Skip to main content

G. Santayana (Scepticism and Animal Faith, 1923) and E. Husserl (Cartesianische Meditationen, 1929), Readers of R. Descartes

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Companion to George Santayana’s Scepticism and Animal Faith

Part of the book series: Palgrave Companions ((PC))

  • 31 Accesses

Abstract

Moreno shows that Santayana believed he had found an ally regarding his doctrine of essence in the philosophy of Husserl. He then reveals the parallels and differences between Santayana’s and Husserl’s philosophies, bringing each thinker’s ideas into sharper relief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Max H. Fisch included Santayana in Classic American Philosophers: Peirce, James, Royce, Santayana, Dewey, Whitehead (1951), and Alfonso López Quintás included him in Filosofía española contemporánea (1970). These pioneers were joined by John J. Stuhr, who included Santayana alongside Charles S. Peirce, William James, Josiah Royce, John Dewey, and Herbert Mead in Classical American Philosophy: Essential Readings and Interpretative Essays (1987), and José Luis Abellán, who included Santayana in the monumental Historia crítica del pensamiento español (1989). More recently, Professor Manuel Garrido gave him a place of honor in El legado filosófico y científico del siglo XX (2007) and, together with Miguel de Unamuno and José Ortega y Gasset, in El legado filosófico español e hispanoamericano del siglo XX (2009).

  2. 2.

    Cf. The Philosophy of M. Henri Bergson and The Philosophy of Mr. Bertrand Russell (WD, 58–109, 110–154); Postscript (Santayana 1927, 171–174).

  3. 3.

    See also Beltrán Llavador (2002), 178–180.

  4. 4.

    “If anyone reading our statements objects that they mean changing all the world into a subjective illusion and committing onself to a ‘Berkeleyan idealism,’ we can only answer that he has not seized upon the sense of those statements. They take nothing away from the fully valid being of the world as the all of realities, just as nothing is taken away from the fully valid geometrical being of the square by denying that the square is round (a denial admittedly based, in this case, on what is immediately obvious)” (Husserl 1983, 129).

  5. 5.

    Cf. Flamm (2021).

  6. 6.

    The congress was attended by three hundred philosophers, among them: W. Windelband, J. Royce, Xavier Léon, B. Croce, É. Boutroux, and H. Münsterberg. Germany was the most represented country and the main topics were logic, epistemology, history of philosophy, ethics, and politics; less coverage was given to aesthetics and the philosophy of religion (cf. Fullerton 1908). Compare this with today’s world congresses.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Moreno (2017).

  8. 8.

    These four meditations were not published until 1931, in the French translation, Méditations cartésiennes. For this edition, the famous, and lengthy, “Fifth Meditation” was added, where Husserl defends himself against solipsistic criticism by explaining—rightly, in my opinion—that only a cursory reader could have taken his transcendental idealism to be Berkeleyan idealism.

  9. 9.

    A comparison of Husserl’s Ideen and later Cartesianische Meditationen reveals two reformulations: (1) In CM phenomenology is no longer defined as the science of essences, since Husserl uses essence in its Aristotelian sense; hence the terms eidos (pure eidetic phenomenology, eidetic analysis), cogitationes, and cogitatum qua cogitatum come to the fore; (2) CM constantly alludes to the correlate between the transcendental-eidetic sphere and the empirical-factual sphere both in the mind and in the world, including therein the human being as a psycho-physical, social, and cultural entity, which is never called into question. In this way, CM insists on distancing itself from Berkeleyan idealism by never overlooking the empirical-factual sphere.

  10. 10.

    For the different meanings of the important word “is,” see Santayana (1924).

  11. 11.

    Furthermore, in the “Author’s Preface to the English Edition” of Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, Husserl referred to those who had fallen into the same trap by alluding, without naming names, to his favourite but already wayward pupil, Martin Heidegger, and describing him as an anthropologist (Husserl 1931, 16). Indeed, in his similarly incomplete Being and Time (1927), Heidegger had applied the phenomenological method to describe the existential structures of his life as an example of a human being in the world, of his own space and time; whereas Husserl sought to describe the general structures of the human mind, those that make humanity as a whole distinctive in the universe. Husserl had aspirations for a general science, while Heidegger devoted his efforts to knowledge that was merely regional—and with an expiry date.

Abbreviations

CM:

(Cartesian Meditations)

Ideen:

(Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie)

SAF:

(Scepticism and Animal Faith)

References

  • Beltrán Llavador, J. 2002. Celebrar el mundo. Introducción al pensar nómada de George Santayana. Valencia, Spain: PUV, Biblioteca Javier Coy d’estudis nord-americans. Segunda edición en 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flamm, M. 2021. Santayana’s Ambassador. Limbo. Boletín internacional de estudios sobre Santayana 41: 131–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fullerton, G. 1908. The Meeting of the Third International Congress of Philosophy, at Heidelberg, August 31 to September 5, 1908. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 5 (21,Oct. 8): 573–577.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1931. Author Preface to the English Edition. In Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology (1913), translated by W. R. Boyce Gibson, London: George Allen & Unwin/New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1960. Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology. Translated by Dorion Cairns. The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy (1913), translated by F. Kersten. The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. This edition does not include the “Author’s Preface to the English Edition” (1931).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kremplewska, K. 2019. Life as Insinuation. George Santayana’s Hermeneutics of Finite Life and Human Self. Albany, New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovely, E.W. 2012. George Santayana’s Philosophy of Religion: His Roman Catholic Influences and Phenomenolopy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, D. 2017. Gnoseología Cartesiana. Laguna. Revista de filosofía 40: 51–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santayana, G. 1913. Winds of Doctrine. Studies in Contemporary Opinion. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1915. Philosophical Heresy. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 12 (21, Oct. 14): 561–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1923. Scepticism and Animal Faith. Introduction to a System of Philosophy. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1924. Some Meanings of the Word ‘is’. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 21 (14, Jul. 3): 365–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1927. The Realm of Essence. Book First of Realms of Being. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1942. Realms of Being. One-Volume Edition, with a New Introduction by the Author. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. The Letters of George Santayana. Book Three (1921–1927). Edited by William G. Holzberger. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Recently Discovered Letters of George Santayana/ Cartas recién descubiertas de George Santayana, bilingual edition by Daniel Pinkas, with a Presentation by José Beltrán, and translated by Daniel Moreno. Valencia, Spain: PUV, Biblioteca Javier Coy d’estudis nord-americans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. 1960. Excursus: Santayana’s Ultimate Scepticism Compared With Husserl’s Phenomenological Reduction. In The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, 2 vols., Springer-Science, vol. I, 138–139.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Moreno .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Moreno, D. (2024). G. Santayana (Scepticism and Animal Faith, 1923) and E. Husserl (Cartesianische Meditationen, 1929), Readers of R. Descartes. In: Coleman, M.A., Tiller, G. (eds) The Palgrave Companion to George Santayana’s Scepticism and Animal Faith. Palgrave Companions. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-46367-9_19

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics