of an argumentation system. In: Brewka, G., Lang, J. (eds.) KR, pp. 124–134. AAAI Press (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Batens, D.: A universal logic approach to adaptive logics. Logica Universalis 1, 221–242 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Batens, D.: Towards the unification of inconsistency handling mechanisms. Logic Log. Philos. 8, 5–31 (2000). Appeared 2002

    Google Scholar 

  38. Batens, D., Meheus, J., Provijn, D.: An adaptive characterization of signed systems for paraconsistent reasoning (to appear)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Caminada, M., Gabbay, D.: A logical account of formal argumentation. Studia Logica 93(2), 109–145 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Grossi, D.: Doing argumentation theory in modal logic. Tech. Rep, ILLC Technical Report (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Boella, G., Hulstijn, J., van der Torre, L.W.N.: A logic of abstract argumentation. In: Parsons, S., Maudet, N., Moraitis, P., Rahwan, I. (eds.) Argumentation in Multi-Agent Systems. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 4049, pp. 29–41. Springer (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Batens, D.: Towards a dialogic interpretation of dynamic proofs. In: Dégremont, C., et al. (eds.) Dialogues, Logics and Other Strange Things. Essays in Honour of Shahid Rahman, pp. 27–51. College Publications, London (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Neophytos, D., Antonis, K.: Argumentation with abduction. In: Proceedings of the Fourth Panhellenic Symposium of Logic (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Meheus, J., Batens, D.: A formal logic for abductive reasoning. Logic J. IGPL 14, 221–236 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am thankful to Diderik Batens, Joke Meheus and the anonymous referees of the Journal of Logic and Computation for valuable comments which helped to improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Straßer .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Straßer, C. (2014). Towards the Proof-Theoretic Unification of Dung’s Argumentation Framework: An Adaptive Logic Approach. In: Adaptive Logics for Defeasible Reasoning. Trends in Logic, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-00792-2_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics