Skip to main content

Abundance and Variety

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Images of the Economy of Nature, 1650-1930

Part of the book series: Evolutionary Biology – New Perspectives on Its Development ((EBNPD,volume 7))

  • 132 Accesses

Abstract

Seventeenth-century “mechanical philosophy”, particularly its Cartesian form, challenged the long-standing belief in final causes as explanatory principles of the order of nature. To many it also seemed to threaten the idea that the world was ruled by Providence. Reactions took many forms. One of them, natural theology, or physico-theology, exerted a pervasive influence on the image of nature for a long time. Order, abundance, variety, compensation and contrivance were key concepts in the attempts to defend a basically optimistic view of what was traditionally called the “economy of nature”. But then an old question returned: how could providential order be reconciled with the existence of suffering, death and destruction? Attitudes towards the problem of evil interacted in various ways with attitudes towards the teleological order of nature. The economy of nature was, in fact, the moral economy of nature. Science and natural philosophy were imbued with moral meaning. The more nature was known, the more God’s, and nature’s, ways to the human being were vindicated. This belief became a tacit assumption which also influenced authors who cannot, strictly speaking, be described as natural theologians or apologetic writers. Its influence lasted for a long time, and survived the so-called Darwinian revolution.

For the invisible things of him from the creation of the world

are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made,

even his eternal power and Godhead

—Paul, Romans, 1: 20

This is the best of all possible worlds, in which the maximum variety coexists with the maximum order.

In the face of this principle all objections drawn from evils that one sees reign in the world dissolve

—Madame du Châtelet

Variety is life. Uniformity is death

—Benjamin Constant

Il mondo è bello perché è vario

(Variety is the spice of life)

—Italian proverb

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Man’s soul was a separate substance of its own. How it could act on the quite different substance of the body remained an open problem (generally referred to as ‘Cartesian dualism’) for a long time for Cartesians themselves.

  2. 2.

    The literature on the Scientific Revolution is enormous. For a well-balanced overall view of the “birth of modern science”, see Rossi (1997).

  3. 3.

    Newton himself was a theologian, although a heretical one, as his manuscripts, which were found only in the twentieth century, reveal. The reference work on Newton is Westfall (1983). See also Mamiani (2022).

  4. 4.

    For instance, Lovejoy used it rather freely in his seminal The Great Chain of Being (1936, repr. 2001). Hodge (1972) uses “popular theodicy” when discussing Robert Chambers’ Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation (1844), and Martin and Watkins (2019: 403) call “Darwinian theodicies” the views of those who explained evil as necessary to evolutionary progress. Leibniz defined “theodicy” as the “doctrine of the justice (that is, the wisdom and goodness) of God”. On Leibniz’ theodicy, see Belaval (1975), Theis (1987), Latzer (1993, 1994), Rutherford (1995), Mormino (2005a, b), Hick (2007), Antognazza (2009, 2014), Rateau (2008). On theodicy in the broad sense, and in general on the problem of evil after Descartes, see Landucci (1986), Fonnesu (1994), Nadler (2010), and Neiman (2015). A very useful overview of the eighteenth-century debates is Fonnesu (2006).

  5. 5.

    Mandelbrote (2020: 75) reports that the Newtonian lexicographer and instrument maker Benjamin Martin enumerated in vol. 5 of his General Magazine of Arts and Sciences (1755–1765) fifteen forms of physico-theology: Helio-theology, Planeto-theology, Seleno-theology, Cometo-theology, Astro-theology, Aero-theology, Hydro-theology, Geo-theology, Phyto-theology, Zoo-theology, Ornitho-theology, Ichthyo-theology, Insecto-theology, Herpeto-theology, and Anthropo-theology. Mandelbrote concludes: “Physico-theology had come to mean any particular study of nature that shed light on divine design”.

  6. 6.

    See Landucci (1984), Chiereghin (1990), McLaughlin (1990). On Schopenhauer, see below, Chap. 3.

  7. 7.

    The classical reference on Timaeus is Cornford (1935). The figure and the role of the Demiurge has been the subject of a number of different interpretations, from Aristotle onwards: was he a god or a craftsman, or both? See Solmsen (1963), Leinkauf and Steel (2005). A well-documented, updated and concise discussion is Rossi Monti (2014).

  8. 8.

    Kant dealt with teleology in many other writings, for instance in On the use of teleological principles in philosophy (Kant 1788) and in On the miscarriage of all philosophical attempts in theodicy (Kant 1791; Engl tr. in Kant 1996).

  9. 9.

    To mention only a few reference works in an enormous literature: Cassirer (1991) (orig. 1944); Larson (1979, 1994), Löw (1980), Lenoir (1982), Fabbri Bertoletti (1990), Friedman (1991), Friedman and Nordmann (2006), Sloan (19792006), Steigerwald (2006a, b), Zammito (2017), Gambarotto (2018). Lenoir’s thesis that Kant’s “teleomechanism” was largely adopted as a regulative approach in the German life sciences has been criticised for overestimating Kant’s influence on empirical scientists (Richards 2002: 229; Zammito 2012). The relation between Kant and vitalism in biology (as represented in Germany mainly by the so-called Göttingen school) is also under constant revision by historians. Another big problem is that of the way Kant was interpreted by the Naturphilosophen, particularly Schelling. On Goethe and Kant, see at least Beyer (1975), Schmidt (1984), Giacomoni (1993) (but in this case, too, the literature is very vast).

  10. 10.

    And on the possible gradual derivation of present forms from original forms generated “by one primal mother”. This hypothesis was “a daring adventure of reason”, but there were few “archeologists of nature” to whom “it had not at times presented itself” (Kant 2000, § 80, and note). See Lovejoy (1968).

  11. 11.

    I say “creative” because Goethe himself did not conceal his doubts concerning Kant’s view of teleology as a regulative principle (Jardine 1988: 330–331).

  12. 12.

    Hume’s warning is often conflated with George Edward Moore’s (1903) criticism of the “naturalistic fallacy”. However, this is incorrect, for the simple reason that Moore had a quasi-Platonic view of good, which was not at all the case with Hume.

  13. 13.

    Brogi (2006) is a concise and very informative overview. The readers who are thirsty for more on this minor problem will find all they want in Meister et al. (2018) and Chignell (2019).

  14. 14.

    There is a vast and complex debate on Plotinus, Neoplatonism and their relation to Plato’s philosophy of nature. In addition to works mentioned in note 7 see Deck (1967), Baltes (1976–1978), Wagner (2002), Opsomer (2005), Chiaradonna and Trabattoni (2009), Wilberding and Horn (2012), Armstrong (2013). Here again, a useful discussion is offered by Rossi Monti (2014).

  15. 15.

    To make just one reference in a vast specialist literature, see Pinsent (2018).

  16. 16.

    There are many important works dealing with Bayle’s decisive role in these debates: van der Lugt (2021) On Bayle see Cantelli (1969), Paganini (1980), Mori (1990, 1996, 1999, 2016), Brogi (1998, 2006), Labrousse (2014a, b), McKenna (2015), Leduc et al. (2015), Bost (2021).

  17. 17.

    Natural evil has often been identified with physical evil, but the two should not be confused. Indeed, a distinction between them was a matter of controversy since Bishop William King (1702) and Leibniz (1710) introduced their tripartite classification of evil in the early eighteenth century. For a discussion of such complex subject and its no less complex implications, see Antognazza (2014).

  18. 18.

    Here it is sufficient to mention some classical works bearing, directly or indirectly, on the relations between the new science, divine design and the natural philosophies of Christian scientists: Houghton (1942), Cassirer (1932; Engl. tr. 2009); H. Fisher (1953), Hurlbutt (1965), Boas Hall (1966), Casini (1967, 1969), Westfall (1973), McGuire (1972), Pacchi (1973), Sina (1976). On deism see Orr (1934) and Lechler (1965; 1st ed 1841). On physico-theology, in addition to works mentioned in text, see Philipp (1957, 1967), Barth (1971), Trepp (2020). A key primary source is Fabricius (1725) (in particular Chap. 8). Glacken (1967; repr. 1990) is still an important reference on the ‘ecological’ aspects of physico-theology.

  19. 19.

    It is worth noting that Linnaeus added to Oeconomia naturae a note containing some quotations from Seneca, the first of which said: “Nature, Fortune, Providence and Fate are manifestations of a sole and same God, who acts in various ways in human affairs”.

  20. 20.

    Olaus Söderberg was one of Linnaeus’ students. Doctoral students acted as their tutor’s mere respondentes, that is they expounded and defended the theses of the praeses. The contents of their dissertations should thus be attributed to Linnaeus. Hereafter, however, the dissertations collected in the Amoenitates academicae (1749–1785) will be referred to by both the name of Linnaeus and the individual respondens, in order to facilitate their location in the collection. The same dissertation will appear twice in the reference list: under Linnaeus’s name and under that of the discussant.

  21. 21.

    Ray (1691): 4–6; Lesser 1742: 122. For Lesser (1692–1754) there are 765 species of insects (including earth worms and water worms, starfish, but excluding slugs, snails, and “shells”), 500 kinds of birds, 1000 “water dwellers”, and 150 snakes (ibid.: 177–122). Lesser’s other physico-teleological works include his influential Testaceo-theologia (1741). On Ray, see Raven (1950), Gillespie (1987), Zeitz (1994), Brooke (2000).

  22. 22.

    Ray (1691): 120–121, 166–167. In fact, the figure in one of Leeuwenhoek’s better-known calculations was 2,730,000 (letter to the Royal Society dated 23 April 1677, excerpts of which are given in Leeuwenhoek 1695: 40–41). Leeuwenhoek was the author of many other calculations on the quantity of animalcules (first observed by him in 1677) in the seminal liquid of various animals and the capacity for the geometrical multiplication of animals and plants (see, for example, 1696: 103; 1697: 15–17, 206–207, 236–237). In his letter of 25 April 1679 he calculated that cod’s milk contains 150 billion animalcules, to wit, more than 10 times the maximum number of men (estimated at 13,385,000,000) that the earth could supposedly contain (1697: 8–11). On this aspect of Leeuwenhoek’s work, see Egerton 1968. Galen’s calculation cited by Ray is in De foetuum formatione, VI, 4.7.

  23. 23.

    For example, Galen’s calculation was taken up by Mersenne (1623, col. 103; cf. Barth 1971: 269), then by Wilkins ([1675] 1693: 81), and by many others until William Paley (1802: 133–134). Hume could not fail to mention it in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Hume 1992, part XII: 455). Leeuwenhoek’s calculations were also popular, albeit to a lesser extent: see, for example, Cheyne (1705) and Abbé Noël-Antoine Pluche’s Le spectacle de la nature (9 tomes, 8 volumes, 1732–1750), which enjoyed enormous success and was reprinted many times until 1888 and translated into many languages.

  24. 24.

    Bonnet took his cue from the following passage in Johann Heinrich Lambert’s (1728–1777) Cosmologische Briefe über die Einrichtung des Weltbaues (1761): “All globes are inhabited and […] all the space in the universe is filled as far as possible with globes. Spaces and gaps could not be left empty in such a perfect work […] Do we not actually see the earth itself all full of life and movement, and Nature everywhere intent on fecundating, and giving life (organiser)?” Bonnet cited from the French translation by J.B. Mérian, Système du monde. Lettres cosmologiques (Berlin 1770), Chap. 3: 24–25. If the earth is full of life why, asked Lambert, should the universe not be full of planets and comets? If the universe is full of planets and comets, says Bonnet, why should it not be full of life?

  25. 25.

    We will return to the strong connection between the principle of plenitude and Bonnet’s, and many others, theory of emboîtement, according to which all the generations of a species were boxed up in original germs (see below: 2.14). It is interesting to note the analogy between this theory of generation and another implication of the principle of plenitude. Leibniz wrote: “There is also nothing to preclude the existence in the universe of animals resembling that one which Cyrano de Bergerac encountered in the sun. The body of this animal being a sort of fluid composed of innumerable small animals, that were capable of ranging themselves in accordance with the desires of the great animal, by this means it transformed itself in a moment, just as it pleased; and the dissolution of continuity caused it no more hurt than the stroke of an oar can cause to the sea” (Theodicy, § 343, in Leibniz 1998). Leibniz was referring to the libertine writer, and famous swordsman, Cyrano de Bergerac’s Les Estats et Empires du Soleil (1662, posthumous). By imagining inhabited worlds Cyrano, like others before and after him, was giving literary expression to an idea to which Leibniz himself would give a metaphysical formulation, as we shall see in § 6. There was a revival of interest in the issue of the plurality of worlds in England as late as 1833, when the philosopher William Whewell admitted that they could exist, although he rejected this idea in 1853 (see Brooke 1977; Yeo 1979, 1986, 1993; Rupke 1983: 213–215).

  26. 26.

    The words “per variar natura è bella” do not come from the works of the Italian poet Torquato Tasso. On the history of this expression, which enjoyed a remarkable success in Italy and abroad, and of its equivalent in modern Italian, “il mondo è bello perché è vario” (literally, the world is beautiful because it is varied), see Pasini (2012) and Becchi (2020).

  27. 27.

    The idea that there are no two identical leaves in the world is a classical topos. We find it, for example, in Seneca’s letter CXIII to Lucilius. On this page of Voltaire it is worth noting that the idea of the infinite diversity of created things is associated with the immutability of the laws of nature, the inscrutability of Providence (or destiny), and universal compensation (“chance does not exist: everything is trial, or punishment, or reward, or providence”). The idea that a plurality of inhabited worlds was a sign of divine power was also old, even if, obviously, not shared by everyone. For example, the Right Rev. John Wilkins (1614–1672), Bishop of Chester, wrote in 1638: “There may be many other species of creatures beside those that are already known in the world; there is a great chain betwixt the nature of men and angels: it may be the inhabitants of the planets are of a middle nature between both these. It is not improbable that God might create some of all kinds, that so he might more completely glorify himself in the works of his power and wisdom” (Wilkins 1802, vol. 1: 102).

  28. 28.

    Grew (1701): 101. See also Derham (1713), Book V, Chap. 9; Book I, Chap. 6; Book V, Chap. 2: 327. The argument of the variety of human faces was already in the Jesuit Leonard Lessius’ De providentia numinis et animi immortalitate libri duo adversus Atheos & Politicos (Amsterdam 1617: 109 ff). It was taken up by Mersenne who extended it to social differences: if all men were rich, application and diligence would count for nothing (1623, Ratio XXIX). The praise of variety is also a major issue in the physician George Cheyne’s Philosophical principles of natural religion: containing the elements of natural philosophy, and the proofs for natural religion, arising from them (1705–1715). Cheyne was an advocate of lacto-vegetarian diet as a treatment of obesity (first of all his own) and the author of the famous The English Malady (1733), in which he dealt with many nervous diseases. On Cheyne’s natural philosophy, see Casini (1967).

  29. 29.

    On the principle of plenitude in the period following that covered in Lovejoy’s classical study, particularly in the nineteenth-century England, see Yeo (1986).

  30. 30.

    Leibniz, Remarques sur le livre de l’origine du mal publié depuis peu en Angleterre, § 7, in Leibniz (1998): 414; Théodicée, § 118 (ibid.: 190). As Lovejoy remarked, this idea was already present in Thomas Aquinas, who wrote that it was false to say that, “since an angel is better than a stone, therefore two angels are better than one angel and a stone […] Although an angel, considered absolutely, is better than a stone, nevertheless two natures are better than one only; and therefore a universe containing angels and other things is better than one containing angels only; since the perfection of the universe is attained essentially in proportion to the diversity of natures in it, whereby the divers grades of goodness are filled, and not in proportion to the multiplication of individuals of a single nature” (cit. in Lovejoy 2001: 77). Lovejoy (ibid.: 362, note 32) also pointed out that the same principle was enunciated by Kant in his Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels (1755), where he said that it was of more consequence to nature to conserve lice as a whole species, worthless as they might be considered, than to conserve a small number of members of a superior species. On the basis of similar considerations many naturalists argued that all species were equally dear to the Creator, that all contributed to the order and beauty of creation, and that the loss of even a single one would damage the entire system. On this same basis some ruled out the extinction of species altogether: see below, Chaps. 4, 5.

  31. 31.

    Bolingbroke countered the arguments of the French mathematician, physicist and philosopher, and president of the Berlin Academy of Science, Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (1698–1759). Chapter 2 of Maupertuis’ Essai de philosophie morale (1749) bore the title “In ordinary life the quantity (la somme) of evils outweighs the quantity of goods”. On Maupertuis, see Tonelli (1987).

  32. 32.

    Whewell (1833): 38. Whewell’s book was the third of the Bridgewater Treatises, a series of eight essays by different authors published in execution of the last will and testament of the Earl of Bridgewater, who left 8000 pounds sterling for the publication of works on “the Power, Wisdom and Goodness of God as manifested in the works of Creation”. On the Bridgewater Treatises, see Topham (1998).

  33. 33.

    “Mayo (Philosophy of Living) quotes Whewell as profound because he says length of days adapted to duration of sleep of man!!! Whole universe so adapted!!! & not man to Planets––instance of arrogance!!” (Darwin 1987, Notebook D: 49). Darwin wrote these words between 23 and 27 August 1838, commenting on the doctor and physiologist Herbert Mayo’s The Philosophy of Living (1837: 136), which referred to Whewell.

  34. 34.

    Anonymous review of Louis Cotte, Leçons d’histoire naturelle sur l’industrie des animaux, pour servir de suite aux le lecons élémentaires naturelle, à l’usage des enfants et des jeunes gens (1799) in Magazin encyclopédique, V année, t. II, 1799: 554–555.

  35. 35.

    Derham (1713), Book VIII, Chap. 6, “Of the Care of Insects about their Young”.

  36. 36.

    The role of ichneumons as “moderators” of the excessive reproduction of Phalaena strobilella had been pointed out by Wilcke and Linnaeus (1760: 26–27), who referred to the observations of another of Linnaeus’ disciples, Daniel Rolander. Ichneumons were mentioned by Darwin’s grandfather Erasmus in his Temple of Nature (1803, Canto IV: 131, lines 33–34) as one of numberless instances of the ever-raging war of nature: “The wing’d Ichneumon for her embryon young/Gores with sharp horn the caterpillar throng”.

  37. 37.

    Derham (1713: 419) mentioned the “Ichneumon-Fly” which “wounded those Nymphae [of insects] and darted its Eggs into them, and so made them the Foster-Mother of its young”. The geologist Charles Lyell, who exerted a strong influence on Darwin, drew heavily from Kirby and Spence (as well as from Wilcke and other Linnaeans) for examples of destructive insects acting as “benefactors” of different species of vegetables and beings “peculiarly instrumental in preserving [their] present abundance”. Ichneumons afforded “a good illustration of the checks and counterchecks which nature has appointed to preserve the balance of power amongst species” (Lyell 1830–1833, II: 133). As we shall see in Chap. 6, Darwin mentioned them as an instance of cruelty which raised doubts on the goodness of God.

  38. 38.

    I am quoting from the second, much larger edition of the work. More himself translated it into Latin (1679), which ensured it a wider circulation.

  39. 39.

    On the question of evil in the eighteenth century, see: Cassirer (1932; Engl. tr. 2009), Kremer (1909), Tsanoff (1931), Hazard (1941, 1946), II, Chap. 3; Crocker (1959, 1963), Meisters et al. (2018), and Chignell (2019). On theodicy, see: Kremer (1909), Wegener (1909), Lempp (1910), Totok (1949, 1986), Mormino (2005a, b), Antognazza (2014).

  40. 40.

    As we have seen, Leibniz approved of this argument. In his comment Law quoted a long extract from Addison (Spectator, No. 519) on the “Scale of Being” (King 1731: 94–95). Addison mentioned Locke’s Essay on Human Understanding, Chap. 6, § 12.

  41. 41.

    This is a revised text of Clarke’s Boyle Lectures (1719). He held another series of these lectures, or sermons, the following year, published in 1721 as Enquiry into the Cause and Origin of Moral Evil.

  42. 42.

    Ibid.: 276–277. Clarke refers to Genesis 1, 28: 9, 1–3. Others, however, derived a different lesson from these and other biblical texts. See below, Chap. 4. On this issue, see Passmore (1974): 4–18. On changing attitudes towards animals in England an indispensable reference is Thomas (1984).

  43. 43.

    Opinion approved by Ray (1691: 127–128), who referred to Cicero. It is interesting to note that More used an anthropomorphic argument to warn against excesses of anthropocentrism. We should not, he argued, see a utility for man in all the characteristics of animals: they also have right to their personal pleasure and also to some frivolity. “Thus fittingly does Nature gratifie all Creatures with accommodations sutable to their temper, and nothing is in vain. Nor are we to cavil at the red pugger’d attire of the Turkey, and the long Excrescency that hangs down over his Bill, when he swells with pride and anger; for it may be a Receptacle for his heated blood, that has such free recourse to his head, or he may please himfelf in it as the rude Indians, whose Jewels hang dangling at their Noses. And if the bird be pleasur’d, we are not to be displeased, being always mindful that Creatures are made to enjoy themselves, as well as to serve us, and it is a gross piece of Ignorance and Rusticity to think otherwise” (More 1655, Book 2, Chap. 11: 139; original spelling, as in subsequent quotations).

  44. 44.

    Here is the whole passage: “And indeed Man seems to be brought into the world on purpose that the rest of the Creation might be improved to the utmost usefulness and advantage; For were it not better that the hides of Beasts and their Flesh should be made so considerable use of as to feed and cloathe Men, then [sic] they should rot and stink upon the ground, and fall short of so noble an improvement, as to be matter for the exercise of the wit of Man, and to afford him the necessary conveniences of life? For if man did not make use of them, they would either dye of Age, or be torn apieces by more cruel Masters […] And being furnish’d with fit Materials to make himself weapons, as well as with natural wit and valour, he did bid battel to the very fiercest of them, and either chased them away into solitudes and deserts, or else brought them under his subjection, and gave laws unto them; under which they live more peaceably, and are better provided for (or at least might if Men were good) then they could be when they were left to the mercy of the Lyon, Bear and Tyger. And what if he do [sic] occasionally and orderly kill some of them for food? their [sic] dispatch is quick, and so less dolorous then the jaw of the Bear, or the teeth of the Lyon, or the tedious Melancholy and sadness of old Age, which would first torture them, and then kill them, and let them rot upon the ground stinking and useless”. (More 1655, Book 2, Chap. 8: 116–117)

  45. 45.

    There have been many versions of the argument that man’s dominion over the animals he feeds on is not only morally acceptable but also advantageous for them. See below, Chap. 4.

  46. 46.

    Derham quotes Pliny (Natural History, VIII, 55): “Benigna circa hoc Natura, innocua & esculenta animalia foecunda generavit” (beneficent nature endowed the edible animals she had generated with great fertility). See also Plato, Protagoras: 320d–321b. Cf. Ray 1691: 101–102; Grew 1701: 99; and many others.

  47. 47.

    Wilcke and Linnaeus (1760): 35–36; cf. 1749: 52. See also Lesser (1742), 1: 121–122. Or fertility as inversely proportional to the cure of the offspring, see, for example, Pluche (1768), 2: 16.

  48. 48.

    Linnaeus not only recognised the inevitability of the circle but also justified it in terms of the circularity of natural processes, which was itself a proof of God’s greatness. As the observer gradually advances in his knowledge of nature, he glimpses order “in the great confusion”, an order so admirable that, “struck by admiration, he admits that it is difficult and indeed vain to search for a beginning and an end in the divine works, as […] everything moves in a circle” (Wilcke and Linnaeus 1760: 18). On Linnaeus’ view of nature, see Hagberg (1952), von Hofsten (1957), Querner (1980), Petry’s Introduction to Linnaeus 2001 (which contains a rich bibliography).

  49. 49.

    Biberg and Linnaeus (1749): 35–36; cf. 52–53. Pliny (Natural History, VIII, 55), Derham’s Physico-theology and Petrus van Musschenbroek’s Oratio de sapientia divina (1744) are mentioned or referred to. Cf. Westermann and Linnaeus 1743: 448–449; Wilcke and Linnaeus (1760): 23, 36.

  50. 50.

    Kirby and Spence (1815–1826), 1: 176, 194. Darwin made a pencil mark in the margin next to both examples in his copy of the work (University Library, Cambridge).

  51. 51.

    On Paley see Le Mahieu (1976).

  52. 52.

    Horrenda venatio, infanda laniena, bellum veluti omnium in omnes, horrenda laniena, laniena et bellum omium in omnes are among the terms used (Söderberg and Linnaeus 1748: 541, 542–543; Biberg and Linnaeus 1749: 52; Wilcke and Linnaeus 1760: 36).

  53. 53.

    Cf. Wilcke and Linnaeus (1760): 17–18: “If a man, naked as at the moment of creation or when he was newborn, but endowed with mature judgment as in the best period of his life, found himself fallen into this world, […] and contemplated carefully, with all his senses, the terraqueous globe almost as if it were a new refuge, he would observe that the earth is covered with innumerable different vegetables which, mixed with each other in the greatest confusion, are treated wretchedly by worms, insects, fish, amphibians, birds and mammals. He would see that not only do these beings devour the most beautiful flowers but that they, exercising an extraordinary reciprocal tyranny, tear each other apart without pity. In short, he would see nothing but a war of all against all (bellum omnium in omnes) and would find himself undefended and so exposed to the violence of the majority of beings that, hesitating and uncertain, he would hardly find a place, if any, where he could feel protected”.

  54. 54.

    Order is the purpose, and reproduction, conservation and destruction are the means. “In order for natural things created to persist over time in a continuous series, the wisdom of the supreme Divinity has arranged for all living beings to do their utmost uninterruptedly to generate new individuals, and all natural things reciprocally to offer each other help to favour the conservation of all species, and, lastly, death and destruction of the one always to serve the re-establishment of the other” (Biberg and Linnaeus 1749: 2). Cf. Linnaeus 1767–1770, I: 18: “The economy of nature consists of generation, conservation and destruction, so that the work of the Creator is conserved intact, and all of Nature conspires to this end […] The destruction of the one becomes the restoration of the other, when, due to a shortage of corpses [to feed on], life finds sustenance through the fatigues of the hunt. Hence the universal robbery, because the liveliest escape thanks to their weapons, and their defences, and to diverse movements or exhalations, while the weak succumb and the most vigorous flee rapidly. Thus the work of nature shines in perennial luxuriance”.

  55. 55.

    “The main activities of the citizens of Nature are: (1) to multiply their species, so that there are enough members to perform its functions; (2) to maintain the balance between animal species and vegetable species, so that the general proportion is preserved; to prune plants annually, so that every year the scene is renewed; to repress the wrong [sorts of] creatures, so that the regular ones are not ousted; to remove the sick, the dead, impurity, dirt, whatever is stagnant, acid or putrid, so that the splendour of the palace shines; (3) to avoid death, so that the society does not remain deserted” (Linnaeus 1767–1770, I: 18).

  56. 56.

    Earlier, however, Linnaeus had said the opposite: “Wild beasts have not been created for the sustenance of other creatures at all, but the weakest in function of the rapacious; and thus the tiger has not been created for the cow, nor the vultures for the hen, but the contrary. All the work of creation proceeds in the same way from insects, birds and quadrupeds to man” (Söderberg and Linnaeus 1748: 548). But the context makes it clear that he had food relations in mind, and not the hierarchy of duties and prerogatives. In this sense should be also interpreted the statement that “animals support themselves on vegetables, vegetables on minerals (terrestribus), minerals on the earth” (Linnaeus 1767–1770, I: 10; cf. Pan Suecicus, § 5, in Ramsbottom 1959: 156). Whatever the case, many considered Linnaeus’ ‘official position’ to be the one presented in the passage cited in the text. Suffice it to mention here the illustrious example of Kant (Critique of the Faculty of Judgement, § 82) and that of the Scottish naturalist John Fleming (1822, I: 52). Fleming’s passage referring to Linnaeus caught Darwin’s attention, who made a mark in the margin of his copy of the work (Darwin Archives, University Library, Cambridge). On Fleming, see Rehbock (1985).

  57. 57.

    On the beneficial effects of the “law of poison”, see also Linnaeus’ Pan Suecicus (1749) in Ramsbottom (1959): 156, 163.

  58. 58.

    Wilcke and Linnaeus (1760): 20–21. Comparisons of this kind were not infrequent among eighteenth-century naturalists. Bonnet (1764, I, part V: 188) compared the oaks, which provide support for ivy, to the great lords who offer protection to the poor and weak.

  59. 59.

    Söderberg and Linnaeus (1748): 550, 552, 563. Cf. Gedner and Linnaeus (1752): 234): “We have been created for the glory of the Creator, which only manifests itself if we know Him through Revelation, or through Nature, which is the work of creation”. And Biberg and Linnaeus (1749: 56–57): “If we follow the series of things created and consider with what forethought they have been made one for another, we see that all things have in the end been made for man, so that, admiring the works of the Creator, he exalts His glory and jointly enjoys all the things he needs to spend life in comfort and joy”.

  60. 60.

    The Sami inhabitants of Lappland, where he made an important voyage of exploration, enjoyed perfect health because they were ignorant of “inflaming alcoholic beverages, tobacco, tea, coffee, sugar, silk, most spices” (Koerner 1999: 71, 75, 130). Linnaeus criticised luxury food and fashionable habits, including almonds, oysters, raisins, wall-paper, music concerts, maid servants, oil paintings, plaster, “large windows”, “coffee and chocolate, jams and confections, wines and lemonades, jewels and pearls, gold and silver, silk and pomade, dances and parties, music and theater”. He was in favour of bans on import of foreign food, and its replacement by homeland products. Coffee, for instance, was not only a plant that could never be successfully planted in Sweden, since its homeland was on the equator, but also, as Koerner sums it up (ibid., 130), “a French fashion and therefore a moral and medical hazard”. It could be replaced by a brew of “boiled water mixed with burnt peas, beechnuts, almond, beans, maize, wheat, or toasted bread”.

  61. 61.

    For example, lice absorb the excess humours on children’s heads; dogs prefer to leave their foul-smelling and infected excrement on stones or tree trunks or other elevated places, so that plants are not corrupted; insect bites force quadrupeds to move and to keep their legs exercised; mosquito larvae deodorise and purify stagnant water by “eating up the putrefaction”; and so forth (Biberg and Linnaeus 1749: 55).

  62. 62.

    Rediscovered in 1844, they were partially published in 1848 by Elias Magnus Fries (2nd edn. 1878), then in a revised and expanded edition by Knut Hagberg in 1878 (2nd edn. 1960). The complete edition was edited by A.K.E. Malmeström and L. Gustafssson (Linnaeus 1968). German and English translations are available (Linnaeus 1981, 2001, respectively). On the story, the characteristics, the contents of the manuscript and its sources, see Geoffroy (1861), Malmeström (1926 (in particular, 171–186, 191–208, 236–246), 1942, 1981), Gustafsson (1981), Lepenies (1981, 1982), Petry in Linnaeus (2001).

  63. 63.

    On the Lisbon earthquake, see below, Chap. 3.

  64. 64.

    The English translation (1983, repr. 1994) of Lindroth (1965–1966) bore the title The Two Faces of Linnaeus. Perhaps “bivalence” or “ambiguity” would be better than the “duplicity”, which I used. Whatever term we find appropriate, Linnaeus remains a profoundly enigmatic figure. On Linnaeus’ religiosity, see also Malmeström (1926, 1942).

  65. 65.

    As we saw, Linnaeus expressed himself differently in 1752. Diaeta naturalis and other writings contain some even less orthodox opinions. In his Clavis medicinae duplex, exterior et interior (1766), for example, Linnaeus represented the soul as a material substance, inseparable from the body and located between the cerebellum and the medulla oblongata. Not surprisingly Linnaeus incurred criticism by some theologians: see Ehnmark (1951–1952), Wikman (1970): 20, 93; Lindroth (1994).

  66. 66.

    Particularly Seneca. Cf. Wikman (1970: 88): “We have here, then, purely Stoical virtues in a Christianized paraphrase”.

  67. 67.

    The influence of Leibniz and Wolff was mediated by the astronomer Anders Celsius (1701–1744) and the mathematician Samuel Klingenstjerna (1698–1765). Among the physico-theologians who influenced Linnaeus were the already cited Musschenbroek and Derham (whose Physico-Theology had two Swedish editions, in 1736 and 1760), the physiologist and theologian Johann Albert Fabricius (1668–1736), who translated into German Derham’s Astro-Theology (1728) and Physico-Theology (1730), and another German, the already cited pastor Lesser, author of the Insecto-Theologia (1738) and the Testaceo-Theologia (1744), who corresponded with Linnaeus. Between 1740 and 1760 Sweden witnessed a blossoming of physico-theological writings, many of which were imbued with Wolffism. One of the most representatives of this literature was Carl Gustav Löwenhielm (1701–1768). He divided the study of universal economy in oeconomia divina, or naturalis (stora naturliga oeconomien), oeconomia publica (allmänna hushållning) and oeconomia privata (enskilte hushållning). He placed great emphasis on the balance of nature (Lepenies 1982: 18). Linnaeus also drew on the Theologisk og historisk Afhandling om den guddomelige Giengiaeldelses Ret eller just talionis divinum (Theological and Historical Treatise on the Divine Right of Compensation or jus talionis divinum, Copenhagen 1758) by Christian Friis, which was translated into Swedish in 1763. On Linnaeus’ physico-theological sources, see also Ehnmark (1951–1952), Frängsmyr (1971–1972), and Petry in Linnaeus (2001).

  68. 68.

    On Paracelsism in Sweden, see Lindroth (1943). In Linneaus’ Clavis there are also traces of numerology and Pythagoraeanism, which suggests that his use of dichotomies and pentatomies was anything but instrumental. Other examples are given by Lindroth 1994. Linnaeus’ language reveals traces of hermeticism, and of an initiatory notion of natural philosophy. He considered himself not just the prince of botanists, but as God’s anointed. Finally, one should not underestimate the influence of the Lutheran theologian Johann Arndt’s (1555–1621) Vom wahren Christentume (1605–1610), which ran through many editions and reprints, was translated into Swedish in 1647, and generated much controversy.

  69. 69.

    Svagelski (1981: 185–220) argued that compensation was not a cardinal concept in Buffon’s view of nature, as Buffon often stressed imbalances in compensation. It seems excessive, however, to devote refined analysis to what often turns out to be more of a rhetorical topos than a philosophical concept, which Buffon used—like its contrary—as it suited him.

  70. 70.

    “Le cochon” (in Histoire naturelle, 5, 1755: 102–103). Hereafter Buffon’s Histoire naturelle (1749–1767, 15 vols.) will be referred to as HN. Buffon then goes on to say: “[The pig] obviously has useless parts, or rather parts of which it cannot make use, digits in which all the bones are perfectly formed and which nevertheless do not serve any purpose. Nature is therefore very far from submitting to final causes in the composition of beings; why should she not add superabundant parts sometimes, since she so often misses putting essential parts there? […] Why does one want each part to be useful to the others and necessary to the whole in each individual? Is it not enough that, placed together, they do not harm each other? […] All that can subsist together survives; and perhaps there are, in the majority of beings, fewer related, useful, or necessary parts than indifferent, useless, or superabundant ones” (ibid.: 103–104; English transl. in Roger 1997: 292–293). Whenever possible, I have used the translation of Buffon’s texts in Roger (1997), with only a few minor alterations.

  71. 71.

    “Les toucans”, in Histoire naturelle des oiseaux (Buffon 1770–1783), 7, 1780: 109–110.

  72. 72.

    In spite of his criticism of anthropocentrism, Buffon often got carried away by his love for rhetorical effect, to the point of indulging in anthropomorphic vocabulary, especially in his descriptions of animals. Vivid instances are given in Roger (1997: 282–283), who remarks that, by doing so, Buffon was not consistent with his own view of animals. Far from humanising them, he considered them as “mere machines, only insensitive automata”: they had feelings, “even in a higher degree than we have”; they had sensations, and even “consciousness of their current existence”, but they did not think (Buffon 1753: 40–41).

  73. 73.

    We can imagine how Bonnet would have reacted to other examples of beneficial compensation in the Histoire naturelle. To mention only one of them, Buffon (1766: 357) says that fierce animals reproduce rapidly and hence have always been a danger for man, but fortunately Nature has only made timid animals intelligent enough to unite in groups.

  74. 74.

    On the picture of taxonomic relations that emerges from this passage, see Barsanti (1985): 123, note 136. On the concept of species in Buffon, see Barsanti (1983), Chap. 2; Barsanti (1984), Sloan (1976, 1973, 19791987).

  75. 75.

    Buffon compared the invasions of mice, locusts and so forth to the great barbaric invasions: “In times when man was still half savage and, like animals, subject to all the laws, and also to the excesses, of nature, have we not witnessed these floods of the human species, the Norse, the Alans, the Huns, the Goths, the peoples, or rather the tribes of animals with human face, without a home and without a name, emerge suddenly from their caves, advance like wild herds, overwhelm everything without any other strength than numbers, ransack cities, overturn empires and, after having destroyed nations and devasted the earth, repopulate it with men equally new and even more barbarous than themselves?” (Buffon 1756a: 248). For Buffon these great movements of men, like the great invasions of mice and locusts, are only “small vicissitudes in the normal course of living nature”.

  76. 76.

    That is, the two types of death are more or less necessary according to whether the species are more or less “crowded”.

  77. 77.

    The notion of a constant quantity of life on earth is an outcome of Buffon’s doctrine of matter and life. The quantity of life is constant because the quantity of “organic molecules” is fixed. They are the indestructible units of living matter. They are able to unite to inorganic matter to form organised bodies. They can be assimilated by the organisms and pass continually from one body to another, thus renewing life. The body of every animal or vegetable is a “mould” (moule), which “assimilates the organic molecules of all animals or vegetables destroyed by death or consumed by time, without distinction”. The inorganic parts which entered into the composition will revert to the common mass of inorganic (brute) matter; the organic parts, which are “perennial”, will be taken up by organized bodies. First, they are sucked up by plants, and then absorbed by animals that feed on vegetables. They serve to the development, maintenance and growth of both animals and vegetables, they constitute their life, and, circulating continually from body to body, animate all organised beings. On the earth, in the air and in the water therefore there is “a given quantity of organic matter that nothing can destroy; at the same time there exists a given number of moulds able to assimilate it, that are continually destroyed and renewed, and the total number of these moulds or individuals is always the same, always proportionate to the quantity of living matter. If such matter were superabundant, if it were not, at all times, employed in equal measure and absorbed entirely by existing moulds, new one would be formed, and new species would appear, because the living matter cannot remain inactive, indeed is always active, and it is sufficient that it unites with organic parts for it to form organised bodies. The form of Nature itself depends on this vast combination, or rather on this invariable proportion” (Buffon 1765: vii–viii, ix). On the concept of organic molecules, see Casini 1958; on Buffon’s theory of life and reproduction, see Roger’s seminal work (1971: 527–584) and Gayon ed. (1992).

  78. 78.

    The obstacles to human population growth are abandonment, mutilation, infanticide, abortion and religious celibacy.

  79. 79.

    The imprint (empreinte) or mould (moule) is the “type” of a species. “Its main features are carved in indelible and perennial characters”, but its “accessory touches” vary, as “no individual is identical to another and no species exists without a great number of varieties” (Buffon 1765, ix–x). The question of whether Buffon was an evolutionist is extremely tricky, all the more so because he changed the meaning he attached to the terms “species” and “genus” (Roger 1997: 325–329) without warning the reader. Fortunately, it is not my job to deal with the question. I can only refer to Daudin’s (1926) classical work, Casini (1958), Barsanti (1983, Chap. 2), Sloan (1973, 1976, 1987), and above all Roger (1997) (esp. Chap. 19).

  80. 80.

    I have used the English translation of this text in Roger (1997): 241.

  81. 81.

    Virey contributed to Charles-Nicolas-Sigisbert Sonnini de Manoncourt’s 1798–1814 edition of Buffon’s Histoire naturelle and wrote many articles for the Nouveau dictionnaire d’histoire naturelle he edited (1st edn., Paris, Déterville, 1803–1804; 2nd edn. 1816–1819). He also published an Histoire naturelle du genre humain (1800).

  82. 82.

    A voracious reader, Virey pushed his strong tendency to eclecticism to the point of endorsing contradictory opinions “with the same force of persuasion”, to the point of deserving the definition of “champion of volte-face” (Blanckaert 1988: 99, 125; same judgement in Rey 1988: 33, and Laurent 1988: 61). He seems to have been the first to use “évolution” in the modern sense, and he was the first critic of Lamarck (Corsi 1987). In his Discours Virey rejects spontaneous generation, vindicating an immaterial “life principle”, final causes and the providential design of an “infinitely intelligent Supreme Cause”. He believed in the radical separation of brute matter and animate matter; yet he argued that the “moral” was nothing but “the physical which escapes vulgar eyes”. He attributed sensibilité to the most elementary forms of animality and saw even in vegetables an “obscure sensitivity”, a “sort of instinct”, “a sort of life, or rather a sort of spirit, conservative and provident, as in animals” (Virey 1801: 13, 33–34).

  83. 83.

    It is no coincidence that Virey manifested sympathy for Bernardin de Saint-Pierre (see below, § 15), albeit specifying that he considered many of his opinions untenable (Virey 1801: 12, note).

  84. 84.

    The law of Sparta is also mentioned by Rousseau (1992: 21), who can hardly be described as a supporter of competitive capitalism.

  85. 85.

    On Virey’s equation of physical beauty and moral superiority, and that of ugliness and physical and spiritual inferiority, see Blanckaert’s (1988: 156–157) shrewd remarks.

  86. 86.

    “Ephemeral roses that shine for the space of dawn” is a reference to the famous line of François de Malherbe’s Consolation à M. du Périer sur la mort de sa fille (1599): “Mais elle était du monde, où les plus belles choses /ont le pire destin; /et, rose, elle a vécu ce que vivent les roses, /l’espace d’un matin”. Virey (1799: 36–37) has the same message as the passage quoted in text, but with a slightly different pitch: “The end that nature imposes on all beings that she has created is the maximum possible reproduction. As it is necessary to destroy in order to live, when the total of dying organised bodies is higher, the general quantity of life must increase in the same proportion, in order to re-establish equilibrium. We live only to destroy, and to form beings of which we will then become the prey: this a universal yoke, which unquestionably weighs on all our heads, and the river of life drags us without respite towards our last dwelling place in the ocean of death. For nature living is only nourishing oneself in order to reproduce: this is the inevitable circle that she forces us to take. Weak instruments of its immortal operations, momentary springs that move a hidden machinery, mortal and pitiful toys in her tyrannical hands, dare we believe ourselves her rivals!”

  87. 87.

    ‘Animalculists’ believed that the organism was preformed in one of the “sperm worms”, whereas “ovists” believed that the organism was preformed in the egg (ovum).

  88. 88.

    Bonnet to Spallanzani, 13 January 1781, in Bonnet 1971, 425–426. Bonnet was responding to Spallanzani’s letters of 12 and 15 December 1780 (Spallanzani 1958–1964, II, 352, 364).

  89. 89.

    Spallanzani, “Judgement, and Rebuttal of Sperm Worms” (“Sentenza, e confutazione de’ vermicelli spermatici”, draft of a lesson at the University of Pavia (probably November 1791, Biblioteca Municipale “A. Panizzi” of Reggio Emilia; Mss. Regg. B 98, 23v).

  90. 90.

    Needham (1750): 155. On Needham, see Roger (1971): 503–520. Obviously, the argument of waste also affects those who only attribute a nutritive function to tiny animals (Bonnet) or a stimulating function (Spallanzani: see Bonnet to Spallanzani, 29 November 1780, in Bonnet 1971, 409). On the disagreement between Bonnet and Spallanzani regarding the role of seminal liquid in fertilisation, see Bernardi (1986). According to Needham, matter is a compound of two agents, both of them simple and unextended, a principle of movement and a principle of resistance, which act one against the other. As a consequence, all effects in the universe are but the result of action and reaction, and “the life of the universe is a counter-balanced action” (cit. in Starobinski 1999: 47). Starobinski suggests that in these words there can be an echo of Cudworth’s doctrine of immaterial “plastic natures” charged by God to move matter in a regular and ordered way. He also sees in these and other statements of Needham “the source of the idea of compensation, which will be upheld by authors of optimist systems such as Antoine de La Salle or Pierre-Hyacinthe Azaïs” (ibid.: 47, 371 note 78).

  91. 91.

    Voltaire (1756), II: line 121 (Aux élémens unis dans leur utile guerre). Voltaire will be discussed later, in Chap. 3.

  92. 92.

    The reader must be patient until Chaps. 8 and 9.

  93. 93.

    The entire passage is full of warlike images and military terms. On Bayle, see the secondary literature in note 16.

  94. 94.

    Svalgelski (1981) discusses all four in detail. La Salle, Azaïs and Robinet are discussed in Rosso (1954a, b, 19691977). On La Salle, see Thuillier (1964). On Azaïs, see Schwieger (1913). On Formey, see Crispini (1989). On Robinet, who is the most studied, see also Damiron (1858–1864), II: 480–539; Vernière (1954), II: 642–652; Roger (1971): 642–657; Solinas (1987). In De la nature Robinet also developed the idea of nature as a gradation of beings, from stones to man, formed by the variations of a single “prototype”. The prototype was “a germ which tends naturally to develop itself”. Each degree of development is a variation of the prototype, “a new combination of the primitive universal plan”. The only difference between stone, plant and animal is “the measure in which they participate in that essence. […] A stone, an oak, a horse, a monkey, a man are graduated variations of the prototype which began to form itself with the least possible number of elements”. See Crocker (1968: 134–135), from which these quotations are taken. We will return to Robinet in Chap. 4. According to Berthelot (1929), it was from Robinet that Goethe drew his influential idea of the prototype of animal form Urthier (“original animal”). Hegel identified the Urthier with Man. Man, he said, is “the unit of measure” of the other forms of life, because it is only the most complex, developed and “perfect” that can be the basis on which rationally to understand the less developed: “it makes no sense to start from infusoria” (Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, § 368 Z, in Hegel 1970, vol. 9: 502–516). It was conceptual understanding, not empirical explanation in terms of efficient causes, that Hegel pursued. Philosophy could not in the least dispense with taking into account the results of science. Quite the contrary, its task was to bring them to the conceptual unity towards which they all “instinctively conspired”, by revealing their inner logic and rationality, and by connecting them in a general system. In striving after this achievement, it brought to light what scientists themselves often neglected, or were unaware of, because they did not reflect enough on the very categories and concepts they used. This is why Hegel, who rejected the “highly talented Frenchman” Lamarck’s transformism, also objected to the conceptual foundations of Cuvier’s fixism: it is impossible, he said, to establish clear-cut separations between genera, as living nature is too rich and varied to allow such rigid distinctions (ibid., §§ 250–251). As regards Lamarck, his theory of adaptation was ingenious and interesting from an empirical point of view, but faulty from the perspective of conceptual understanding: “However, as often as a thick coat of fur may be found to go together with northerly latitudes, and that the structure of a fish is to be found to go together with water, and that the structure of birds goes together with air, nevertheless the concept of a thick covering of fur is neither contained in the concept of the north, nor does the concept of the sea contain the concept of the structure of fish, nor does the concept of air contain the concept of the structure of birds” (Hegel 2018: 152). Hegel (1970, vol. 2, § 249, § 252 Z: 37–40) did use “evolution” and “involution” in relation to the “stages of nature”, but he had a conceptual structure, not an actual transformation, in mind. Likewise, he did not object to the notions of a scale of organic forms and of a successive appearance of them on earth, provided they were understood in a merely ideal sense, as in the case of Goethe’s metamorphosis of plants, which he accepted (ibid., vol. 9, § 345 Z: 411). Life could not be explained by mechanical or chemical laws. This digression on Hegel and the sciences is much indebted to Bodei (1975), Chap. 2.

  95. 95.

    In a 1792 address to the Convention nationale, Bernardin de Saint-Pierre advocated the institution of a ménagerie in addition to the botanical garden and the cabinet of comparative anatomy, on the grounds of political and moral as well as scientific reasons (Rey 1992; Blanckaert et al. 1997; Baratay and Hardouin-Fugier 1998; Spary 2000; Baratay 2010; Serna 2017). On Bernardin de Saint-Pierre, see Maury (1896), Roule (1930). For a general discussion of the moral and social aspects of the French debate in this period on the relations between natural history, the treatment of animals, their domestication and the image of man’s place in nature, see Piazzesi (2023). I am very grateful to Benedetta Piazzesi for allowing me to read her manuscript before publication.

  96. 96.

    Unlike Newton, La Salle held that the reaction occurs when the action has ceased (1788, 1: 132–133).

  97. 97.

    To be fair, we should note that La Salle applies these recommendations to himself. “My complexion, cold and slothful”, he wrote when presenting himself to the reader in the Preface, “suffers from long stagnation and peace; unrest and a war are necessary for my health” (La Salle 1788, I: xiii). On the widespread belief that war is a beneficent stimulus and a remedy against man’s softening up, see La Vergata (1990), Chap. 3, § 4.

  98. 98.

    The edition of the first volume of Robinet which I used bears the indication “troisième edition” and the date 1766. The second volume bears the date 1763. The third and fourth bear the date 1766.

  99. 99.

    Then work and physical and intellectual effort are necessary: “the gods sold every thing to mortals at the price of labour; not out of envy, but from kindness, for the greatest enjoyment of existence, the sensation of active striving powers, lies in this very struggle, in this striving after the comforts of ease” (Herder 1966: 219). However, Herder argues that “Want alone, even when there is no deficiency of powers in a nation to obey it’s demands, seems equally incapable of producing civilisation: for as soon as the Indolence of man has rendered him contented under his Necessities, and both together have begotten the child he names Convenience, he persists in his condition, and cannot be impelled to improve it without difficulty” (ibid.: 202). On the ethics of effort and the theme of human laziness and the “need for a whip”, see La Vergata (1990), Chap. 3, § 4.

  100. 100.

    Verra (1971: 49). Verra emphasises the importance for Herder’s philosophy of history of the concept of nemesis he developed in his Nemesis (1785) and Gott (1787), in which Herder credited the Swiss mathematician and physicist Johann Heinrich Lambert for giving that “fundamental law” a physical and mathematical formulation.

  101. 101.

    For instance Erasmus’ “asserting the progression of every other race of animal from some lower species” and his “absurd notion […] of Man’s having progressed from an Ouran Outang state” (cit. in King-Hele 1984: 144). In his “Notes of Stillingfleet” Coleridge coined the verb “to darwinize” to refer to such wild “mode of reasoning”: “What! did Sir W[alter] R[aleigh] believe that a male and female ounce (and, if so, why not two tigers and lions, &c.?) would have produced, in course of generations, a cat, or a cat a lion? This is Darwinizing with a vengeance” (Coleridge 1875: 423). Coleridge was commenting on Stillingfleet’s reporting of Raleigh’s “prudent caution, that men ought not to take animals of a mixed nature, as mules or hyenas, nor such as differ in size and shape from each other, as the cat of Europe and ounce of India, into the several species of animals”. On Erasmus Darwin, see Potter (1925), Robinson (1954), Garfinkle (1955), Harrison (1971), Hassler (1973a, b), King-Hele (1977, 1986, 1999, 2014), McNeil (1987), Uglow (2002). A concise presentation is Weber (2014). Elliott (2003) argues that Erasmus influenced Herbert Spencer’s development more than Spencer acknowledged.

  102. 102.

    E. Darwin (1803), I: lines 3–4, 377; II: lines 8, 33; IV: line 146. See also expressions such as “eternal war the Gout and Mania wage” (II: line 361) and such like. Not to mention poetic metaphors such as “warring winds” (I: line 53) or “struggling ships” (I: line 360).

Bibliography

  • Ackrill JL (1981) Aristotle the philosopher. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Antognazza MR (2009) Leibniz. An intellectual biography. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Antognazza MR (2014) Leibniz’s metaphysical evil revisited. In: Newlands S, Jorgensen L (eds) New essays on Leibniz’s theodicy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 112–134

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Appel TA (1987) The Cuvier–Geoffroy debate: French biology in the decades before Darwin. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong AH (2013) The architecture of the intelligible universe in the philosophy of Plotinus. An analytical and historical study. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • von Arnim H (1903–1905) Stoicorum veterum fragmenta. Teubner, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltes M (1976–1978) Die Weltentstehung des platonischen Timaios nach den antiken Interpreten. Brill, Leiden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baratay É, Hardouin-Fugier É (1998) Zoos. Histoire des jardins zoologiques en Occident (XVIe–XXe siècle). La Découverte, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Baratay É (2010) Une révolution née de la Révolution. In: Lachance M (ed) L’animal dans la spirale des besoins de l’humain. Yvon Blais, Cowansville, pp 3–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsanti G (1983) La mappa della vita. Teorie della natura e teorie dell’uomo in Francia, 1750–1780. Guida, Naples

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsanti G (1984) De Linné à Buffon: deux visions de la nature et de l’histoire naturelle. Revue de synthèse IIIe série 113–114:83–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsanti G (1985) Introduzione. In: Buffon G-L Teoria della natura. Scritti metodologici e sistematici. Introduzione, traduzione e cura di Giulio Barsanti. Roma Theoria

    Google Scholar 

  • Barth HM (1971) Atheismus und Orthodoxie. Analysen und Modelle christlicher Apologetik im 17. Jahrhundert. Göttingen (Forschungen zur systematischen und ökumenischen Theologie, 26). Vandenkoeck & Ruprecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayle P (1734) Ovide. In: Dictionnaire historique et critique (1695–1702). Cinquième édition, revue, corrigée et augmentée de remarques critiques, avec la vie de l’Auteur, par Mr. Des Maizeaux. Tome quatrième. M-R. par la Compagnie des Libraires, Amsterdam, pp 433–450

    Google Scholar 

  • Becchi A (2020) Leibniz, il teatro della natura e le metamorfosi del vivente. Intersezioni 40(2):175–202

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser (2002) German idealism: the struggle against subjectivism, 1781–1801. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Belaval Y (1975) Leibniz. Initiation à sa philosophie, 4th edn. Vrin, Paris (1st edn. 1955 with the title Pour connaître la pensée de Leibniz. Bordas, Paris)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernardi W (1986) Le metafisiche dell’embrione. Scienze della vita e filosofia da Malpighi a Spallanzani. Olschki, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernardin de Saint-Pierre J-H (1792) Études de la nature. Quatrième édition, revue et corrigée par l’Auteur, de l’imprimerie de Didot Jeune, Paris (1st edn. 1784)

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthelot R (1929) Lamarck et Goethe: l’évolutionnisme de la continuité au début du XIXe siècle. Rev Metaphys Morale 36:285–341

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyer H (1975) Natur und Kunst. Goethe und Schelling. Goethe Jahrbuch 92:9–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Biberg IJ, Linnaeus, C (1749) Oeconomia naturae. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 2 (1751), pp 1–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair A, von Greyerz K (eds) (2020) Physico-theology: religion and science in Europe, 1650–1750. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanckaert C (1988) J. J. Virey, observateur de l’homme (1800–1825). In: Bénichou C, Blanckaert C (eds) Julien-Joseph Virey: naturaliste et anthropologue. Vrin, Paris, pp 97–182

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanckaert C, Cohen C, Corsi P (eds) (1997) Le Muséum au premier siècle de son histoire. Éditions du Muséum National d’Histoire Naturelle, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Boas Hall M (1966) Robert Boyle on natural philosophy. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Boas G (1972) Warfare in the cosmos. Diogenes 20:38–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bodei R (1975) Sistema ed epoca in Hegel. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolingbroke HS-J (1841) The works of Lord Bolingbroke. With a life, prepared expressly for this edition. Containing additional information relative to his personal and public character, selected from the best authorities. In four volumes. Carey & Hart, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Bondí R (2001) L’onnipresenza di Dio. Saggio su Henry More. Rubbettino, Soveria Mannelli

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet C (1762) Considérations sur les corps organisés. In: Oeuvres d’histoire naturelle et de philosophie, vol 1. de l’imprimerie de Samuel Fauché, Neuchâtel

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet C (1764) Contemplation de la nature. In: Oeuvres d'histoire naturelle et de philosophie, vol. 4 (two tomes). de l’imprimerie de Samuel Fauché, Neuchâtel

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet C (1769) Palingénesie philosophique, ou idées sur l’état passé et sur l’état futur des êtres vivans. In: Oeuvres d'histoire naturelle et de philosophie, vol 7. de l’imprimerie de Samuel Fauché, Neuchâtel

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet C (1971) Lettres à M. l’Abbé Spallanzani. Edizione critica condotta sugli originali, introduzione e note di C. Castellani. Prefazione di Jean Rostand. Episteme, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Bost H (2021) Bayle calviniste libertin. Champion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdier F (1969) Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire versus Cuvier: the campaign for paleontological evolution. In: Schneer CJ (ed) Toward a history of geology. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle R (1688) A disquisition about the final causes of natural things: wherein it is inquired, whether, and (if at all) with what cautions, a naturalist should admit them? Printed by H.C. for John Taylor, London (also in The works of the honourable Robert Boyle. A new edition [edited by Thomas Birch], 5: 392–452. Printed for W. Johnston, S. Crowder, T. Payne, etc. 1772). London. Repr. 1966, George Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung, Hildesheim)

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle R (1772) The works of the honourable Robert Boyle. A new edition [edited by Thomas Birch], vol 5, London, pp 392–452. London: printed for W. Johnston, S. Crowder, T. Payne, etc. Repr. 1966, George Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogi S (1998) Teologia senza verità. Bayle contro i “rationaux”. Franco Angeli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogi S (2006) I filosofi e il male. Storia della teodicea da Platone ad Auschwitz. Franco Angeli, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (1977) Natural theology and the plurality of worlds: observations on the Brewster-Whewell debate. Ann Sci 34:2 21–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (1989a) Science and the fortunes of natural theology: some historical perspectives. Zygon 24:2–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (1989b) Scientific thought and its meaning for religion: the impact of French science on British natural theology, 1827–1859. Rev Synth 4:33–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (2000) Wise men now think otherwise: John Ray, natural theology and the meanings of anthropocentrism. Notes Rec R Soc 54(2):199–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (2014) Science and religion: some historical perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1st edn. 1991)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brooke JH (2020) Was physico-theology bad theology and bad science? In: Blair A, von Greyerz K (eds) Physico-theology. Religion and science in Europe, 1650–1750. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 23–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1749–1767) Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, avec la description du Cabinet du Roi, 15 vols. Imprimerie Royale, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1749–1789) Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, 36 vols. Imprimerie Royale, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1749a) Histoire des animaux. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 2

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1749b) Histoire naturelle de l’homme. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 2, pp 429–603; vol 3, pp 305–530

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1753) Discours sur la nature des animaux. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 4, pp 1–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1755) Le cochon. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 5

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1756a) Le lièvre. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 6, pp 55–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1756b) Les animaux sauvages. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 6, pp 246–252

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1758a) Les animaux carnassiers. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 7, pp 3–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1758b) Le rat. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 8, pp 278–280

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1765) De la nature. Seconde vue. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 12

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1766) De la dégénération des animaux. In: Buffon 1749–1767, vol 14, pp 311–374

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon G-L Leclerc de (1770–1783) Histoire naturelle des oiseaux. 9 vols. Imprimerie royale, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldani MA (1778) Institutiones physiologicae. Editio secunda auctior. Typis Cominianis, Patavii. (1st edn. 1773)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantelli G (1969) Teologia e ateismo. Saggio sul pensiero filosofico e religioso di Pierre Bayle. La Nuova Italia, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Casini P (1958) Il concetto di “molecola organica” nella filosofia naturale del Settecento. Giornale critico della filosofia italiana 37:359–374

    Google Scholar 

  • Casini P (1967) George Cheyne e la religione naturale newtoniana. Giornale critico della filosofia italiana 46:383–404

    Google Scholar 

  • Casini P (1969) L’universo-macchina. Origini della filosofia newtoniana. Bari Laterza

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E (1953) The Platonic renaissance in England. Gordian Press, New York (English trans. of Die Platonische Renaissance in England und die Schule von Cambridge, 1932)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E (1991) Rousseau, Kant, Goethe. Meiner, Hamburg (1st edn. 1944)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E (2009) The philosophy of the Enlightenment. Updated edition. With a new foreword by Peter Gay. Princeton University Press, Princeton (English trans. of Die Philosophie der Aufklärung. 1932. Verlag von J.C.B. Mohr–Paul Siebeck, Tübingen)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers R (1844) Vestiges of the natural history of creation. Churchill, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Charleton W (1652) The darkness of atheism dispelled by the light of nature. A physico-theological treatise. Printed by J.F. for William Lee, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne G (1705) Philosophical principles of natural religion: containing the elements of natural philosophy, and the proofs for natural religion, arising from them. George Strahan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiaradonna R, Trabattoni F (eds) (2009) Physics and philosophy of nature in Greek Neoplatonism. Brill, Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiereghin F (1990) Finalità e idea della vita. La recezione hegeliana della teleologia di Kant. Verifiche 19:127–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Chignell AA (ed) (2019) Evil: a history. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke J (1720) An enquiry into the cause and origin of evil. In which the principal phaenomena of nature are explained according to the true principles of philosophy; more particularly in answer to Mr. Bayle and other defenders of the antient Manichaean scheme of two independent principles. Being the substance of eight sermons preached at the parish-church of St. Mary le Bow in the year 1719, at the lecture founded by the Honourable Robert Boyle, Esq. J. Knapton, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke S (1705) A demonstration of the being and attributes of God. Printed by Will Bothan for James Knapton, London. Faksimile-Neudruck F Frommann Verlag, Stuttgart–Bad Cannstadt (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman W (1964) Georges Cuvier, zoologist. A study in the evolution theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coleridge ST (1875) Notes on Stillingfleet. The Athenaeum, vol 2474, pp 422–423

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornford FM (1935) Plato’s cosmology. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Corsi P (1987) Julien Joseph Virey, le premier critique de Lamarck. In: Fischer J-L, Roger J (eds) Histoire du concept d’espèce dans les sciences de la vie. Fondation Singer-Polignac, Paris, pp 181–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Crispini F (1989) La psicologia wolffiana in Samuel Formey e Louis de Beausobre. Rivista di storia della filosofia 44:477–498

    Google Scholar 

  • Crocker LG (1959) An age of crisis. Man and world in eighteenth-century French thought. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Crocker LG (1963) Nature and culture. Ethical thought in the French Enlightenment. The Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Crocker LG (1968) Diderot and eighteenth-century French transformism. In: Glass B, Temkin O, Straus WL Jr (eds) Forerunners of Darwin, 1745–1859. The Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD, pp 114–143 (1st edn. 1959)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuvier G (1805) Leçons d’anatomie comparée. Crochard, Fantin; Baudoin, imprimeur de l’Institut. Paris. Impression anastaltique “Culture et civilisation”, Bruxelles, 1969

    Google Scholar 

  • Damiron J-P (1858–1864) Mémoires pour servir à l’histoire de la philosophie au XVIII siècle. Repr. 1967 Slatkine Reprints, Geneva

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1987) Charles Darwin notebooks, 1836–1844. Geology, transmutation of species, metaphysical enquiries. Transcribed and edited by P. H. Barrett, P. J. Gautrey, S. Herbert, D. Kohn, S. Smith, British Museum (Natural History)/Cambridge University Press, London/Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin E (1794–1796) Zoonomia, or the laws of organic life. J. Johnson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin E (1800) Phytologia; or, the philosophy of agriculture and gardening, with the theory of draining morasses and with an improved construction of the drill plough. P. Byrne, Dublin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin E (1803) The temple of nature; or, the origin of society: a poem with philosophical notes. J. Johnson, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daston L, Vidal F (eds) (2004) The moral authority of nature. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Daudin H (1926) De Linné à Lamarck. Méthodes de la classification et idée de série en botanique et en zoologie (1740–1790). Alcan, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawson G (2016) Show me the bone: reconstructing prehistoric monsters in nineteenth-century Britain and America. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deck JN (1967) Nature, contemplation, and the one. A study in the philosophy of Plotinus. University of Toronto Press, Toronto

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Derham W (1713) Physico-theology; or, a demonstration of the being and attributes of God from his works of creation. Being the substance of XVI sermons preached in St. Mary le Bow-Church, London, at the Hon. Mr. Boyle” lectures, in the years 1711 and 1712. With large notes and many curious observations. W. Innis, London. Repr. 1976. G. Olms, Hildesheim–New York (Anglistica & Americana, 162)

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond A (1989) The politics of evolution. Morphology, medicine, and reform in radical London. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Duméril A-M-C (1799) Mémoire sur les moyens que les insectes employent pour leur conservation. Magazine encyclopédique 25 (5e année, tome premier): 7–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Egerton FN (1968) Leeuwenhoek as a founder of animal demography. J Hist Biol 1:225–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehnmark E (1951–1952) Linnaeus and the problem of immortality. Kungliga Humanistika Veteskampssamfundet i Lund Årsberättelse 1951–1952:63–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott P (2003) Erasmus Darwin, Herbert Spencer, and the origins of the evolutionary worldview in British provincial scientific culture, 1770–1850. Isis 94(1):1–29

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fabbri Bertoletti S (1990) Impulso, formazione e organismo. Per una storia del concetto di Bildungstrieb nella cultura tedesca. Olschki, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius JA (1725) Delectus argumentorum et Syllabus scriptorum qui veritatem religionis Christianae adversus Atheos, Epicureos, Deistas seu Naturalistas, Idolatras, Judeos et Muhammedanos lucubrationibus suis asseruerunt. Sumptu Theodosi Christophori Felginer, Hamburgi

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher H (1953) The scientist as a priest: a note on Robert Boyle’s natural theology. Isis 44:252–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleming J (1822) The philosophy of zoology; or, a general view of the structure, functions, and classification of animals. Archibald Constable and Co, Edinburgh

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fonnesu L (1994) Der Optimismus und seine Kritiker im Zeitalter der Aufklärung. Studia Leibnitiana 26:131–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Fonnesu L (2006) The problem of theodicy. In: Haakonssen K (ed) The Cambridge history of eighteenth-century philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 749–778

    Google Scholar 

  • Formey J-H-S (1761) Ébauche du système de la compensation (1759). Histoire de l’Académie Royale des Sciences et Belles-Lettres [de Berlin] 12:378–389. chez Haude et Spener, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Frängsmyr T (1971–1972) Den gudomliga ekonomin: Religion och hushhållning i 1700-talets Sverige. Lychnos 1971–1972:217–244

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1991) Regulative and constitutive. South J Philos 30 (Supplement: system and teleology in Kant’s Critique of Judgement): 73–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M, Nordmann A (eds) (2006) The Kantian legacy in nineteenth-century science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fries EM (1878) Carl von Linnés anteckningar öfver nemesis divina. Utgifne af Elias Fries och Th.M. Fries. Ny, omarbetad och tillökad upplaga. Lundequistska bokhandeln, Uppsala (1st edn. 1848)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gambarotto A (2018) Vital forces, teleology, and organization: philosophy of nature and the rise of biology in Germany. Springer, Cham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkle N (1955) Science and religion in England, 1790–800: the critical response to the work of Erasmus Darwin. J Hist Ideas 16:376–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (ed) (1992) Buffon 88. Actes du colloque international pour le bicentenaire de la mort de Buffon. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Gedner C, Linnaeus C (1752) Quaestio historico-naturalis: Cui bono? In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 3 (1764), pp 231–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Geoffroy A (1861) Le Nemesis Divina de Linné. Revue des deux mondes, seconde période, 31e année, 32 (mars-avril 1861): 178–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Giacomoni P (1993) Le forme e il vivente. Morfologia e filosofia in J.W. Goethe. Guida, Naples

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie NC (1987) Natural history, natural theology, and social order: John Ray and the ‘Newtonian ideology’. J Hist Biol 20(1):1–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glacken CJ (1990) Traces on the Rhodian shore. Nature and culture in western thought from ancient times to the end of the eighteenth century. University of California Press, Berkeley (1st edn. 1967)

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith O (1760) A comparative view of races and nations. In: Collected works of Oliver Goldsmith. Edited by Arthur Friedman. 1966. Oxford: Clarendon Press, vol 3, pp 66–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith O (1774) An history of the earth, and animated nature. Selected passages. In: Goldsmith 1854, vol 4, pp 337–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith O (1854) Extracts from “An history of the earth and animated nature”. In: Cunningham P (ed) The works of Oliver Goldsmith, vol 4. Murray, London, pp 335–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf A (2012) Teleology, first principles, and scientific method in Aristotle’s biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory F (1989) Kant’s influence on natural scientists in the German Romantic period. In: Visser RPW, Bos HJM, Palm LC, Snelders HAM (eds) New trends in the history of science. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 53–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Grew N (1701) Cosmologia sacra, or a discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God. Chiefly written to demonstrate the truth and excellency of the Bible, which contains the laws of his kingdom in this lower world. Printed for W. Rogers, S. Smith, and B. Walford, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gustafsson L (1981) Carl von Linné und seine Nemesis Divina in philosophischer Sicht. In: Linnaeus 1981, pp 293–320

    Google Scholar 

  • Gysi L (1962) Platonism and Cartesianism in the philosophy of Ralph Cudworth. Lang, Bern

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagberg K (1952) Carl Linnaeus (trans: Blair A from Swedish). Jonathan Cape, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Haller A von (1748) Uber den Ursprung des Uebels (1734). In: Versuch Schweizerischer Gedichte. Vierte, vermehrte und veränderte Auflage. Abram Vandenhoeck, Göttingen, pp 129–155 (also in Gedichte, ed. by Ludwig Hirzel. J. Huber, Frauenfeld, 1882, pp 118–142)

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison J (1971) Erasmus Darwin’s view of evolution. J Hist Ideas 33:247–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison P (2020) What’s in a name? Physico-theology in seventeenth-century England. In: Blair A, von Greyerz K (eds) Physico-theology. Religion and science in Europe, 1650–1750. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 39–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassler DM (1973a) The comedian as the letter D: Erasmus Darwin’s comic materialism. Nijhoff, The Hague

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hassler DM (1973b) Erasmus Darwin. Twayne, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazard P (1941) Le problème du mal dans la conscience européenne du dix-huitième siècle. Romanic Rev 33:147–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazard P (1946) La pensée européenne au XVIIIème siècle. De Montesquieu à Lessing. Boivin et C.ie, éditeurs, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel GFW (1970) Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). In: Moldenhauer E, Michel KM (eds) Werke in zwanzig Bänden, vol 8–10. Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel GFW (1971) Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie (1840–1844). In: Moldenhauer E, Michel KM (eds) Werke in zwanzig Bänden, vol 18–20. Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel GWF (2018) The phenomenology of Spirit (trans and ed: Pinkard T). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Herder JG (1966) Outlines of a philosophy of the history of mankind. English trans: Churchill T of Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784–1791). Bergman Publishers, New York (1st edn. London, 1800)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick J (2007) Evil and the god of love. Reissued with a new preface. Palgrave MacMillan, London (1st edn. 1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge MJS (1972) The universal gestation of nature: Chambers’s Vestiges and Explanations. J Hist Biol 5(1):127–151

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hofsten N (1957) Linnaeus’s conception of nature. Kungliga Vetenskaps-Societetens Ǻrsbok:65–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Houghton WE (1942) The English virtuoso in the XVIIIth century. J Hist Ideas 3(51–73):190–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1992) Dialogues concerning natural religion. In: Green TH, Gross TH (eds) The philosophical works. London, 1886. Repr. Scientia Verlag Aalen, Darmstadt, vol 2, pp 377–468

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurlbutt RH (1965) Hume, Newton and the design argument. Univ. of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton S (2019) Ralph Cudworth: plastic nature, cognition and the cognizable world. In: Perler D, Bender S (eds) Causation and cognition in early modern philosophy. Routledge, London, pp 105–122

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutton S (2021) ‘Plastick powers’ and the power of sympathy in Cudworth and More: the spirit of nature and plastic nature. In: Jorati J (ed) Powers. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 189–213

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley TH (1857–1858) On the agamic reproduction and morphology of aphis. Trans Linnean Soc Lond 22(1856–1859):193–219, 221–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine N (1988) The significance of Schelling’s “epoch of a wholly new natural history”: an essay on the realization of questions. In: Woodhouse RS (ed) Metaphysics and philosophy of science in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 327–350

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston TD (2021) The pre-Darwinian history of the comparative method, 1555–1855. Hist Philos Life Sci 43. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-021-00474-8

  • Kant I (1788) Über den Gebrauch teleologischer Principien in der Philosophie. In: Gesammelte Schriften, vol 8. De Gruyter, Berlin–Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften, pp 157–184

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1996) Über das Misslingen aller philosophischen Versuche in der Theodicee (1791). English trans: di Giovanni G, On the miscarriage of all philosophical trials in theodicy. In: Wood AW, di Giovanni G (trans & ed) Religion and rational theology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 19–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (2000) Critique of the power of judgment (1790). Trans: Guyer P, Matthews E. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele D (1977) Doctor of revolution. The life and genius of Erasmus Darwin. Faber and Faber, London

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele D (1984) Shelley: his thought and work. Palgrave Macmillan, London (1st edn. 1964, Macmillan, London)

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele D (1986) Erasmus Darwin and the romantic poets. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele D (1999) Erasmus Darwin: a life of unequalled achievement. Giles de la Mare Publishers, London

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele D (2014) Erasmus Darwin and evolution. Stuart Harris, Sheffield

    Google Scholar 

  • King W (1704) De origine mali. Juxta exemplar Londinense. Apud Philippum Godofredum Saurmannum, Bernae (1st edn. 1702)

    Google Scholar 

  • King W (1731) Essay on the origin of evil… Translated from the Latin, with large notes; tending to explain and vindicate some of the Author’s principles against the objections of Bayle, Leibnitz, the Author of a “Philosophical enquiry concerning human liberty”; and others. To which is prefix’d a Dissertation concerning the fundamental principle and immediate criterion of virtue. As also, the obligation to, and approbation of it. With some account of the origin of the passions and affections, by Edmund Law, M.A., Fellow of Christ College in Cambridge. W. Thurlbourn. London, Repr. 1978. Garland Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirby W, Spence W (1815–1826) An introduction to entomology: or, elements of the natural history of insects. Longman, Hurst, Rees, Orme, Brown, and Green, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Koerner L (1999) Linnaeus: nature and nation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kremer J (1909) Das Problem der Theodizee in der Philosophie und Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Kant und Schiller. (“Kantstudien”, Ergänzungshefte im Auftrag der Kantgesellschaft, 13). Verlag von Reuther und Reichard, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • La Salle A de (1788) La balance naturelle, ou Essai sur une loi universelle appliquée aux sciences, arts et métiers, et aux moindres détails de la vie commune. Londres (no publisher mentioned)

    Google Scholar 

  • La Vergata A (1990) Nonostante Malthus. Fecondità, popolazioni e armonia della natura: 1700–1900. Bollati Boringhieri, Turin

    Google Scholar 

  • Labrousse E (2014a) Pierre Bayle. Seconde édition (avec des additions). Kluwer/Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht (1st edn. 1963–1964. M. Nijhoff, The Hague)

    Google Scholar 

  • Labrousse E (2014b) Pierre Bayle. Albin Michel, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambert JH (1761) Cosmologische Briefe über die Einrichtung des Weltbaues. Eberhard Klett, Augsburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Landucci S (1984) Sulla ‘finalità interna’ della natura in Kant. Rivista di Filosofia 75:185–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Landucci S (1986) La teodicea nell’età cartesiana. Bibliopolis, Naples

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson JL (1979) An alternative science. Linnæan Natural History in Germany, 1770–1790. Janus 66:267–283

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Larson JL (1994) Interpreting nature: the science of living form from Linnaeus to Kant. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Latzer M (1993) The nature of evil: Leibniz and his medieval background. The modern schoolman. Q J Philos 71(1):59–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Latzer M (1994) Leibniz’s conception of metaphysical evil. J Hist Ideas 1994:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurent G (1988) Virey et le transformisme. In: Bénichou C, Blanckaert C (eds) Julien-Joseph Virey: naturaliste et anthropologue. Vrin, Paris, pp 61–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Guyader H (2004) Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire 1772–1844: a visionary naturalist. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (English trans. of Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire: un naturaliste visionnaire. Belin, Paris, 1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Mahieu DL (1976) The mind of William Paley: a philosopher and his age. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

    Google Scholar 

  • Lechler GR (1965) Geschichte des englischen Deismus (1841). Mit einem Vorwort und bibliographischen Hinweisen von Günther Gawlich. J.G. Cotta, Stuttgart. Repr. Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Leduc C, Rateau P, Solère J-L (2015) Leibniz et Bayle: confrontation et dialogue. F. Steiner, Stuttgart

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leeuwenhoek A van (1695) Arcana Naturae, ope et beneficio exquisitissimorum microscopiorum detecta, variisque experimentis demonstrata, una cum discursu et ulteriori dilucidatione; epistolis suis ad celeberrimum, quod Ser.mi regis Magnae Britanniae auspicio Londini floret, Philosophorum Collegio datis comprehensa… Lugduni Batavorum: apud Henricum a Krooneveld

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeuwenhoek A van (1696) Continuatio epistolarum datarum ad longe celeberrimam Regiam Societatem Londinensem… Editio altera. Lungduni Batavorum: apud Cornelium Boutenstein

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz GW (1969) Essais de Théodicée, sur la bonté de Dieu, la liberté de l’homme et l’origine du mal (1710). Garnier-Flammarion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz GW (1979) Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Erste Reihe. Zehnter Band (1694). Akademie-Verlag, Darstadt-Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz GW (1978) Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, herausgegeben von C.J. Gebhardt. Dritter Band. Erste Abtheilung. Nachdruck der Ausgabe Berlin 1887. Georg Olms Verlag, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz GW (1998) Theodicy, or essays on the goodness of God, the freedom of man, and the origin of evil. Edited with an introduction by Austin Farrer (trans: Huggard EM). Open Court, Chicago (1st edn. Routledge, London, 1951)

    Google Scholar 

  • Leinkauf T, Steel C (eds) (2005) Platons Timaios als Grundtext der Kosmologie in Spätantike, Mittelalter und Renaissance. Leuven University Press, Leuven

    Google Scholar 

  • Lempp O (1910) Das Problem der Theodicee in der Philosophie und Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts bis auf Kant und Schiller. Gekrönte Preisschrift der Walter-Simon Preisaufgabe der Kantgesellschaft. Verlag der Dürr’schen Buchhandlung, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2001) Aristotle’s philosophy of biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir T (1982) The strategy of life. Teleology and mechanics in nineteenth-century German biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepenies W (1981) Eine Moral aus irdischer Ordnungsliebe: Linnés Nemesis Divina. In: Linnaeus C Nemesis divina. Nach der schwedischen Ausgabe von Elis Malmeström und Telemak Fredbärj herausgegeben von Wolf Lepenies und Lars Gustafsson. Aus dem Lateinischen und Schwedischen übersetzt von Ruprecht Volz. Carl Hanser Verlag, Munich, pp 321–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepenies W (1982) Linnaeus’s Nemesis Divina and the concept of divine retaliation. Isis 73:11–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lesser FC (1744) Testaceo-Theologia; oder, gründlicher Beweis des Daseyns und der vollkommensten Eigenschaften eines göttlichen Wesen, aus natürlicher und geistlicher Betrachtung der Schnecken und Muscheln ausgefertigte. Blochberger, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Lesser FC (1742) Théologie des insectes; ou, démonstration des perfections de Dieu dans tout ce qui concerne les insectes. Traduit de l’allemand, avec des remarques de P. Lyonnet. La Haye: chez Jean Swart (orig. Insecto-Theologia, oder: Vernunft- und Schriftsmässiger Versuch, wie ein 1744 Mensch durch aufmerksame Betrachtung derer sonst wenig geachteten Insecten zu lebendiger Erkänntniss und Bewunderung der Allmacht, Weisheit, der Güte und Gerechtigkeit des grossen Gottes gelangen könne, 1738)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lessius L (1617) De providentia numinis et animi immortalitate libri duo adversus Atheos & Politicos. Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindroth S (1943) Paracelsismen i Sverige till 1600-talets mitt. Almqvist & Wiksell, Uppsala

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindroth S (1965–1966) Linné—legend och verklighet. Lychnos 1965–1966:56–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindroth S (1994) The two faces of Linnaeus. In: Frängsmyr T (ed) Linnaeus. The man and his work. Revised edition (1st edn. Science History Publications, Canto, MA, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1983; orig. Linné—legend och verklighet. Lychnos 1965–1966, pp 56–122)

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C, Biberg IJ (1749) Oeconomia naturae. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 2 (1751), pp 1–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C, Wilcke HCD (1760) Politia naturae. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 6 (1763), pp 17–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C, Gedner C (1752) Quaestio historico-naturalis: Cui bono? In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 3 (1764), pp 231–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C, Söderberg O (1748) Curiositas naturalis. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 1 (1749), pp 540–563

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C, Westmann J (1743) Oratio de telluris habitabilis incremento. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 2 (1751), pp 430–459

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1749) Pan Suecicus. In: Ramsbottom 1959

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1749–1785) Amoenitates academicae; seu dissertationes variae physicae, medicae, botanicae, antheac seorsim editae, nunc collectae et auctae cum tabulis aeneis. Lugduni Batavorum: apud Cornelium Haak (vol. I); Holmiae: sumtu et literis Direct. Laurentii Salvii (vols. II-VII); Erlangae: sumtu Jo. Jacobi Palm (vols. VII–IX)

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1751) Philosophia botanica, in qua explicantur fundamenta botanica cum definitionibus partium, exemplis terminorum, observationibus rariorum. apud Godofr Kiesewetter, Stockholmiae

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1766) Clavis medicinae duplex, exterior et interior. Impensis Direct. Laurentii Salvii, Holmiae

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1767–1770) Systema naturae, per regna tria naturae, secundum classes, ordines, genera, species, cum characteribus, differentiis, synonymis, locis. Editio decima tertia ad editionem duodecimam reformatam Holmiensem. Jo. Th. Trattnern, Vindobonae

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1968) Nemesis divina. Utgiven af E. Malmeström och T. Fredbärj. Bonnier, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (1981) Nemesis divina. Nach der schwedischen Ausgabe von Elis Malmeström und Telemak Fredbärj herausgegeben von Wolf Lepenies und Lars Gustafsson. Aus dem Lateinischen und Schwedischen übersetzt von Ruprecht Volz. Carl Hanser Verlag, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus C (2001) Nemesis divina. Edited and translated with an introduction and explanatory notes by M.J. Petry. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotti B (2004) Ralph Cudworth e l’idea di natura plastica. Campanotto Editore, Udine

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy AO (1968) Kant and evolution. In: Glass B, Temkin O, Straus WL Jr (eds) Forerunners of Darwin, 1745–1859. The Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD, pp 173–206 (1st edn. 1959)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy AO (2001) The great chain of being. A study of the history of an idea. The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University, 1933. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1st edn. 1936)

    Google Scholar 

  • Löw R (1980) Philosophie des Lebendigen. Der Begriff des Organischen bei Kant, sein Grund und seine Aktualität. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyell C (1830–1833) Principles of geology, being an attempt to explain the former changes of the Earth’s surface, by reference to causes now in operation. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Malmeström E (1926) Carl von Linnés religiösa askadning. Akademisk avhandling av Elis Malmeström. Svenska Kyrkans Diakonistentyrelses Bogforlag, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Malmeström E (1942) Die religiöse Entwicklung und die Weltanschauung Carl von Linnés. Zeitschrift für systematische Theologie 19:31–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Malmeström E (1981) Entstehung, Quellen und Character der Aufzeichnungen Linnés zur Nemesis Divina. In: Linnaeus 1981, pp 13–42 (German trans. of Anteckningarnas tillkomst, källor och karaktär, in Linnaeus 1968, pp 9–32)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mamiani M (2022) Introduzione. In: Isaac Newton, Trattato sull’Apocalisse. Bollati Boringhieri, Turin

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbrote S (2020) What was physico-theology for? In: Blair A, von Greyerz K (eds) Physico-theology. Religion and science in Europe, 1650–1750. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 67–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquard O (1976) Kompensation. Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie 4:912–918

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquard O (1978a) Glück im Unglück: zur Theorie des indirekten Glückes zwischen Theodizee und Geschichtsphilosophie. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 3:23–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquard O (1978b) Kompensation: Ueberlegungen zu einer Verlaufsfigur geschichtlicher Prozesse. In: Faber KG, Meier C (eds) Historische Prozesse. Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, Munich, pp 330–362

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin E, Watkins E (2019) Evil, natural science, and animal suffering. In: Chignell AA (ed) Evil: a history. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 383–413

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maupertuis P-L Moreau de (1749) Essai de philosophie morale. In: Oeuvres. Nouvelle édition corrigée et augmentée. 1768, vol 1. Chez Jean-Marie Bruyset, Lyon, pp 171–252

    Google Scholar 

  • Maury F (1896) Étude sur la vie et les oeuvres de Bernardin de Saint-Pierre. Hachette, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo H (1837) The philosophy of living. John W. Parker, London

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire E (1972) Boyle’s conception of nature. J Hist Ideas 33:523–342

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna A (2015) Etudes sur Pierre Bayle. Champion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin P (1990) Kant’s critique of teleology in biological explanation: antinomy and teleology. Edwin Mellen, Lewiston

    Google Scholar 

  • McNeil M (1987) Under the banner of science: Erasmus Darwin and his age. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Meister C et al (eds) (2018) The history of evil, vol 6. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mersenne M (1623) Quaestiones celeberrimae in Genesim, cum accurata textus explicatione. In hoc volumine athei et deistae impugnantur et expurgantur, et vulgata editio ab haereticorum calumniis vindicatur… . sumptibus Sebastiani Cramoisy, Lutetiae Parisiorum

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1874) Nature. In: Three essays on religion. Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1903) Principia ethica. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • More H (1655) An antidote against atheism, or, an appeal to the natural faculties of man, whether be a god. The second edition corrected and enlarged: with an appendix thereunto annexed (1st edn. 1652). J. Flesher, London. Facsimile repr. with an introduction by G.A.J. Rogers, 1997. Thoemmes Press, Bristol

    Google Scholar 

  • Mori G (1990) Tra Descartes a Bayle. Poiret e la teodicea. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Mori G (1996) Introduzione a Bayle. Laterza, Rome

    Google Scholar 

  • Mori G (1999) Bayle philosophe. Honoré Champion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Mori G (2016) L’ateismo dei moderni. Filosofia e negazione di Dio da Spinoza a d’Holbach. Carocci, Roma

    Google Scholar 

  • Mormino G (2005a) Determinismo e utilitarismo nella Teodicea di Leibniz. FrancoAngeli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Mormino G (2005b) La limitation originaire des créatures chez Leibniz. In: Pasini E (ed) La Monadologie de Leibniz: genèse et contexte. Mimesis, Milan-Udine, pp 55–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler S (2010) The best of all possible worlds: a story of philosophers, god, and evil in the age of reason. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham JT (1750) Nouvelles observations microscopiques, avec des découvertes intéressantes sur la composition et la décomposition des corps organisées. chez L.E. Ganeau, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Neiman S (2015) Evil in modern thought: an alternative history of philosophy. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelli S (1984) Teodicea e libero arbitrio nel De origine mali di William King. Annali dell’Istituto di Filosofia dell’Università di Firenze 6:77–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsomer J (2005) A craftsman and his handmaiden: Demiurgy according to Plotinus. In: Leinkauf T, Steel C (eds) Platons Timaios als Grundtext der Kosmologie in Spätantike, Mittelalter und Renaissance. Leuven University Press, Leuven, pp 67–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr J (1934) English deism: its roots and fruits. William Eerdmans, Grand Rapids

    Google Scholar 

  • Osler MJ (1994) Divine will and the mechanical philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Osler MJ (2001) Whose ends? Teleology in early modern natural philosophy. Osiris 16:151–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Outram D (1984) Georges Cuvier: vocation, science and authority in post-revolutionary France. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacchi A (1973) Cartesio in Inghilterra. Da More a Boyle. Laterza, Bari

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini G (1980) Analisi della fede e critica della ragione nella filosofia di Pierre Bayle. La Nuova Italia, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Paley W (1802) Natural theology: or, evidences of the existence and attributes of the deity, collected from the appearances of nature. Printed for R. Faulder by Wilks and Taylor, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasini E (2012) La concordia e l’armonia. Leibniz e la globalizzazione di una tradizione europea. Revista de Filosofia de la Universidad de Costa Rica 51:373–381

    Google Scholar 

  • Passmore JA (2013) Ralph Cudworth. An interpretation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1st edn. 1955)

    Google Scholar 

  • Passmore JD (1974) Man’s responsibility for nature. Ecological problems and western traditions. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Philipp W (1957) Das Werden der Aufklärung in theologiegeschichtlicher Sicht. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, Göttingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Philipp W (1967) Physicotheology in the age of Enlightenment: appearance and history. Stud Voltaire Eighteenth Cent 5:1233–1267

    Google Scholar 

  • Piazzesi B (2023) Del governo degli animali. Allevamento e biopolitica. Quodlibet, Macerata

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkard T (2002) German philosophy, 1760–1860. The legacy of idealism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinsent A (2018) The history of evil in the medieval age, 450–1450 CE. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pitman JH (1972) Goldsmith’s “Animated nature”. Shoestring Press, New York (1st edn. 1924)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ploucquet G (1782) Expositiones philosophiae theoreticae. Editio ultima. Stutgardiae: apud Jo. Bened. Mezler (1st edn. 1772)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pluche N-A (1768) Lo spettacolo della natura… Italian transl. of Le spectacle de la nature (1732–1750). Vincenzo Manfredi, Naples

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi S (2000) Il genio e l’unità della natura. La scienza nella Germania romantica (1790–1830). Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Pope A (1733–1734) An essay on man. In: Butt J (ed) The poems of Alexander Pope, a one-volume edition of the Twickenham text, with selected annotations. Yale University Press, New Haven, pp 501–547

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter GR (1925) Coleridge and the idea of evolution. PMLA/Publications of the Modern Language Association of America 40(2):397–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulteney R (1805) A general view of the writings of Linnaeus, 2nd edn. K. Mawman, London (1st edn. 1781)

    Google Scholar 

  • Querner H (1980) Das teleologische Weltbild Linnés—Observationes, Oeconomia, Politia. In: Goerke H, Querner H, Andreae C, von Engelhardt W, Heywood VH (eds) Carl von Linné. Beiträge über Zeitgeist, Werk und Wirkungsgeschichte gehalten auf dem Linnaeus-Symposion in Hamburg am 21. und 22. Oktober 1978. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, Göttingen, pp 25–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsbottom J (1959) Caroli Linnaei Pan Suecicus. Transactions (and Proceedings) of the Botanical Society of Edinburgh 38:151–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Rateau P (2008) La question du mal chez Leibniz. Honoré Champion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Raven C (1950) John Ray, naturalist: his life and works. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray J (1691) The wisdom of good manifested in the works of creation. Printed for Samuel Smith, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray J (1713) Three physico-theological discourses, concerning I. The primitive chaos, and creation of the world. II. The general deluge, its causes and effects. III. The dissolution of the world, and future conflagration. Printed for William Innys, London (1st edn. Miscellaneous discourses concerning the dissolution and changes in the world. Printed for S. Smith, London)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehbock PF (1983) The philosophical naturalists. Themes in nineteenth-century British biology. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehbock PF (1985) John Fleming (1785–1857) and the economy of nature. In: Wheeler A, Price JH (eds) From Linnaeus to Darwin: commentaries on the history of biology and geology. Society for the History of Natural History, London, pp 129–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey R (1988) Le vitalisme de Virey. In: Bénichou C, Blanckaert C (eds) Julien-Joseph Virey: naturaliste et anthropologue. Vrin, Paris, pp 31–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey R (1992) L’animalité dans l’oeuvre de Bernardin de Saint-Pierre: convenance, consonance et contraste. Rev Synth 113(3–4):311–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards RS (2002) The romantic conception of life. Science and philosophy in the age of Goethe. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robinet J-B (1763–1766) De la nature. Chez F. van Harrevelt, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson EH (1954) Erasmus Darwin’s Botanic Garden and contemporary opinion. Ann Sci 10:314–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roger J (1971) Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée française du XVIIIe siècle. La génération des animaux de Descartes à l’Encyclopédie, 2nd edn. Armand Colin, Paris (1st edn. 1963)

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger J (1997) Buffon. A life in natural history (trans: Bonnefoi SL; ed: Pearce Williams L). Cornell University Press, Ithaca (orig. Buffon. Un philosophe au Jardin du Roi. Fayard, Paris, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross WD (1923) Aristotle. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossi Monti M (2014) “Un filosofo mancato”. Aporie della concezione plotiniana della natura. In: La Vergata A (ed) Nature. Studi su concetti e immagini della natura. ETS, Pisa, pp 13–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossi P (1984) The dark abyss of time. The history of the earth and the history of nations from Hooke to Vico. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (orig. I segni del tempo. Storia della terra e storia delle nazioni da Hooke a Vico. Feltrinelli, Milan, 1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossi P (1997) The birth of modern science in Europe. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosso C (1954a) Il paradosso di Robinet. Filosofia 1:37–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosso C (1954b) Compenso e bilancia. Filosofia 1:420–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosso C (1969) Illuminismo, felicità e dolore. Miti e ideologie francesi. Edizioni Scientifiche, Naples

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosso C (1977) Moralisti del “bonheur”. Seconda edizione accresciuta e aggiornata. Editrice Libreria Goliardica, Pisa (1st edn. 1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • Roule L (1930) Bernardin de Saint-Pierre et l’harmonie de la nature. (L’histoire de la nature vivante d’après l’œuvre des grands naturalistes français, 6). Flammarion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J-J (1992) Discours sur l’origine de l’inégalité parmi les hommes (1755). English trans. Discourse on the origins of inequality. In: Masters RD, Kelly C (eds) The collected writings of Rousseau, vol 3. (trans: Bush JR, Masters RD, Kelly C, Marshall T). University Press of New England, Hanover

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupke NA (1983) The great chain of history. William Buckland and the English School of Geology (1814–1849). Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupke NA (2009) Richard Owen: biology without Darwin. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (rev. edn. of Richard Owen: Victorian naturalist. Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford D (1995) Leibniz and the rational order of nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt A (1984) Goethes herrlich-leuchtende Natur. Hanser, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwieger J (1913) Der Philosoph Pierre Hyacinthe Azaïs. Inaugural Dissertation zur Erlangung der Doktorwürde genehmigt von der philosophischen Fakultät der Rheinischen Friedrich-Wilhelm-Universität zu Bonn. Druck von H. Ludwig, Bonn

    Google Scholar 

  • Secord J (2000) Victorian sensation. The extraordinary publication, reception, and secret authorship of 'Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation'. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Serna P (2017) Comme des bêtes. Histoire politique de l’animal en Révolution (1750–1840). Fayard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaftesbury AAC, third Earl of (1709) The moralists, a philosophical rhapsody. Being a recital of certain conversations upon natural and moral subjects. Printed for John Wyat, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sina M (1976) L’avvento della ragione. ‘Reason’ e ‘above reason’ dal razionalismo teologico inglese al deismo. Vita e Pensiero, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (1973) The idea of racial degeneracy in Buffon’s Histoire naturelle. Studies in 18th Century Culture 3(1):293–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (1976) The Buffon–Linnaeus controversy. Isis 67:356–375

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (1979) Buffon, German biology, and the historical interpretation of biological species. Br J Hist Sci 12:109–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (1987) From logical universals to historical individuals: Buffon’s idea of biological species. In: Fischer J-L, Roger J (eds) Histoire du concept d’espèce dans les sciences de la vie. Fondation Singer-Polignac, Paris, pp 101–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (2003) Whewell’s philosophy of discovery and the archetype of the vertebrate skeleton: the role of German philosophy of science in Richard Owen’s biology. Ann Sci 60(1):39–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (2006) Kant on the history of nature: the ambiguous heritage of the critical philosophy for natural history. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 37(4):627–648

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Söderberg O, Linnaeus C (1748) Curiositas naturalis. In: Linnaeus 1749–1769, vol 1 (1749), pp 540–563

    Google Scholar 

  • Solinas G (1987) La teodicea negativa di Robinet. In: Solinas G (ed) Ricerche sul pensiero del secolo XVIII. Pubblicazioni dell’Istituto di Filosofia della Facoltà di Lettere dell’Università di Cagliari, Cagliari, pp 7–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Solmsen F (1963) Nature as craftsman in Greek thought. J Hist Ideas 24:473–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spary E (2000) Utopia’s garden. French natural history from Old Régime to Revolution. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Spallanzani L (1958–1964) Epistolario di Lazzaro Spallanzani, a cura di E. Biagi e D. Prandi. Sansoni Antiquariato, Firenze

    Google Scholar 

  • Starobinski J (1989) Le remède dans le mal. Critique et légitimation de l’artifice à l’âge des Lumières. Gallimard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Starobinski J (1999) Action et réaction. Vie et aventures d’un couple. Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Stauffer RC (1960) Ecology in the long manuscript version of Darwin’s origin of species and Linnaeus’ economy of nature. Proc Am Philos Soc 104:235–241

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephen L (1893) Ethics and the struggle for existence. Contemporary Rev 64:158–170. (Also in Id. 1896. Social rights and duties. Swan Sonnenschein & Co., London. Repr. 2011. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge)

    Google Scholar 

  • Svagelski J (1981) L’idée de compensation en France, 1750–1850. Préface de François Dagognet. L’Hermès, Lyon

    Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald J (2006a) Kant’s concept of natural purpose and the reflecting power of judgement. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 37(4):712–734

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald J (ed) (2006b) Special issue: Kant and biology. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 37(4)

    Google Scholar 

  • Theis R (1987) Le meilleur des mondes possibles, le mal métaphysique et le mal moral chez Leibniz. Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 34(1–2):169–184

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas K (1984) Man and the natural world. Changing attitudes in England 1500–1800. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth (1st edn. 1983. Allen Lane, London)

    Google Scholar 

  • Thuillier G (1964) Un aventurier philosophe: Antoine de La Salle. La Revue Adm 17(97):21–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonelli G (1987) In: Cesa C (ed) La pensée philosophique de Maupertuis: son milieu et ses sources. Olms, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Topham JR (1998) Beyond the ‘common context’: the production and reading of the Bridgewater treatises. Isis 89:233–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Totok W (1949) Das Problem der Theodizee in der deutschen Gedankenlyrik der Aufklärung. Dissertation. Philosophische Fakultät, Marburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Totok W (1986) Theodizee bei Leibniz und Lessing. In: Heinekamp A (ed) Beiträge zur Wirkungs- und Rezeptionsgeschichte von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. F. Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 177–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Trepp A-C (2008) Natural order and divine salvation: Protestant conceptions in early modern Germany (1550–1570). In: Daston L, Stolleis M (eds) Natural law and laws of nature in early modern Europe. Ashgate, Aldershot, pp 123–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Trepp A-C (2020) Matters of belief and belief that matters: German physico-theology, Protestantism, and the materialized work of God in nature. In: Blair A, von Greyerz K (eds) Physico-theology. Religion and science in Europe, 1650–1750. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 127–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsanoff RA (1931) The nature of evil. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Uglow J (2002) The lunar men: five friends whose curiosity changed the world. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Usener H (1887) Epicurea. Teubner, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Lugt M (2021) Dark matters. Pessimism and the problem of suffering. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vernière P (1954) Spinoza et la pensée française avant la Révolution. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Verra V (1971) Introduzione. In: Herder JG Idee per una filosofia della storia dell’umanità (Italian translation of Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit). Zanichelli, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Virey JJ (1799) Essai d’histoire naturelle et de physiologie, sur les moyens d’augmenter la perfectibilité de l’homme. Magasin encyclopédique, cinquième année, tome quatrième, pp 7–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Virey J-J (1801) Histoire naturelle du genre humain, ou recherches sur ses principaux fondemens physiques et moraux; précédées d’un discours sur la nature des êtres organiques, et sur l’ensemble de leur physiologie. On y a joint une dissertation sur le sauvage de l’Aveyron. Dufart, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Virey J-J (1815) Fécondité. In: Dictionnaire des sciences médicales, par une société de médecins et de chirurgiens, vol 15, Panckoucke, Paris, pp 480–497

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire (François-Marie Arouet) (1756) Poëme sur la loi naturelle. In: Voltaire 1877–1885, vol 9, pp 439–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire (François-Marie Arouet) (1877–1885) Oeuvres complètes de Voltaire. Nouvelle edition [by Louis Moland].… conforme pour le texte à l’édition de Beuchot. Garnier Frères, Paris. Repr. Nendeln, Kraus Reprint Limited, Lichtenstein

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire (François-Marie Arouet) (2006) Zadig. In Candide and other stories. Translated with an introduction and notes by Roger Pearson. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner MF (ed) (2002) Neoplatonism and nature. Studies on Plotinus’ Enneads. State university of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward LF (1881a) The world’s supply of live stock. Popular Sci Monthly 18:526–539

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward LF (1881b) The animal population of the globe. Bulletin of the Philosophical Society of Washington 4, pp 27–29. Repr. in Id. Glimpses of the cosmos. Comprising his minor contributions now republished, together with biographical and historical sketches of all his writings, vol 2. G.P. Putnam’s Sons, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward LF (1913–1918) Glimpses of the cosmos. Comprising his minor contributions now republished, together with biographical and historical sketches of all his writings. G.P. Putnam’s Sons, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber AS (2014) Erasmus Darwin’s impact on religious and scientific views of English Romanticism. https://www.qscience.com/content/journals/10.5339/rels.2014.science.14?crawler=true&mimetype=application/pdf

  • Wegener R (1909) Das Problem der Theodizee in der Philosophie und Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts, mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Kant und Schiller. Gekrönt Preisschrift der Walter Simon Preisaufgabe der Kantgesellschaft. Niemeyer, Halle a. S.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall RS (1973) Science and religion in seventeenth-century England. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor (1st edn. 1958)

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall RS (1983) Never at rest. A biography of Isaac Newton. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1st edn. 1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • Westmann J, Linnaeus C (1743) Oratio de telluris habitabilis incremento. In: Linnaeus 1749–1769, vol 2, pp 430–459

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell W (1833) On astronomy and general physics considered with reference to natural theology (The Bridgewater treatises on the power wisdom and goodness of God as manifested in the works of creation. Treatise III). William Pickering, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wikman KRV (1970) Lachesis and Nemesis. Four chapters on the human condition in the writings of Carl Linnaeus. Almquist & Wiksell, Stokholm (Scripta Instituti Donneriani Aboensis, IV)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilberding J, Horn Christoph C (eds) (2012) Neoplatonism and the philosophy of nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilcke HCD, Linnaeus (1760) Politia naturae. In: Linnaeus 1749–1785, vol 6 (1763), pp 17–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins J (1693) Of the principles and duties of natural religion (1675). Printed for T. Bassett, R. Chiswell, and C. Brome, London. Repr. Johnson Reprint Collection, New York, 1969

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins J (1802) The discovery of a new world; or, a discourse tending to prove, that (it is probable) there may be another habitable world in the moon. With a discourse concerning the possibility of a passage thither (1675). In: The mathematical and philosophical writings of the right rev. John Wilkins… (1638). Printed by C. Whittingham for Vernor and Hood, Cutchell and Martin, Holborn and J. Walker, London, Repr. Frank Cass & Co., London, 1970

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeo RR (1979) William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid-nineteenth century Britain. Ann Sci 36(5):493–516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeo RR (1986) The principle of plenitude and natural theology in nineteenth-century Britain. Br J Hist Sci 19:263–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeo RR (1993) Defining science: William Whewell, natural knowledge and public debate in Early Victorian Britain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito J (2012) The Lenoir thesis revised. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:120–132

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito J (2017) The gestation of German biology. Philosophy and physiology from Stahl to Schelling. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zeitz L (1994) Natural theology, rhetoric, and revolution: John Ray’s Wisdom of God. Eighteenth-Cent Life 18(1):120–133

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

La Vergata, A. (2023). Abundance and Variety. In: Images of the Economy of Nature, 1650-1930. Evolutionary Biology – New Perspectives on Its Development, vol 7. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-31023-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics