Skip to main content

Function, Adaptation, and Design in Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Functions: From Organisms to Artefacts

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 32))

  • 125 Accesses

Abstract

The main misunderstanding of the etiological conception of the concept of function is to confuse this notion with the concept of adaptation. The explanations by natural selection do not justify function attributions: They explain the configuration of an organic structure by considerations that, among other elements, also include references to the functional performance of this structure. That is why, the best manner of characterizing them is to say that they are design explanations. However, for a correct formulation of the idea of design, it will be necessary to adopt a conception of the function attributions that could avoid the difficulties of the etiological conception. For this, it will be necessary to think of functions as causal roles.

This chapter resulted from the discussion held during my lecture “Explication fonctionelle et explication sélective,” which I gave on 20 June 2006 during a session of the Séminaire Structure et FonctionL’inférence fonctionnelle organized by Jean Gayon and Phillippe Huneman at the Institut d’histoire et philosophie des sciences et des techniques of Sorbonne. To both organizers, and to all those who participated in the discussion, my sincere thanks. In addition, I also must thank the valuable observations made by the reviewers of Signos Filosóficos: They allowed me to improve my work. This was originally published, in Spanish, in the issue 24 of that Mexican journal (cf. Caponi, 2010), which has been generous enough to allow its inclusion in this volume.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Remarks that are similar to that I am making here may be found in Davies (2000, p. 36 n8, 2001, p. 55, 2009, p. 141) and also in Rosenberg and McShea (2008, p. 92).

  2. 2.

    Cuvierian Paleontology always made function attributions to fossil bones, denying, at the same time, any history of the biological structures.

  3. 3.

    The concept of function should not be confused with that of raison d’être. Contrary to what is assumed by the defenders of the etiological conception, the function of something is not always its raison d’être. Even designed devices can fulfill functions that do not explain their existence: A bottle, for example, can function as a projectile.

  4. 4.

    Concerning this aspect of Kant’s thought, see Rosas (2008).

  5. 5.

    Prima facie, the idea of organic teleology, based on the assumption of goals intrinsic to living beings, seems more restrictive than the notion of teleology proposed by Margarita Ponce. This is so because the first position assumes that the goal in question does not depend on a mere theoretical choice but on something that is proper to or inherent in the object of study. Nevertheless, if we accept that the recognition that a particular physical system constitutes an organism presupposes a functional analysis of its parts in which these are considered by virtue of their causal contribution to the operation and constitution of the whole, that difference is diluted (cf. Kant, 1995 [1790], § 66; Merleau-Ponty, 1967, p. 165; Polanyi, 1962, p. 359). The organic teleology may be thought as just a special case of that generalized teleology pointed out by Ponce.

  6. 6.

    For the configuration of a selective pressure, two factors are needed: The environmental factor is needed, which can be a threat or an opportunity for the living beings affected; it is also needed the existence of hereditary variants that favor a better or worse response to this threat or a better or worst harnessing of this opportunity. The ecological variables, by themselves, do not configure selective pressures. A poison that kills indiscriminately and a resource that everyone can use equally are important variables in the ecological environment of a population, but they do not define the selective environment that guides the evolution of the lineage to which that population belongs.

References

  • Abercrombie, M., Hickman, C., & Johnson, M. (1957). A dictionary of biology. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1998). Biological function, adaptation, and natural design. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 571–588). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R., & Lauder, G. (1998). Function without purpose: The uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 335–370). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1878). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux végétaux. Baillière.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bock, W., & Wahlert, G. (1998). Adaptation and the form-function complex. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 117–168). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (2006). Teleology in self-organizing systems. In B. Feltz, M. Crommelinck, & P. Goujon (Eds.), Self-organization and emergence in life sciences (pp. 267–281). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. (1999). Natural teleology. In D. Buller (Ed.), Function, selection, and design (pp. 1–28). SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi, G. (2002). Explicación seleccional y explicación funcional: la teleología en la Biología contemporánea. Episteme, 14, 57–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi, G. (2008). Georges Cuvier, un fisiólogo de museo. UNAM/Limusa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi, G. (2010). Función, adaptación y diseño en Biología. Signos Filosóficos, 24, 71–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. The Journal of Philosophy, 20, 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (2002). Neo-teleology. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions (pp. 57–172). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R., & Roth, M. (2010). Traits have not evolved to function the way they do because of past advantages. In F. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 72–88). Wiley/Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuvier, G. (1817). Le règne animal, Tome I. Deterville.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. (2000). Malfunctions. Biology and Philosophy, 15, 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. (2001). Norms of nature. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. (2009). Conceptual conservatism: The case of normative function. In U. Krohs & P. Kroes (Eds.), Functions in biological and artificial worlds (pp. 127–146). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1999). The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delsol, M., & Perrin, L. (2000). Médecine et Biologie: quelle logique? Masson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1990). The interpretation of texts, people and other artifacts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50(supplement), 177–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1996). Darwin’s dangerous idea. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gans, C. (1998). Adaptation and the form-function relation. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 541–570). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2008). Function and teleology. In S. Sarkar & A. Plutynski (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 525–549). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2006). Les biologistes ont-ils besoin du concept de fonction? Palevol, 5, 479–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1997). Metaphysics and the origins of species. SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili, S. (2009). Adaptación y función. Ludus Vitalis, 17(31), 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1998). Functions: Consensus without unity. In D. Hull & M. Ruse (Eds.), The philosophy of biology (pp. 280–291). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, K. (1951). La structure de l’organisme. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S., & Vrba, E. (1998). Exaptation: A missing term in the science of form. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 519–540). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, V. (1999). Where biology meets psychology. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, W. (1963 [1628]). Movement of the heart and blood in animals. In W. Harvey (Ed.), The circulation of the blood and other writings (pp. 1–112). Everyman’s Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1995 [1790]). Kritik der Urtheilskraft. Köneman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1998). Function and design. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 479–504). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krohs, U. (2009). Functions as based on a concept of general design. Synthese, 166, 69–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krohs, U., & Kroes, P. (2009). Philosophical perspectives on organismic and artifactual functions. In U. Krohs & P. Kroes (Eds.), Functions in biological and artificial worlds (pp. 3–12). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder, G. (1998). Historical biology and the problem of design. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 507–518). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, D. (2008). La complejidad del lenguaje normativo empleado para evaluar técnicamente a los artefactos técnicos. Scientiae Studia, 6(3), 329–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2004). Organism and artifacts: Design in nature and elsewhere. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2007). Functions. In M. Matthen & C. Stephens (Eds.), Philosophy of biology (pp. 525–548). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. (1978). Adaptation. Scientific American, 239(3), 212–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1998). De máquinas y seres vivos. Ed. Universitaria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1976). Cause and effect in biology. In E. Mayr (Ed.), Evolution and diversity of life (pp. 357–407). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (2009). Functions and norms. In U. Krohs & P. Kroes (Eds.), Functions in biological and artificial worlds (pp. 93–102). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1967). La structure du comportement. Press Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1998). In defense of proper functions. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 295–312). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1999). An ambiguity in the notion of function. In D. Buller (Ed.), Function, selection, and design (pp. 115–122). SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2002). Biofunctions: Two paradigms. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions (pp. 113–143). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1998). Teleology revisited. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 197–240). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1998). Functions as selected effects. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 313–334). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlman, M. (2009). Changing the mission of theories of teleology: DOs and DON’Ts for thinking about function. In U. Krohs & P. Kroes (Eds.), Functions in biological and artificial worlds (pp. 17–36). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Perlman, M. (2010). Traits have evolved to function the way they do because of past advantages. In F. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 53–71). Wiley/Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1962). Personal knowledge. Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ponce, M. (1987). La explicación teleológica. UNAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, B. (1998). Why is a wing like a spoon? A pluralistic theory of function. The Journal of Philosophy, 95, 215–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosas, A. (2008). Kant y la ciencia natural de los organismos. Ideas y Valores, 137, 5–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A., & McShea, D. (2008). Philosophy of biology. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, M. (1998). The inference of function from structure in fossils. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purpose (pp. 101–116). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, E. (1945). The directiveness of organic activities. Cambridge at the University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, G. (1998). Self-re-production and functionality: A systems-theoretical approach to teleological explanation. Synthese, 116, 303–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, G. (2007). Functional and developmental constraints on life-cycle evolution. In R. Sansom & R. Brandon (Eds.), Integrating evolution and development (pp. 113–172). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and death. Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2000). The function of fossils: Inference and explanation in functional morphology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31, 191–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wainwright, S., Biggs, W., Currey, J., & Gosline, J. (1980). Mechanical design of organism. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2008). Function. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 349–357). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2004). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weibel, E., Taylor, R., & Bolis, L. (Eds.). (1998). Principles of animal design. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wouters, A. (2007). Design explanation: Determining the constraints on what can be alive. Erkenntnis, 67, 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1972). Explanation and teleology. Philosophy of Science, 39, 204–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. The Philosophical Review, 82, 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Caponi, G. (2023). Function, Adaptation, and Design in Biology. In: Gayon, J., de Ricqlès, A., Dussault, A.C. (eds) Functions: From Organisms to Artefacts. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 32. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-31271-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics