Skip to main content

Beltrami’s Models of Non-Euclidean Geometry

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Mathematicians in Bologna 1861–1960

Abstract

In two articles published in 1868 and 1869, Eugenio Beltrami provided three models in Euclidean plane (or space) for non-Euclidean geometry. Our main aim here is giving an extensive account of the two articles’ content. We will also try to understand how the way Beltrami, especially in the first article, develops his theory depends on a changing attitude with regards to the definition of surface. In the end, an example from contemporary mathematics shows how the boundary at infinity of the non-Euclidean plane, which Beltrami made intuitively and mathematically accessible in his models, made non-Euclidean geometry a natural tool in the study of functions defined on the real line (or on the circle).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In a letter to Genocchi in 1868 ([15] p. 578–579), Beltrami says that he had the manuscript of the Saggioready in 1867, but that, faced with criticism from Cremona, he had postponed its publication. After reading Riemann’s Habilitationschrift, he felt confident in submitting the article to the Neapolitan Giornale di matematiche, emended of a statement about three dimensional non-Euclidean geometry and with some integration “which I can hazard now, because substantially agreeing with some of Riemann’s ideas.”

  2. 2.

    In another letter to Genocchi ([15] p. 588), Beltrami writes that this fact clearly follows from his Saggio, and that “in the note of Hoüel I do not find further elements to prove it”. Beltrami being generally rather unassuming about his own work, it is likely that he had already thought of this consequence of his model, but that he thought it prudent to leave it to state explicitely to the reader.

  3. 3.

    Interestingly, the work of Saccheri, which had an indirect role in the development of non-Euclidean geometry and was then forgotten, was re-discovered by Beltrami [10].

  4. 4.

    The obtuse hypothesis holds on a sphere, using geodesics (great circles) as straight lines; but on a sphere we do not have uniqueness of the geodesic through two points. This was considered to be a major problem by Beltrami, who was looking for a geometry in which all principles of Euclidean geometry hold true, but the uniqueness of parallels, but not for Riemann. In the Habilitationschrift, Riemann offered the sphere as a model for a geometry in which no parallel existed. Some of the principles used by Saccheri had to be abandoned: uniqueness of the line through two points, it seemed; but also the infinite extension of lines (Riemann seems to be the first to point out that the right geometric requirement is not that the straight lines have infinite length – what he calls “infinite extent of the line”, translated in “unboundedness” in modern netric space theory –, but that one finds no obstructions while following a straight line – a property he calls “unboundedness”, translated nowadays in “metrically complete and without boundary”). Clifford used the two-to-one covering of the real projective plane by the sphere to exhibit a geometry with positive constant curvature in which (1) there was just one line through two points; (2) space was homogeneous and isotropic; and (3) there are no distinct, parallel straight lines. Kelin realized the role of this model in the discussion of non-Euclidean geometries. Of course, in the projective-space model, often called Riemann’s non-Euclidean geometry, one not only has to give up the infinite extension of straight lines, but also the fact that a line divides the plane into two parts; or, which is about the same, orientability of the plane.

  5. 5.

    This is true also for geodesics not in the form u = constand v = const. See the formulae at p. 381 in the Saggio.

  6. 6.

    This amounts to say that, for each given value of Rthere is, but for isometries, exactly one non-Euclidean plane having “radius of curvature” equal to R(where Ris connected to the universal geometric constants envisioned by Lobachevsky, Bolyai, and Gauss).

  7. 7.

    As a matter of fact, later Hilbert showed that no regular surface in Euclidean three space is isometric to the whole pseudosphere. Much later, Nash showed that any surface can be isometrically imbedded in a Euclidean space having dimension large enough.

  8. 8.

    At this point only I disagree with Gray’s account of Beltrami’s work. He writes, p. 208 in [19]: “...but all Beltrami did was hint that the pseudosphere [the tractroid, in this paper’s terminology] must be cut open before there is any chance of a map between it and the disc [Beltrami’s projective model]”. In fact, Beltrami’s hint at p. 390 follows his formula (12), which can be used to find (after a cut) a surface of revolution in Euclidean space, what we call here S 3. Formula (14) at p. 393 leads to our S 2and, finally, formula (17) at p. 394 leads to the tractroid, our S 1below. The tractrix, called by Beltrami linea dalle tangenti costanti(constant tangent curve) is explicitly mentioned at p. 395. I find it indicative of Beltrami virtuosism, that he managed to exhibit three different surfaces of revolution by using the projective model, which is not especially amenable to this sort of calculations.

  9. 9.

    The main reason for this is that, infinitesimal balls centered at the point (r, 0) in \({\mathbb{B}}_{{\mathbb{C}}^{2}}\)(0 < r < 1), have two (real) large directions and two (real) small directions. Let \(z = x + iy\): end consider (z, 0) in the small ball the x(normal) direction is small exactly as in the Beltrami–Klein model. Due to the holomorphic coupling of the variables in the metric (21), the (tangential) direction yis small as well. We have then two large and one small tangential directions, causing an interesting degeneracy of the metric in the limit.

  10. 10.

    A similar remark is in Teoria, p. 427.

References

  1. Ahlfors, Lars Valerian. 1938. An extension of Schwarz’s lemma. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.43: 3 359–364.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1904. Opere matematiche di Eugenio Beltrami, pubblicate per cura della Facoltà di Scienze dalla Regia Università di Roma. vol. I (1902) vii + 437 p.; vol. II, 468 p., Hoepli: Milano.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1865. Risoluzione del problema: “Riportare i punti di una superficie sopra un piano in modo che le linee geodetiche vengano rappresentate da linee rette”. Ann. Mat. Pura App.I no. 7: 185–204.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1867. Delle variabili complesse sopra una superificie qualunque, Ann. Mat. Pura App.Ser. II vol. I 329–366.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1868. Saggio di interpretazione della geometria non-euclidea, Giornale di Matematiche. VI 284–312; English transl., Essai d’interpretation de la géométrie noneuclidéenne, Annales scientifiques de l’É.N.S. I resérie, 6, 1869, 251–288.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1868–1869. Teoria fondamentale degli spazii di curvatura costante, Ann. Mat. Pura App., Serie II, vol. II, (Unknown Month 1868), 232–255; English transl., Théorie fondamentale des espace de courbure constante, Annales scientifiques de l’É.N.S. I resérie, 6, 1869, 347-375-288.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1871–1873. Osservazione sulla nota del prof. L. Schlaefli alla memoria del sig. Beltrami “Sugli spazi di curvatura costante”. Ann. Mat. Pura Appl.V, 194–198.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1872. Teorema di geometria pseudosferica. Giorn. Mat.X, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1872. Sulla superficie di rotazione che serve di tipo alle superficie pseudosferiche. Giorn. Mat.X, 147–159.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Beltrami, Eugenio. 1889. Un precursore italiano di Legendre e di Lobatschewsky. Rendiconti della R. Accad. dei Lincei, V. I semestre, 441–448.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Bonola, Roberto. 1906. La geometria non-euclidea. Zanichelli: Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Boyer, Carl B. 1959. The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development. Dover Publications, Inc.: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bridson, Martin R. 1999. André, Häfliger, Metric Spaces of Non-Positive Curvature, Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften, Vol. 319, p. Springer: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cannon, James W. Floyd, William J., Kenyon, Richard, Walter R. 1997. Hyperbolic Geometry. Math. Sci. Res. Inst. Publ., Cambridge Univ. Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cicenia, Salvatore. 1989. Le lettere di E. Beltrami ad A. Genocchi sulle geometrie non euclidee. Nuncius, 567–593.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Enriques, Federigo. 1918. Conferenze sulla geometria non-euclidea. Zanichelli: Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hoüel, Jules. 1870. Note sur l’impossibilité de démotrer par une construction plane le principe des parallèles, dit Postulatum d’Euclide, Nouvelles annales de mathématiques 2esérie. tome 9: 93–96.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Gray, Jeremy. 1979. Non-Euclidean geometry: a re-interpretation. Historia Mathematica6: 236–258.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Gray, Jeremy. 2007. Worlds out of nothing: a course in the history of geometry in the 19th Century. Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series. Springer: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Merrick, Teri. 2006. What Frege Meant When He Said: Kant is Right about Geometry. Philophia Math.(III), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Milnor, John. 1982. Hyperbolic Geometry: the first 150 years. Bull. Am. Math. Soc.6: 19–24.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Monge. 1850. Application de l’Analyse à la Géométrie, 5. éd., rev., cor. et annotée par m. Liouville. Bachelier: Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Osserman, Robert. 1999. From Schwarz to Pick to Ahlfors and beyond. Notices Amer. Math. Soc.46: no. 8, 868–873.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Pick, Georg. 1915. Über eine Eigenschaft der konformen Abbildung kreisförmiger Bereiche. Math. Ann.77: 1 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Poincaré, Henri. 1882. Théorie des groupes Fuchsiens. Acta Math.1: 1 1–76.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Riemann, Bernhard. 1873. Ueber die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen, Abhandlungen der Kniglichen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, 13, 1867, On the Hypotheses which lie at the Bases of Geometry, Nature, no. VIII, 183: 14–17.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Scanlan, Michael J. 1988. Beltrami’s Model and the Independance of the Parallel Postulate. Hist. Philos. Logic, 9: no. 1, 13–34.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Winger, R.M. 1925. Gauss and non-Euclidean geometry. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.31: 7 356–358.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicola Arcozzi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Basel AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Arcozzi, N. (2012). Beltrami’s Models of Non-Euclidean Geometry. In: Coen, S. (eds) Mathematicians in Bologna 1861–1960. Birkhäuser, Basel. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-0348-0227-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics