Skip to main content

Pleasure and “Happiness” in Aristotle: A Key to Understanding the Tourist?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Tourism and Culture in Philosophical Perspective
  • 74 Accesses

Abstract.

In ancient Greek thought, the final destination of humans’ life journey is eudaimonia, “happiness.” Aristotle follows this tradition in taking eudaimonia as the “goal” (telos) of human life. Eudaimonia, however, is not a momentary achievement or a means for attaining something else, nor is it identified with the chance “goods” of aristocracy, wealth, beauty, or political power. It is tied rather to the specific nature of human beings and depends on their particular function or “work” (ergon) as their proper condition throughout an entire lifetime. There is also a pleasure (hêdonê) which corresponds to this activity as the most essential and highest possible pleasure for human beings according to their nature. What is the proper activity for the human species and its proper pleasure? Which pleasure corresponds to a human being’s true nature? This paper explores the paramount importance of pleasure within the ethical/political framework of Aristotle’s philosophy and its association with the ultimate destination of human life – which is to fully realise our human potential and function according to our nature. As such, Aristotle’s view of pleasure and happiness may provide some key insights for understanding – and perhaps redirecting – the pursuits of the tourist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    While in Homer, e.g., possessing great political power was the paragon of aretê, the pattern of the best possible way of life (cf. Iliad 6.476–478).

  2. 2.

    NE 1.12, 1102a5–6: ἐστὶν ἡ εὐδαιμονία ψυχῆς ἐνέργειά τις κατ’ ἀρετὴν τελείαν. Cf. NE 10.7, 1177a12. On this definition, see e.g. Purinton 1998. Cf. Heinaman 2007. On eudaimonia in Aristotle’s ethics, see e.g. Hardie 1965; Ackrill 1974; McDowell 1980; Kraut 1989, esp.15–77; Kenny 1991; Lear 2004, esp. 37–71; Irwin 2012.

  3. 3.

    Cf. Wedin 1981; Whiting 1988; Gomez-Lobo 1991; Lawrence 2006.

  4. 4.

    NE 1.7, 1098a10–11: προστιθεμένης τῆς κατὰ τὴν ἀρετὴν ὑπεροχῆς πρὸς τὸ ἔργον.

  5. 5.

    NE 1.7, 1098a18–20: ἔτι δ’ ἐν βίῳ τελείῳ. μία γὰρ χελιδὼν ἔαρ οὐ ποιεῖ, οὐδὲ μία ἡμέρα⋅ οὕτω δὲ οὐδὲ μακάριον καὶ εὐδαίμονα μία ἡμέρα οὐδ’ ὀλίγος χρόνος. Cf. 2.4, 1105a33.

  6. 6.

    Cf. also NE 10.6, 1176b18–19: οὐ γὰρ ἐν τῷ δυναστεύειν ἡ ἀρετὴ οὐδ’ ὁ νοῦς, ἀφ’ ὧν αἱ σπουδαῖαι ἐνέργειαι.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Liatsi 2022. On ‘virtue’ in Aristotle’s ethics, see e.g. Hutchinson 1986; Sherman 1991; Gottlieb 2009; Lorenz 2009.

  8. 8.

    Cf. NE 4.1, 1120a24–25: αἱ δὲ κατ’ ἀρετὴν πράξεις καλαὶ καὶ τοῦ καλοῦ ἕνεκα.

  9. 9.

    Cf. NE 2.6, 1106b21–23: τὸ δ’ ὅτε δεῖ καὶ ἐφ’ οἷς καὶ πρὸς οὓς καὶ οὗ ἕνεκα καὶ ὡς δεῖ, μέσον τε καὶ ἄριστον, ὅπερ ἐστὶ τῆς ἀρετῆς.

  10. 10.

    Cf. Hardie 1977; Urmson 1980; Wolf 2006.

  11. 11.

    NE 2.4, 1105a32: προαιρούμενος δι’ αὐτά (scil. τὰ κατὰ τὰς ἀρετὰς γινόμενα).

  12. 12.

    Merker 2016; cf. Charpenel 2017, 186–208.

  13. 13.

    Russell 2014. Cf. Cooper 1996.

  14. 14.

    Cf. Flannery 2013.

  15. 15.

    On the following views, see Liatsi 2020.

  16. 16.

    Cf. NE 2.9, 1109a28–35.

  17. 17.

    Cf. NE 2.9, 1109b1–7: σκοπεῖν δὲ δεῖ πρὸς ἃ καὶ αὐτοὶ εὐκατάφοροί ἐσμεν⋅ ἄλλοι γὰρ πρὸς ἄλλα πεφύκαμεν⋅ τοῦτο δ’ ἔσται γνώριμον ἐκ τῆς ἡδονῆς καὶ τῆς λύπης τῆς γινομένης περὶ ἡμᾶς. εἰς τοὐναντίον δ’ ἑαυτοὺς ἀφέλκειν δεῖ⋅ πολὺ γὰρ ἀπάγοντες τοῦ ἁμαρτάνειν εἰς τὸ μέσον ἥξομεν, ὅπερ οἱ τὰ διεστραμμένα τῶν ξύλων ὀρθοῦντες ποιοῦσιν.

  18. 18.

    Cf. NE 2.3, 1105a7–9: ἔτι δὲ χαλεπώτερον ἡδονῇ μάχεσθαι ἢ θυμῷ, καθάπερ φησὶν Ἡράκλειτος, περὶ δὲ τὸ χαλεπώτερον ἀεὶ καὶ τέχνη γίνεται καὶ ἀρετή.

  19. 19.

    That is why Aristotle agrees with Plato that the right education consists of feeling joy or pity towards the right things. This, according to Aristotle, is how we must be raised from childhood onwards. The ἀρετή, appropriate education from an early age can teach people, as Aristotle points out, how important is to be pleased with the right activities and similarly how meaningful it is to be sorry in case they resort to unenviable activities. See NE 2.3, 1104b3–13, esp. 1104b11–13. Cf. Plato, Politeia 401 E – 402 A; Nomoi 653 A – C.

  20. 20.

    Cf. also Wolfsdorf 2013, esp. 130–133.

  21. 21.

    The pleasures of the body are closely related to desires, to epithumiai. Aristotle does not reject them, but he disapproves of pleasures that exceed moderation and lead to excess (hyperbole). These are harmful and thus should be kept at bay since they destroy eudaimonia.

  22. 22.

    See. n. 2.

  23. 23.

    Cf. Met. Λ 9. 1074b16: δοκεῖ μὲν γὰρ εἶναι τῶν φαινομένων θειότατον.

  24. 24.

    On the different aspects of the relation between eudaimonia and theôria in Aristotle’s ethics, see Destrée and Zingano 2014.

  25. 25.

    NE 10.7, 1177a16–18: ἡ τοῦ (scil. τοῦ νοῦ) ἐνέργεια κατὰ τὴν οἰκείαν ἀρετὴν εἴη ἂν ἡ τελεία εὐδαιμονία. ὅτι δ῾ ἐστὶ θεωρητική, εἴρηται. / Cf. NE 10.8, 1178b32: ὥστ᾽ εἴη ἄν ἡ εὐδαιμονία θεωρία τις. Cf. Protreptikos fr. 87: “Complete and unimpeded activity contains within itself pleasure, so that the activity of theoretical intellect must be the most pleasant of all.”

  26. 26.

    Cf. Long 2011.

  27. 27.

    NE 10.8, 1178b21–23: ἔτι δὲ μᾶλλον τοῦ ποιεῖν, τί λείπεται πλὴν θεωρία; ὥστε ἡ τοῦ θεοῦ ἐνέργεια, μακαριότητι διαφέρουσα, θεωρητικὴ ἂν εἴη: καὶ τῶν ἀνθρωπίνων δὴ ἡ ταύτῃ συγγενεστάτη εὐδαιμονικωτάτη.

    Cf. Met. Λ 7, 1072b14–16: διαγωγὴ δ᾽ ἐστὶν οἵα ἡ ἀρίστη μικρὸν χρόνον ἡμῖν οὕτω γὰρ ἀεὶ ἐκεῖνο: ἡμῖν μὲν γὰρ ἀδύνατον, ἐπεὶ καὶ ἡδονὴ ἡ ἐνέργεια τούτου. See Liatsi 2016.

  28. 28.

    NE 10.7, 1177a23–24: ἡδίστη δὲ τῶν κατ’ ἀρετὴν ἐνεργειῶν ἡ κατὰ τὴν σοφίαν.

  29. 29.

    NE 10.7, 1178a5–6: τὸ γὰρ οἰκεῖον ἑκάστῳ τῇ φύσει κράτιστον καὶ ἥδιστόν ἐστιν.

  30. 30.

    It is somehow the Aristotelian version of Plato’s “resemblance to God”, (ὁμοίωσις θεῷ, Theaitetos 176b1), as the way for human beings to reach eudaimonia in life. Cf. Sedley 2017.

  31. 31.

    NE 10.7, 1177b33–34: ἐφ᾽ ὅσον ἐνδέχεται ἀθανατίζειν καὶ πάντα ποιεῖν πρὸς τὸ ζῆν κατὰ τὸ κράτιστον τῶν ἐν αὑτῷ.

References

  • Ackrill, J.L. 1974. Aristotle on Eudaimonia. Proceedings of the British Academy. 60: 339–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charpenel, Eduardo. 2017. Ethos und Praxis: Der Charakterbegriff bei Aristoteles. Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John. 1996. Reason, Moral Virtue, and Moral Value. In Rationality in Greek Thought, ed. Michael Frede and Gisela Striker, 81–114. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Destrée, Pierre, and Marco Zingano, eds. 2014. Theoria: Studies on the Status and Meaning of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics. Louvain-La-Neuve: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flannery, Kevin L. 2013. Action and Character According to Aristotle: The Logic of the Moral Life. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso. 1991. The Ergon Inference. In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy IV: Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. John P. Anton and Anthony Preus, 43–57. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, Paula. 2009. The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardie, W.F.R. 1965. The Final Good in Aristotle’s Ethics. Philosophy 40: 277–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Aristotle’s Doctrine that Virtue is a ‘Mean’. In Articles on Aristotle II: Ethics and Politics, ed. Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield, and Richard Sorabji, 33–46. London: Gerald Duckworth and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinaman, Robert. 2007. Eudaimonia as an activity in Nicomachean Ethics 1.8–12. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 33: 221–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, D.S. 1986. The Virtues of Aristotle. London: Routledge\Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, Terence H. 2012. Conceptions of Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics. In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 495–528. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, Anthony. 1991. The Nicomachean Conception of Happiness. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Supplemental Volume: 67–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Richard. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, Gavin. 2006. Human Good and Human Function. In The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 37–75. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lear, Gabriel Richardson. 2004. Happy Lives and the Highest Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Liatsi, Maria. 2016. Aristotle’s Silence about the Prime Mover’s Noêsis. In Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda – New Essays, ed. Christoph Horn, 229–245. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Natural Inclination to Ethics in Aristotle. In Ethics in Ancient Greek Literature, ed. Maria Liatsi. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2022. Agôn: An Aristotelian Way of Life. In The Agon in Classical Literature: Essays in Honour of Professor Chris Carey eds. Michael Edwards, Athanasios Efstathiou, E. Volanaki, and Ioanna Karamanou. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies Supplements 146. London: Institute of Classical Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Long, A.A. 2011. Aristotle on eudaimonia, nous and divinity. In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Jon Miller, 92–114. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, Hendrik. 2009. Virtue of Character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 177–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1980. The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle’s Ethics. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, 359–376. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Merker, Anne. 2016. Le Principe de l’action humaine selon Démosthène et Aristote: Hairesis – Prohairesis. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Purinton, Jeffrey S. 1998. Aristotle’s Definition of Happiness (NE 1.7, 1098a16–18). Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 16: 259–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel C. 2014. Phronesis and the Virtues (NE vi 12–13). In The Cambridge Companion to the Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 203–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedley, David. 2017. Becoming Godlike. In The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics, ed. Christopher Bobonich, 319–337. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, Nancy. 1991. The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s Theory of Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J.O. 1980. Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean. In Essays in Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. A.O. Rorty, 157–170. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wedin, M. 1981. Aristotle on the Good for Man. Mind 90: 243–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, Jennifer. 1988. Aristotle’s Function Argument: A Defence. Ancient Philosophy 8: 33–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Ursula. 2006. Über den Sinn der Aristotelischen Mesoteslehre. In Aristoteles. Nikomachische Ethik, ed. Orfried Höffe, 83–108. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfsdorf, David. 2013. Aristotle on pleasure and activation. In Pleasure in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Liatsi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Liatsi, M. (2023). Pleasure and “Happiness” in Aristotle: A Key to Understanding the Tourist?. In: Zovko, MÉ., Dillon, J. (eds) Tourism and Culture in Philosophical Perspective. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-36659-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics