Skip to main content

Until the End of the World

On Eidetic Variation and Absolute Being of Consciousness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Invention of Infinity: Essays on Husserl and the History of Philosophy

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 124))

  • 110 Accesses

Abstract

One of the most controversial claims of Husserl’s phenomenology is that consciousness “has” (or “is”) an absolute being, i.e., something that in Ideas I is described by means of a rather famous Cartesian quote: “nulla ‘re’ indiget ad existendum.” Consciousness “has” (or “is”) an absolute being insofar as it has no need of any “thing” in order to exist.

It’s the end of the world as we know it. | It’s the end of the world as we know it, | and I feel fine.

R.E.M.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The immanent being is, therefore, without doubt absolute being in the sense that, in principle, nulla ‘re’ indiget ad existendum” (Hua III/1, p. 104/89).

  2. 2.

    Per substantiam nihil aliud intelligere possumus, quam rem quae existit, ut nulla alia re indiget ad existendum” (Descartes, 1644, p. 24).

  3. 3.

    “The philosophical ἐποχή that we adopt should, to put it formally, consist in the fact that we completely withhold judgment regarding the doctrinal content of all previous philosophy and carry out all our demonstrations within the framework of withholding such judgment” (Hua III/1, pp. 39–40/33). On this point see Chap. 12 in this volume.

  4. 4.

    Or, at least, Heidegger does not seem to take advantage of Husserl’s equivocity when he establishes the distinctions between the several meaning of phenomenon spelled out in Being and Time §7a (see Heidegger, 1977, pp. 28–31/27–30).

  5. 5.

    This holds of course only as long as we neglect, for the sake of the argument, that a book has “spiritual” predicates and belongs to the region Geist. According to Husserl, a book counts as a mere “thing” only in the naturalistic attitude. See Hua IV, pp. 173–185/183–194.

  6. 6.

    See Hua III/1, pp. 186–7/159–61.

  7. 7.

    Again, one should not conflate this concrete “ego” (belonging to the region “consciousness”) with a concrete “person” (belonging to the region “spirit”) or a concrete psycho-physiological “soul” (non-independent with regards to its living body within the region “nature”), as Husserl will further clarify in Ideas II.

  8. 8.

    “Higher order personalities” (Höhere Ordnung Persönlichkeiten) belong to the sphere of the Gemeingeist. See Hua XIV, pp. 192–203. On the concept of region see Chap. 4 of this volume.

  9. 9.

    A notable exception can be found in the systematic attempts of Rochus Sowa, which have greatly contributed to the understanding of Husserl’s key ontological notions. See for instance Sowa (2007a).

  10. 10.

    See Hua III/1, pp. 145–8/124–7.

  11. 11.

    See Husserl (1999, pp. 409–429/339–354).

  12. 12.

    Ultimately, the analysis of the relation between (methodic) constitution of εἴδη and (methodological) intuition of eidetic states of affairs might even help understanding what Heidegger (1979, §7, pp. 99–103/72–75) calls the “third fundamental discovery of phenomenology,” after intentionality and categorial intuition, i.e., “the original sense of the a priori”.

  13. 13.

    This claim is rooted in the Aristotelian correlation between τόδε τι and τὸ τί ἐστι spelled out in Met. Z, 1 (1028a11). See Aubenque (2000, pp. 93–97). See also Chap. 3 of this volume.

  14. 14.

    This has certainly nothing to do with Heidegger’s (1977, 1979) search for the Quis? instead of the Quid? And in this sense, one cannot be disappointed if the answer to Heidegger’s question is nowhere to be found in Ideas I. Besides, Husserl explicitly puts aside all analysis related to what he calls “subjectively-oriented phenomenology,” so that the question of the Quis? should find its right context precisely in the analysis of time consciousness (see Hua III/1, pp. 180–3/155–8).

  15. 15.

    The point is made clear in the first part of the second of the Logical Investigations: see, for instance, Hua XIX, II.1, pp. 113–115/ I, pp. 239–40.

  16. 16.

    See Sowa (2007a, pp. 5–10).

  17. 17.

    Husserl follows this third option several times, especially when he talks about non-objective forms of intentionality in his account of inner time consciousness. More details on this point can be found in Majolino (2010, pp. 606–621).

  18. 18.

    Nota bene: this is neither a definition of the term “world” nor a descriptive account of its essential or conceptual features. It is only an indisputable example of what certainly counts as a world—our world. The world of the natural attitude fixes the meaning of the term “world” and establishes its semantic boundaries.

  19. 19.

    Although, strictly speaking, in his studies on phantasy consciousness Husserl rules out the very idea of a “fictional world.”

  20. 20.

    See Hua XXIII, p. 88/95.

  21. 21.

    On this point see Chap. 5 of this volume.

References

I – Works of Husserl

    II – Other Works

    • Husserl, E. (1939). Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik (L. Landgrebe, Ed.). Meiner. 1999. (English Translation by Churchill, J. S., & Ameriks, K. Experience and judgment. Investigations in a genealogy of logic. Northwestern University Press, 1973).

      Google Scholar 

    • Aubenque, P. (2000). Sur l’ambivalence du concept aristotélicien de substance. In N.-L. Cordero (Ed.), Ontologie et dialogue (pp. 93–106). Vrin.

      Google Scholar 

    • Descartes, R. (1644). Principia Philosophiæ. In C. Adam & P. Tannery (Eds.), Œuvres (Vol. VIII, pp. 1–353). English translation by V. R. Miller & R. P. Miller, Principles of Philosophy. Riedel, 1983.

      Google Scholar 

    • Heidegger, M. (1977). Sein und Zeit (Gesamtausgabe 2. Ed. F.-W. von Hermann). Klostermann. English translation by J. Stambaugh, Being and Time. SUNY Press, 1996.

      Google Scholar 

    • Heidegger, M. (1979). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (Gesamtausgabe 20). Klostermann. English translation by T. Kisiel, History of the Concept of Time. Prolegomena. Indiana University Press, 2008.

      Google Scholar 

    • Majolino, C. (2010). La partition du réel : Remarques sur l’eidos, la phantasia, l’effondrement du monde et l’être absolu de la conscience. In F. Mattens, H. Jacobs, & C. Ierna (Eds.), Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences. Essays in Commemoration of Edmund Husserl (pp. 573–660). Springer.

      Chapter  Google Scholar 

    • Sartre, J.-P. (1938). La Nausée. Gallimard. English translation by L. Alexander, Nausea. New Directions.

      Google Scholar 

    • Sowa, R. (2007a). Wesen und Wesensgesetze in der deskriptiven Eidetik Edmund Husserls. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 2007, 5–37.

      Article  Google Scholar 

    • Woolf, V. (1925). Mrs. Dalloway. Penguin.

      Google Scholar 

    Download references

    Author information

    Authors and Affiliations

    Authors

    Corresponding author

    Correspondence to Claudio Majolino .

    Rights and permissions

    Reprints and permissions

    Copyright information

    © 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

    About this chapter

    Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

    Cite this chapter

    Majolino, C. (2023). Until the End of the World. In: The Invention of Infinity: Essays on Husserl and the History of Philosophy. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 124. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-34150-2_6

    Download citation

    Publish with us

    Policies and ethics