Keywords

5.1 Introduction

Conducting research during epidemics is of critical importance. Yet, owing to practical constraints, time pressures, uncertainty, the importance of flexibility, and the potential for research to detract from epidemic response, the ways in which research is conducted in this context may warrant adaptations or adaptive designs.

Adapting research entails choosing different research designs or methods if research goals, contexts or constraints warrant or necessitate a different approach. For example, as Case 5.1 illustrates, researchers who initially planned to conduct research involving face-to-face interaction to generate data may have to instead adopt remote forms of data generation, owing to epidemic-related risks and measures that restrict mobility. And as Cases 5.2 and 5.3 highlight, failing to adapt and instead pausing research, given the challenges presented by an epidemic, may have negative impacts on research participants.

Adaptive research, by contrast, is a type of research that prospectively plans for modifications after research has been initiated, while maintaining the validity and integrity of the research (Mahajan and Gupta 2010). For instance, research may be designed with a plan to revisit the treatments under study, the treatment doses, the sample size, and so forth (Pallmann et al. 2018). Case 5.4 provides a nice example of adaptive research via the RECOVERY Trial, wherein study arms were added when there was reason to believe an intervention offered a benefit or removed when sufficient data had been collected to establish that an intervention was associated with a lack of benefit. And Case 5.5 highlights the possible implications of not using an adaptive research design in the context of evolving scientific evidence.

While adaptation and adaptive designs introduce an important degree of flexibility to research conducted during epidemics and help to address research objectives and constraints, this does not mean that “anything goes”. Scientific rigour and validity, in addition to adherence to universally accepted ethical standards, remain essential. Consequently, important ethical questions exist regarding the conditions that justify adaptations to research, the kinds of adaptive research designs that can be ethically justified, and how ethics review bodies ought to evaluate such novel approaches to research in epidemic contexts.

5.2 Adapting – Not Deviating From – Scientific and Ethical Standards for Research

If epidemic contexts sometimes warrant or necessitate that research be adapted or adaptive, does this mean that exceptions should be made to the scientific and ethical standards that otherwise govern research? Such standards include both scientific standards, such as those commonly used for participant selection, sample size estimation and sample size allocation, as well as ethical standards, such as those governing the ethics review and informed consent processes (see Chap. 6).

London and Kimmelman argue that the challenges that rigorous scientific methods are designed to address do not disappear during public health emergencies like epidemics, nor do researchers’ obligations to align the conduct of their research with the public interest or to protect the interests of research participants, both of which are advanced by research ethics standards and regulations (London and Kimmelman 2020). In other words, they argue that “the moral mission of research remains the same: to reduce uncertainty and enable caregivers, health systems, and policy-makers to better address individual and public health” (p. 476). Consequently, while accepted ethical and scientific standards should be interpreted in light of, and adapted in response to, particular circumstances and contexts in epidemics, the aim must still be to generate the best possible evidence about important questions. Adaptive research designs and adaptations to research therefore do not sidestep the need for rigorous scientific evaluation and adherence to universal ethical standards and must be explicitly ethically justified and reviewed through transparent and inclusive processes.

The evidence base can evolve rapidly during an epidemic. Researchers and those charged with reviewing ongoing studies (e.g. research ethics committees) therefore have a responsibility to monitor emerging evidence from other research initiatives, review the implications for the studies they are leading or overseeing and decide whether those studies should be continued, modified, suspended or cancelled, in order that they continue only if they have scientific and social value and so that people are not asked to participate in research that is no longer likely to produce meaningful results or which poses risks without the prospect of benefit (PAHO 2020). In other words, the justification and ethical acceptability of research can vary throughout its duration as a result of rapidly evolving evidence. Decision-making in this context can be particularly challenging as evidence may be uncertain or contested. Consequently, the intervals at which studies are reviewed and report to research oversight bodies ought to be shorter and more frequent during an epidemic. Researchers should also develop plans that account for how their study might be affected by new evidence or adapted in response to it.

The Nuffield Council on Bioethics (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2020, pxxii) raises two key questions that they suggest ought to be asked when considering adaptations to standard research procedures during public health emergencies, like epidemics:

Is this the right study for this location and this population/subpopulation? Who has been involved in identifying and characterising the problem that the research seeks to answer? Will local populations benefit from any positive findings?

Is this the right design for this location and this population? How have local needs, concerns or preferences been taken into account?

Following on from these questions, the Council offers two recommendations:

Study protocols should be developed with the input of local communities before being finalised, in order to ensure that proposed procedures are acceptable to communities, as well as meeting ethical requirements. Even in multi-site trials, there will be elements that can and should be operationalised differently in different sites in response to engagement and feedback.

Any exclusion criteria from studies should be clearly justified with reference to the risks and benefits for the group in question, in this context, rather than an automatic exclusion of ‘vulnerable groups’.

5.3 Adaptive Clinical Trials

Adaptive clinical trials (ACTs) are a particularly salient type of adaptive research that may be considered during epidemics. For instance, the magnitude and high case fatality rate of the 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease (EVD) epidemic in West Africa prompted calls for the accelerated evaluation and development of investigational therapeutic interventions that had shown promising results in the laboratory and in animal models. In response, a World Health Organization ethics advisory panel concluded that it was ethical to offer investigational agents with the intent to treat those suffering from EVD, and that a moral duty existed to evaluate these interventions in the best possible clinical studies (WHO 2014); however, it was unclear what the ethical requirements were for the appropriate design of such investigations. Proponents of placebo-controlled randomized controlled trials (RCTs), for instance, argued that these designs ought to be used as they were best able to generate robust, statistically valid evidence about safety and efficacy, which could be used to ensure all patients receiving treatment after the trial received the safest and most effective intervention (Joffe 2014). On the other hand, proponents of ACTs argued that ACTs would be preferable as they better allow for emerging, accumulated data to be used to rapidly identify and deploy beneficial new therapies to improve outcomes among trial participants (Adebamowo et al. 2014).

The principal argument favouring the conduct of placebo-controlled RCTs in the context of epidemics and other public health emergencies is that one ought to collect the best possible evidence in order to develop the safest and most effective intervention, and that a placebo-controlled RCT is the most appropriate, and perhaps morally obligatory, method of achieving this goal. The principal argument favouring the conduct of ACTs in the context of epidemics and other public health emergencies is that, owing to the severity and urgency present during epidemics, in addition to the higher fatality rates associated with conventional, supportive care in the absence of effective therapies, one should give greater weight to the well-being of the patients affected and therefore favour ACTs, given their ability to adapt to emerging evidence of treatment safety and efficacy (Singh 2023). Table 5.1 outlines the key relative merits of RCTs and ACTs, as well as the ethical considerations regarding each, in order to elucidate the potential value, as well as the potential pitfalls, of conducting ACTs during an epidemic.

Table 5.1 Relative merits of RCTs and ACTs and ethical considerations regarding each type of trial

5.4 Adapting Research to Epidemic Contexts

The ethical appropriateness of any research design should to some extent be informed by the context in which the research is to be conducted (Pullman and Wang 2001). That is, it has been argued that methodological orthodoxy ought to be eschewed in order to critically consider the research context, background information, risks of the research and the most appropriate means of answering specific research questions and achieving stated goals (Pullman and Wang 2001; Cartwright 2007; Ezeome and Simon 2010). Appreciating the motivations for and principal objectives of conducting clinical trials in the context of an epidemic may, at least in part, be instructive of which trial design ought to be favoured, and whether adaptations are ethically justifiable (if not ethically obligatory). For example, while not necessarily mutually exclusive, there were at least two central objectives that were advanced in relation to conducting trials in the midst of the EVD epidemic: (1) to aid the current humanitarian response and to make potential therapies rapidly available in order to save as many lives as soon as possible; and (2) to generate the most robust, scientifically valid data that would lead to the development of a licensed product that could, in turn, be used to ensure the safest and most efficacious intervention was available for patients receiving treatment following the conclusion of the trial. Preference for either trial design in the context of an epidemic may therefore be dependent, at least in part, on which objective is considered the priority.

A World Health Organization ethics advisory panel argued that investigational therapeutic options should not divert resources or attention from the public health measures, which they claim ought to remain the priority in an epidemic response (WHO 2014). In 2022, WHO argued that “emergency use of interventions for which there is insufficient evidence of safety or efficacy for regular use in health systems is ethically permissible outside clinical trials or other research contexts, if the primary aim is clinical benefit for individual people or groups or benefit for populations, and if such use during public health emergencies complies with a sound ethical framework that ensures adequate justification, ethical and regulatory oversight, consent process and contribution to evidence” (WHO 2022). Others have warned that research conducted during an epidemic or other public health emergency could have the effect of encouraging the modification of public health priorities, perhaps from providing a humanitarian response to the rigorous collection of data (Ezeome and Simon 2010). As such, if substantial resources are to be invested to conduct a trial during an epidemic, then there is a strong argument to be made that a moral responsibility exists to use those resources in such a way that they benefit those affected by the epidemic and curb the further spread of the epidemic. While any trial design has the potential to direct attention away from the immediate epidemic response, it appears that ACTs may be more congruent with the immediate epidemic response, although, placebo-controlled RCTs could be designed in a way that makes them align better with the advantages of ACTs. This could be accomplished, for example, by utilizing stepped-wedge RCTs, which involve random and sequential crossover of clusters of participants from a control arm (or arms) to the experimental arm (or arms) until all clusters have been exposed to the experimental intervention (Hemming et al. 2014). Or, placebo-controlled RCTs could utilize data safety and monitoring boards, who are charged with reviewing interim data and implementing early stopping rules based on safety and/or efficacy thresholds.

It is important to acknowledge that, for any research conducted in the context of an epidemic, the ability of participants to provide informed consent may become compromised or the consent process may become less feasible (see Chap. 9). This may be due to participants’ lack of mental or physical capacity in such dire circumstances, a lack of local health-care workers available to recruit participants, and/or a strong therapeutic misconception undermining participants’ abilities to appreciate the clinician’s dual role as researcher and health-care worker (Pullman and Wang 2001; Ezeome and Simon 2010; Adebamowo et al. 2014; Kass 2014; Tangwa 2014). As such, some argue that every effort must be made to provide the most effective treatment to every trial participant, given current information, and that ACTs attempt to accomplish this very task while still ensuring that research objectives can be pursued (Pullman and Wang 2001). The dire circumstances and the prospect of inevitable therapeutic misconception during the EVD epidemic led some to argue that entering West Africa with the aim of doing anything other than saving the lives of those affected by EVD and curbing the spread of the epidemic would be morally irresponsible (Tangwa 2014). This sentiment, if it is to be balanced with the motivation and need to collect crucial evidence about the safety and efficacy of investigational therapies, may be supportive of adopting an adaptive design.

5.5 Conclusion

Epidemics should prompt researchers to evaluate whether their research ought to be adapted or whether adaptive designs might be appropriate and ethically justified. What is clear is that adaptive designs and adaptations to research do not obviate the need for rigorous scientific evaluation and adherence to universal ethical standards, and must be explicitly ethically justified and reviewed through transparent and inclusive processes. Involving the voices of local, affected communities in research planning, design and oversight remains crucial. Engaging local communities in such aspects of the research may foster trust in the research and epidemic response and better ensure local values and customs are both respected and represented (Modlin et al. 2023). Consequently, the input of those affected by an epidemic and who may be impacted by any research conducted ought to be considered of the utmost importance in responding to the question of whether and how research might be adapted.