Skip to main content

The Capitalist State as a Historically Specific Social Form

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Marxism and the Capitalist State

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

Abstract

The critique of social forms best enables us to apprehend the capitalist state in its historical specificity. The capitalist state presupposes and is presupposed by the other essential determinations of generalized commodity production. Within capitalist society, however, the state is fetishized as separate from relations of production and exchange. A critique of the capitalist state as one of capitalist society's essential forms makes it possible to grasp its specificity, its relationship with capital, and its mediation of the abstract and impersonal domination experienced by all members of society. As the political appearance of capitalist society, the capitalist state cannot be described as dominated or captured by capital—but this does not entail that emancipatory struggle consists in the struggle to seize, or wield the power of, the capitalist state. Such a state is an appearance of a social reality that must be abolished.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Fetishism is, inter alia, a social practice of treating determinate and historically specific categories as natural or trans-historical (that is, anterior to their own social constitution) (Murray 2016, 59). For an overview of the critique of the state as a contribution to the critique of fetishism, see Neupert-Doppler (2018). I explore the fetishism of the apparent separation of the political and the economic in Part 4, below.

  2. 2.

    ‘A theory of social forms is of central importance to a critical theory’ (Postone 1993, 179). An adequate account of value-form theory—and of social form theory more generally—is beyond the scope of this essay. For background see Elson (1979), Smith (1990), Clarke (1991a, 92–143), Postone (1993), Backhaus (1997), Bonefeld (2014, 79–137), and Murray (2016).

  3. 3.

    ‘The analysis of the the capitalist state conceptually presupposes the analysis of capital and the reproduction of capitalist relations of production, despite the fact that in reality, of course, the state is itself a moment of the process of reproduction’ (Clarke 1991b, 189). ‘While the commodity form is the economic form of society, the state is its political form’ (Bonefeld 2014, 179).

  4. 4.

    ‘“[V]alue” is neither a category of production, nor a category of exchange, but a category of mediation between the two, expressing the unity-in-difference of privately undertaken production and the exchange that establishes its social necessity’ (Smith 2017, 81).

  5. 5.

    For this claim see Bonefeld (2014, 79–95); for additional perspectives see Singh (2016), Roberts (2020), and Gerstenberger (2022).

  6. 6.

    Cf. Banaji (2010, 131–54) on debates about the extent of the variability in the forms of exploitation that can appear as wage-labour.

  7. 7.

    I am unable to dwell on two issues that are germane to this point. The first is the question of how the account presented here may be related to analytic category of ‘state capitalism’ as it is applied to development in the global periphery (Alami et al. 2022). The second is the contemporary existence of polities that do not conform to the model presented here. Here it must be emphasized that a theory of the capitalist state, like a theory of capitalist production, seeks to explain the specific and preponderant features of its object in order to apprehend it as a historically determinate social form. As such, the existence of states that do not conform (to lesser or greater degrees) to the contours of the account presented here does not by itself vitiate my overall account; nor does the abstraction necessarily involved in the elaboration of an explanatory model constitute evidence that that model is presumptively invalid. For an introduction to issues of abstraction and model-making in Marxian theory see Mattick (2018, 13–33, 50–71).

  8. 8.

    ‘The fact that the rule of economic abstractions benefits the owners of great wealth does not entail that they are in control’ (Bonefeld 2020, 161). On the limits of those conceptions of the state, according to which state power is either wielded on behalf of a class, or is the object of struggle between classes, see Clarke (1991b) and Sumida (2018).

  9. 9.

    On this point see also Kirstin Munro’s contribution to the present volume.

  10. 10.

    On this point see also Chris O’Kane’s contribution to the present volume.

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2006. History and Freedom: Lectures 1964–1965. Edited by Rolf Tiedemann. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alami, Ilias, Milan Babic, Adam D. Dixon, and Imogen T. Liu. 2022. ‘Special Issue Introduction: What Is the New State Capitalism?’ Contemporary Politics 28 (3): 245–63. https://doi.org/10.1080/13569775.2021.2022336.

  • Backhaus, Hans-Georg. 1997. Dialektik der Wertform: Untersuchungen zur Marxschen Ökonomiekritik. Freiburg: Ça Ira.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banaji, Jairus. 2010. Theory as History: Essays on Modes of Production and Exploitation. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellofiore, Riccardo. 2014. ‘Lost in Translation: Once Again on the Marx–Hegel Connection.’ In Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic: A Reexamination, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith, 164–88. Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004270022_009.

  • Bonefeld, Werner. 1995. ‘Money, Equality and Exploitation: An Interpretation of Marx’s Treatment of Money.’ In Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money, edited by Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, 178–209. London: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-14240-8_8.

  • ———. 2014. Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy: On Subversion and Negative Reason. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. ‘On Capital as Real Abstraction.’ In Marx and Contemporary Critical Theory: The Philosophy of Real Abstraction, edited by Antonio Oliva, Ángel Oliva, and Iván Novara, 153–70. London: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-39954-2_9.

  • Bonefeld, Werner, Richard Gunn, and Kosmas Psychopedis, eds. 1991. Open Marxism 1: Dialectics and History. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Simon. 1988. Keynesianism, Monetarism and the Crisis of the State. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991a. Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology: From Adam Smith to Max Weber. Houndmills: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991b. ‘State, Class Struggle, and the Reproduction of Capital.’ In The State Debate, edited by Simon Clarke, 183–203. Houndmills: Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-21464-8_6.

  • ———. 1992. ‘The Global Accumulation of Capital and the Periodisation of the Capitalist State Form.’ In Open Marxism 1: Dialectics and History, edited by Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, and Kosmas Psychopedis, 133–50. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimick, Matthew. 2021. ‘Pashukanis’ Commodity-Form Theory of Law.’ In Research Handbook on Law and Marxism, edited by Paul O’Connell and Umut Özsu, 115–38. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. https://doi.org/10.4337/9781788119863.00013.

  • Elson, Diane, ed. 1979. Value: The Representation of Labour in Capitalism. London: CSE Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerstenberger, Heide. 2022. Market and Violence: The Functioning of Capitalism in History. Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004522633.

  • Heinrich, Michael. 2012. An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital. Translated by Alexander Locascio. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. ‘The “Fragment on Machines”: A Marxian Misconception in the Grundrisse and Its Overcoming in Capital.’ In In Marx’s Laboratory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas, 195–212. Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004252592_010.

  • Holloway, John, and Sol Picciotto, eds. 1978. State and Capital: A Marxist Debate. London: Edward Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1972. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1973. Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy. Translated by Martin Nicolaus. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Translated by Ben Fowkes. Vol. I. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Translated by David Fernbach. Vol. II. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattick, Paul. 2018. Theory as Critique: Essays on Capital. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milios, John. 2018. The Origins of Capitalism as a Social System: The Prevalence of an Aleatory Encounter. Oxford: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, Patrick. 1988. Marx’s Theory of Scientific Knowledge. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The Mismeasure of Wealth: Essays on Marx and Social Form. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neupert-Doppler, Alexander. 2018. ‘Society and Political Form.’ In The SAGE Handbook of Frankfurt School Critical Theory, edited by Beverly Best, Werner Bonefeld, and Chris O’Kane, 3:816–33. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Kane, Chris, and Kirstin Munro. 2022. ‘Marxian Economics and the Critique of Political Economy.’ In Adorno and Marx: Negative Dialectics and the Critique of Political Economy, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Chris O’Kane, 77–95. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postone, Moishe. 1993. Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s Critical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reichelt, Helmut. 2005. ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Conception of Reality.’ In Human Dignity: Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, 31–67. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuten, Geert. 2018. The Unity of the Capitalist Economy and State: A Systematic-Dialectical Exposition of the Capitalist System. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, William Clare. 2020. ‘What Was Primitive Accumulation? Reconstructing the Origin of a Critical Concept.’ European Journal of Political Theory 19 (4): 532–52. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885117735961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, Alfred. 1981. History and Structure: An Essay on Hegelian-Marxist and Structuralist Theories of History. Translated by Jeffrey Herf. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The Concept of Nature in Marx. Translated by Ben Fowkes. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Nikhil Pal. 2016. ‘On Race, Violence, and So-Called Primitive Accumulation.’ Social Text 34 (3): 27–50. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1215/01642472-3607564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Tony. 1990. The Logic of Marx’s Capital: Replies to Hegelian Criticisms. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. ‘Hegel, Marx and the Comprehension of Capitalism.’ In Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic: A Reexamination, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith, 15–40. Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004270022_003.

  • ———. 2017. Beyond Liberal Egalitarianism: Marx and Normative Social Theory in the Twenty-First Century. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberg, Marc W. 2010. ‘Marx, Formal Subsumption and the Law.’ Theory and Society 39 (2): 173–202. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11186-009-9101-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sumida, Soichiro. 2018. ‘Die Zusammenfassung der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft in der Staatsform: Zu Marx’ Theorie des Staats.’ Marx-Engels Jahrbuch 2017 (1): 41–60. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1515/mejb-2018-20170103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Michael, ed. 1988. Value, Social Form and the State. Houndmills: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Ellen Meiksins. 1995. Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Matt Dimick, Nate Holdren, Rafael Khachaturian, Eva Nanopoulos, Paul Mattick, Chris O’Kane, and Dom Taylor for their feedback, suggestions, and critiques.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rob Hunter .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hunter, R. (2023). The Capitalist State as a Historically Specific Social Form. In: Hunter, R., Khachaturian, R., Nanopoulos, E. (eds) Marxism and the Capitalist State. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-36167-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics