Skip to main content

Remote Encounters of a Distant Kind: Natives and Westerners in Adam Smith’s International Thought

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
British Modern International Thought in the Making

Part of the book series: International Political Theory ((IPoT))

  • 51 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter Laurie Bréban and Jean Dellemotte explain how Adam Smith understood the differences and relations between indigenous peoples and Westerners. The authors demonstrate the unity and the ambiguities in Smith’s views of natives and Westerners as presented in his international thought. In doing so, they investigate Smith’s economic thought and moral philosophy and bring new light to his relation to colonialism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    WN henceforth.

  2. 2.

    For instance, Hébert (1996, 74), Mizuta (1996, 57), Skinner (1996, 115) and Winch (1996, 40).

  3. 3.

    See Corr, Letter 149, 185–186.

  4. 4.

    According to Mizuta (1996, 57).

  5. 5.

    See Corr, Letter 208, 251.

  6. 6.

    “The colonial project as such is the most spectacular expression of the mercantile system”, Diatkine (1996, 25). See also Winch (1996, 45).

  7. 7.

    See particularly Clary and Hill (1990), Skinner (1996) and Hébert (1996).

  8. 8.

    See Diatkine (1996), Clary and Hill (1990, 49), Hébert (1996, 83), Skinner (1996, 122–123) and Winch (1996, 41).

  9. 9.

    “The New World was (…) something difficult to locate within the received worldview”, Cremaschi (2017, 15).

  10. 10.

    See Marouby (2004, 242–244) on bibliographical sources which Smith relied on. According to Rothschild (2012, 193–194) Smith was “surrounded (…) by families with commercial and colonial connections”.

  11. 11.

    TMS henceforth.

  12. 12.

    LJ (Lectures on Jurisprudence) or LRBL (Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres) henceforth.

  13. 13.

    See, for example, Montesquieu’s De l’esprit des lois (1748), Hume’s essay Of National Characters (1753), Voltaire’s Essai sur les mœurs et l'esprit des nations (1756), Ferguson’s Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767) or Roberston’s History of America (1777). For a broader discussion of the different depictions of the Natives that emerges from these works, see Dellemotte (2021).

  14. 14.

    WN, I.i.11, 24.

  15. 15.

    See Montesquieu (1748, XX, 1–2).

  16. 16.

    WN, II.iv.4, 412.

  17. 17.

    LRBL, ii.115, 137.

  18. 18.

    Too many authors might be evoked here. Among the most renowned, see Voltaire (1756, introd., sect. 3: “most Negroes, all the Cafris, are immersed in the same stupidity, and will languish there for a long time”), Kant (1764, 61) or Hume (1753, 208, 629–630).

  19. 19.

    “Nature and the climate rule almost alone over the savages” (Montesquieu 1748, XIX.4). Among the disseminators of the climate theory in the eighteenth century, see, apart from Montesquieu, Jean-Baptiste Dubos’ Réflexions critiques sur la poésie et sur la peinture (1712) and John Arbuthnot’s Essay Concerning the Effects of Air on Human Bodies (1733). Buffon also transposes the climate theory into the field of his Natural History (1749–1804) to explain the variety of human phenotypes.

  20. 20.

    WN, introduction, 11.

  21. 21.

    WN, I.iii, 31.

  22. 22.

    See “Early Draft of the WN”, LJ, 583.

  23. 23.

    See the example of rural dwellers (WN, I.i, 18–19).

  24. 24.

    EPS, 48. This essay was published posthumously, but in all likelihood written before the TMS. See Wightman (1980, 5–11).

  25. 25.

    On Smith's historical discourse, see Meek (1976, 99–130) or Marouby (2004).

  26. 26.

    Hunting, pasturage, agriculture and commerce. On the four stages theory, see Meek (1976)’s classical study.

  27. 27.

    About this paradox, see Marouby (2004, 154–159).

  28. 28.

    See Pitts (2005, 29, 34).

  29. 29.

    See Pitts (2005, 28) and Hill (2010, 465).

  30. 30.

    This point has been stressed by early commentators such as Dugald Stewart (1854, 69–70) as well as more recent ones like Rothschild (2012, 196) or Cremaschi (2017, 16–17).

  31. 31.

    WN, V.i.f, 781–782.

  32. 32.

    Forman-Barzilai (2006, 111) considers Smith’s view to be “pluralist” rather than relativist.

  33. 33.

    “Early Draft of part of WN”, LJ, 563–564.

  34. 34.

    Ibid., 564.

  35. 35.

    LJ(B), 326–330, 538–540.

  36. 36.

    See Smith’s diatribe on the deleterious effects of the technical division of labour in WN (V.i.f.50, 781–782).

  37. 37.

    “Humanity is the virtue of a woman, generosity of a man”, TMS, VI.2.10, 190.

  38. 38.

    TMS, V.2.9, 204–205.

  39. 39.

    See Cremaschi (2017, 20–21, 25).

  40. 40.

    See Cremaschi (2017, 23) and Pitts (2005, 25).

  41. 41.

    As Pitts (2005, 36) and Cremaschi (2017, 23–24, 32) judiciously point out, Smith’s distinction between both set of virtues does not amount to saying that savages are altogether incapable of sympathy and of the desire to get other people’s approval, but rather that virtues and characters expressing self-command are more valued in a savage society than virtues and characters expressing sensitivity.

  42. 42.

    WN, V.i.f.59, 786–787; LJ(B), 331–333, 540–541 (“Another bad effect of commerce is that it sinks the courage of mankind, and tends to extinguish martial spirit”, 540).

  43. 43.

    LJ, 339, 540 & 563.

  44. 44.

    As French translators of the TMS notice, this moral critique of slavery contrasts with the essentially economic critique found in the WN. On Smith’s position towards slavery, see Salter (1996) and Lapidus (2002).

  45. 45.

    According to Pitts (2005, 25), Smith has a “respectful posture toward non-European societies he regarded as being in earlier stages of development” and his moral theory “encourages open-mindedness toward unfamiliar values and practices” (43); “Smith is less ethnocentric than most contemporaries”, Cremaschi (2017, 24).

  46. 46.

    Montesquieu (1748, XIV.2).

  47. 47.

    Ibid., XVIII.9.

  48. 48.

    See the famous episode of the slave of Surinam in chapter 19 of Candide (1759).

  49. 49.

    Smith's close friend Hume (1753, 214) also tended to blame African people for the slave trade.

  50. 50.

    TMS, V.2.13, 209.

  51. 51.

    See Pitts (2005, 48–49).

  52. 52.

    WN, V.i.a, 689–708.

  53. 53.

    WN, IV.vii.b.7, 568.

  54. 54.

    WN, V.i.a.9, 694–695; V.i.a.15, 697.

  55. 55.

    See, for instance, WN, V.i.a.19, 698.

  56. 56.

    While Smith considers that specialization in most occupations “is not originally the effect of any human wisdom” (WN, I.ii.1, 25), he believes that the state must intentionally make soldiering a specific occupation (WN, V.i.a.14, 697).

  57. 57.

    WN, V.i.a.39, 705–706.

  58. 58.

    We think particularly of works supposing that a “failure” of the system of sympathy to account for an ideal moral society would have gradually led Smith to an economic treatment of the social question—most notably in France, Dumont (1977, 83–93) and Diatkine (1991) who later changed his mind on the subject. Conversely, we consider that Smith’s moral philosophy is essentially positive, and that the principle of sympathy allows him to account for the genealogy of the moral world as well as its imperfection and corruption.

  59. 59.

    We endorse T.D. Campbell's (1971) classic study on the subject. See Smith’s clarification (TMS, II.i.5.9, 77).

  60. 60.

    See Pitts (2005, 15–16), Forman-Barzilai (2006, 96) and Hill (2010, 471).

  61. 61.

    On the subject, see the balanced analysis of Forman-Barzilai (2006) and Fleischacker (2011).

  62. 62.

    See TMS, V.2.1, 200.

  63. 63.

    See Fleischacker (2011, 40).

  64. 64.

    See Diatkine (2019, 123–137).

  65. 65.

    WN, IV.vii.a.1–4, 556–558.

  66. 66.

    WN, IV.vii.a.4, 558.

  67. 67.

    Ibid., 562.

  68. 68.

    It seems to have been the case in France, since chapter IV, vii. was translated by Elie-Salomon-François Reverdil and published separately in 1778 under the title “Fragment sur les colonies”, before any complete French translation of the book was available. Regarding Britain, Rothschild (2012, 193–194) recalls that “the earliest publications that were actually about Smith were concerned, in general, with his writings on empire”.

  69. 69.

    Williams (2014, 288). Rothschild (2012, 188) conversely highlights “Smith’s diatribes against colonial oppression” and sees them “at the very center of his concerns”. As summarized by Hill (2010, 454), “Smith did not neglect the moral aspects and there are many references to the injustices of empire”.

  70. 70.

    LRBL, ii. 133, 146.

  71. 71.

    WN, IV.vii.a.9, 560.

  72. 72.

    WN, IV.vii.a.14, 561.

  73. 73.

    WN, IV.vii.b.2, 564.

  74. 74.

    Among these, Smith highlights moderate taxes and two arrangements likely to promote an efficient distribution of land: a low prevalence of primogeniture and the obligation for each landowner to improve and cultivate a certain proportion of his land, in order to limit the grabbing of uncultivated land.

  75. 75.

    WN.IV.vii.c.79, 625–626.

  76. 76.

    “According to the natural course of things (…) the greater part of the capital of every growing society is, first, directed to agriculture, afterwards to manufactures, and last of all to foreign commerce”, a natural order of investments which was subverted in Europe (WN, III.i.8–9, 380).

  77. 77.

    See Ince (2021, 1080, 1088, 1091).

  78. 78.

    Ibid., 1088–1092. Ince also puts forward the Lockean argument according to which the occupation of land in a country where it was abundantly available did not infringe the Native’s natural rights.

  79. 79.

    WN, IV.vii.b.7, 568.

  80. 80.

    Given that, for reasons seen above, savage nations are less populated than nations of higher historical stages.

  81. 81.

    History has shown that this was indeed the case, as the slaughter of bison was deliberately used in the nineteenth century as a means of depriving Indians of their main source of food and forcing them onto reservations. In an abundant literature, see for example Smits (1994) and Scott Taylor (2011).

  82. 82.

    “In North America, again, where the age of hunters subsists (…) as there is almost no property amongst them, the only injury that can be done is the depriving them of their game”, LJ(A), i.33, 16.

  83. 83.

    See TMS, II.i.5, 74–78.

  84. 84.

    WN, IV.vii.b.60, 589, our italics.

  85. 85.

    Ibid., IV.vii.b.61.

  86. 86.

    See Locke (1690, 2nd treatise, chap. V) (“Of property”). On the relationship between the colonial context and Locke's theory of property, see Hulme (1990), Tully (1993, 137–176) or Armitage (2004).

  87. 87.

    As editors of the LJ recall, Smith’s explanation of the right to property by occupation is intended as an alternative to Locke’s argument (Meek et al. 1978, 33). See LJ(A), i.35–44, 16–20.

  88. 88.

    WN, IV.vii.c.80, 626. As noted by Rothschild (2012, 195–196), Smith here seriously tempers the enthusiasm displayed by Raynal in his Histoire des deux Indes.

  89. 89.

    See Pitts (2005, 55–56).

  90. 90.

    WN, V.vii.c.101, 636.

  91. 91.

    WN, IV.v.b.6, 527. On this subject, see Bouillot and Diatkine (2017, 111–114).

  92. 92.

    It is noteworthy to observe that this condemnation of the deleterious effects of colonization does not begin with the writing of the WN. In the first and subsequent editions of the TMS, Smith already denounced the Westerners’ attitude towards Africa and their commitment in the slave trade (see TMS, V.2.9, 206–207).

  93. 93.

    See Hébert (1996, 79–80) and Clary and Hill (1990, 46–47).

  94. 94.

    WN, IV.i.32, 448.

  95. 95.

    WN, V.i.a.5, 691–692.

  96. 96.

    WN, IV.vii.c.100, 634.

  97. 97.

    As historian Eric Williams (1944, 10) summarized, “slavery was not born of racism: rather, racism was the consequence of slavery”. As far as philosophers and scholars are concerned, besides Smith, Ferguson (1767) or Rousseau’s (1755) comprehensive discourses, prominent figures of eighteenth-century intellectual life regrettably committed in degrading comparisons and suppositions. Hence Hume (1753, 208) comparing Francis Williams (c. 1700–1770)—a Jamaican born scholar of his time—to a parrot, or Voltaire (1756, introd., sect. 2) assuming sexual intercourse between tropical inhabitants and apes.

  98. 98.

    TMS, VII.ii.1.44, 292. See Hill (2010, 456) and Forman-Barzilai (2006, 391).

  99. 99.

    TMS, i.i.4.9, 23.

  100. 100.

    This is the reason why Smith rejected Stoic cosmopolitanism as being « altogether different» from « the plan and system which Nature has sketched out for our conduct» (TMS, VI I.ii.1.43, 292). See Forman-Barzilai (2000, 393–400), who goes as far as to conclude that Smith theorized “a world without sympathy” (ibid., 392–393).

  101. 101.

    LJ(A), iii. 105–111, 182–185.

  102. 102.

    Smith explains this difference by the greater profitability of the West Indian sugar trade compared to the cultivation of corn in which American planters are chiefly involved. On the relationship between profitability and the treatment of slaves in Smith, see Lapidus (2002, 62–65).

  103. 103.

    Ibid., 183.

  104. 104.

    “They will eat at the same table, work together, and be cloathed in the same manner, and will be alike in every other particular”, ibid., 184.

  105. 105.

    LJ(A), iii. 110, 184–185.

  106. 106.

    LJ(A), iii.108–109, 184 (“Those persons most excite our compassion and are most apt to affect our sympathy who most resemble ourselves, and the greater the difference the less we are affected by them”).

  107. 107.

    See Forman-Barzilai (2006, 100).

  108. 108.

    See LJ(A), iii.114, 186; iii.130, 192; WN, III.ii.10, 388. Smith also speaks of love of “authority” (LJ(A), iii.114, 186; iii.130, 192) or “tyrannizing” (LJ(A), iii.114, 186).

  109. 109.

    See LJ(A), iii.116–117, 187. On the conditions for the abolition of slavery according to Smith, see Lapidus (2002).

  110. 110.

    See LJ(A), vi. 56–57, 352; LJ(B), 222, 494.

  111. 111.

    On how this fits into Smith's critique of the colonies, see Pitts (2005, 54–55).

  112. 112.

    Strictly speaking, Smith does not use the term “pride” in this context, but “love of our nation” (TMS, VI.ii.2.3, 228), which is not a reprehensible sentiment in itself but whose excess can lead to “savage patriotism” or to “national prejudices and hatreds” (TMS, VI.ii.2.3–5, 228–229). On patriotism in Smith, see Forman-Barzilai (2000, 407–410) and Hill (2010, 460–461).

  113. 113.

    WN, IV.vii.c.79, 625–626.

Bibliography

  • Armitage, D. 2004. John Locke, Carolina and the Two Treatises of Government. Political Theory 32 (5): 602–627.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonar, J. 1894. A Catalogue of the Library of Adam Smith. London: Macmillan & co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouillot, C., and Diatkine D. 2017. Le « système de la liberté naturelle » face aux partisans du système mercantile. Qui sont les adversaires de Smith ? Cahiers d’économie politique 73: 91–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bréban L., Denieul S., and Sultan E., eds. 2021. La Science des mœurs au siècle des lumières. Conception et expérimentations. Paris: Classiques Garnier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, T.D. 1971. Adam Smith’s Science of Morals. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Célimène, F., and Legris A., eds. 2002. L’Économie de l’Esclavage Colonial. Paris: CNRS Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clary, B.J., and Hill, L.E. 1990. Adam Smith on Colonies: An Analytical and Historical Interpretation. Forum for Social Economics 19: 45–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cremaschi, S. 2017. Adam Smith on Savages. Revue de philosophie économique 18 (1): 13–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dellemotte, J. 2005. Sympathie, désir d’améliorer sa condition et penchant à l’échange. Cahiers d’économie politique 48: 51–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. La figure du sauvage dans la science des mœurs des XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles, du racisme au relativisme. In ed. L. Bréban, S. Denieul and E. Sultan, 155–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diatkine, D. 1991/1776. Présentation. In Smith, 9–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Adam Smith et le projet colonial ou l'avenir d'une illusion. Cahiers d'économie politique 27–28: 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Adam Smith. La découverte du capitalisme et de ses limites. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumont, L. 1977. Homo aequalis I, genèse et épanouissement de l’idéologie économique. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferguson, A. 1782/1767. An Essay on the History of Civil Society, 5th ed. London: T. Cadell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleischacker, S. 2011. Adam Smith and Cultural Relativism. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 4 (2): 20–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forman-Barzilai, F. 2000. Adam Smith as a Globalisation Theorist. Critical Review 14 (4): 391–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Smith on ‘Connexion’, Culture and Judgment. In Montes and Schliesser, 89–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hébert, R.F. 1996. Adam Smith and the Political Economy of American Independence. Cahiers d’économie politique 27–28: 73–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, L. 2010. Adam Smith’s Cosmopolitanism: The Expanding Circles of Commercial Strangership. History of Political Thought 31 (3): 449–473.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, T. 2013. Adam Smith on American Economic Development and the Future of the European Atlantic Empires. In ed. Reinert and Røge, 53–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulme, P. 1990. The Spontaneous Hand of Nature: Savagery, Colonialism and the Enlightenment. In ed. Hulme and Jordanova, 16–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulme, P., and L. Jordanova, eds. 1990. The Enlightenment and Its Shadows. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1987/1753. Of National Characters, in Essays, Moral, Political and Literary, 197–215. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ince, O. I. 2021. Adam Smith, Settler Colonialism, and Limits of Liberal Anti-imperialism. The Journal of Politics 83 (3): 1080–1096.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, E. 2011/1764. Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime and Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, J. 2017. Population Growth, the Settlement Process and Economic Progress: Adam Smith's Theory of Demo-Economic Development. PhD dissertation in economics, Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lapidus, A. 2002. Le profit ou la domination: la figure de l’esclave dans l’économie d’Adam Smith. In ed. Célimène & Legris, 47–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, T.J. 2000. Persuasion, Domination and Exchange: Adam Smith on the Political Consequences of Markets. Canadian Journal of Political Science 33 (2): 273–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1970/1690. Two Treatises on Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marouby, C. 2004. L’économie de la nature. Essai sur Adam Smith et l’anthropologie de la croissance. Paris, Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meek, R. L. 1976. Social Science and the Ignoble Savage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meek, R. L., Raphael, D.D., and Stein, P.G. . 1978. Introduction. In ed. Smith, 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizuta, H. 1996. Kaleidoscope of the Colonial Discussion. Cahiers d’économie politique 27–28: 57–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montes, L., and Schliesser E., eds. 2006. New Voices on Adam Smith. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montesquieu. 1832/1748. De l’esprit des lois, 3 volumes. Paris: Pourrat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muthu, S., ed. 2012. Empire and Modern Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitts, J. 2005. A Turn to Empire. The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinert, S. A., and Røge, P., eds. 2013. The Political Economy of Empire in the Early Modern World. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, E. 2012. Adam Smith and the British Empire. In ed. Muthu, 184–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. 1995/1755. Discours sur l'origine et les fondements de l'inégalité parmi les hommes. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salter, J. 1996. Adam Smith on Slavery. History of Economic Ideas 4 (1–2): 225–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott Taylor, M. 2011. Buffalo Hunt: International Trade and the Virtual Extinction of the North American Bison. The American Economic Review 101 (7): 3162–3195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, A. S. 1996. Adam Smith: The Demise of the Colonial Relationship with America. Cahiers d'économie politique, 27–28, 113–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1976a/1759. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1976b/1776. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Correspondence of Adam Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Lectures on Jurisprudence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980/1795. Essays on Philosophical Subjects. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991/1776. Recherche sur la nature et les causes de la richesse des nations, trans. G. Garnier. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smits, D. D. 1994. The Frontier Army and the Destruction of the Buffalo: 1865–1883. The Western Historical Quarterly 25 (3): 312–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, D. 1854. Collected Works. Edinburgh: T. Constable and co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tully, J. 1993. An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts, 137–176. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire. 1829/1756. Essai sur les mœurs et l'esprit des nations. Paris: Lefèvre, Werdet & Lequien fils.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wightman, W.P.D. 1980/1795. Introduction. In ed. Smith, 5–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, D. 2014. Adam Smith and Colonialism. Journal of International Political Theory 10 (3): 283–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, E. 1944. Capitalism and Slavery. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, D. 1996. Adam Smith’s Politique Coloniale. Cahiers d’économie politique 27–28: 39–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wyatt-Walter, A. 1996. Adam Smith and the Liberal Tradition in International Relations. Review of International Studies 22 (1): 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Laurie Bréban or Jean Dellemotte .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bréban, L., Dellemotte, J. (2024). Remote Encounters of a Distant Kind: Natives and Westerners in Adam Smith’s International Thought. In: Bourcier, B., Jakonen, M. (eds) British Modern International Thought in the Making. International Political Theory. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-45713-5_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics