Skip to main content

Contemporary Approaches in the Philosophy of Human Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Grounding Human Rights in Human Nature

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 142))

  • 124 Accesses

Abstract

I examine the major approaches in the philosophy of human rights from the point of view of their answer on the precise character of the relation between human rights and their foundations as well as from the point of view of taking into consideration the discoveries of natural sciences. It turns out that the relation between human rights and their foundations is either flawed, weak or unclear. Similarly, there are almost no references to the rapid development of natural sciences dealing with human in the major approaches to human rights.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966).

  2. 2.

    Constitution of the Republic of Poland (1997), art. 30.

  3. 3.

    Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), Preamble, art. 1.

  4. 4.

    German Basic Law (1949, art. 1).

  5. 5.

    UNESCO (1948), p. I. This resembles an incomplete theorised agreement in terms of Cass Sunstein (2017).

  6. 6.

    Nussbaum (2000, 2006, 2011) and Miller (2007, 2012).

  7. 7.

    Griffin (2008).

  8. 8.

    Tasioulas (2015).

  9. 9.

    Piechowiak (1999, 2019).

  10. 10.

    Tasioulas (2011), p. 26.

  11. 11.

    Griffin (2008), p. 2.

  12. 12.

    Rawls (1999), Pogge (2002), Beitz (2009) and Raz (2010, 2015).

  13. 13.

    Rawls (1999), p. 90.

  14. 14.

    Gewirth (1981, 1982); cf. Raz (2010), p. 323.

  15. 15.

    Gewirth (1981), p. 124.

  16. 16.

    Raz (2010), p. 323.

  17. 17.

    Raz (2010), p. 342.

  18. 18.

    cf. Allen (1982).

  19. 19.

    Hume (1739), p. 335.

  20. 20.

    Putnam (2002). Hume’s Guillotine cuts only a logical entailment between factual premises and a normative conclusion. Total separation between descriptive and normative spheres was not intended by Hume and, as Putnam argues (2002), the idea of such a radical separation is a child of logical positivism of early and mid-twentieth century.

  21. 21.

    Witkowski (1975); Makowski (2011), p. 325.

  22. 22.

    Griffin (2008).

  23. 23.

    Griffin (2008), p. 4; p. 33.

  24. 24.

    Griffin (2008), p. 33.

  25. 25.

    Griffin (2008), p. 33.

  26. 26.

    Griffin (2008), p. 38.

  27. 27.

    Griffin (2008), p. 47.

  28. 28.

    Griffin (2008), p. 83.

  29. 29.

    Griffin (2008), p. 14.

  30. 30.

    Tasioulas (2013), p. 302.

  31. 31.

    Tasioulas (2013), p. 303.

  32. 32.

    Renzo (2015), p. 574.

  33. 33.

    Renzo (2015), p. 574.

  34. 34.

    Griffin (2008), p. 4.

  35. 35.

    Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (1948), art. II.

  36. 36.

    Griffin (2008), ch. 7; Griffin (2015).

  37. 37.

    American Anthropological Association’s Statement on Human Rights (1947), p. 542.

  38. 38.

    Griffin (2008), p. 133.

  39. 39.

    Griffin (2008), p. 133.

  40. 40.

    Raz (2010), p. 324.

  41. 41.

    Griffin (2008), p. 4.

  42. 42.

    Griffin (2008), p. 135.

  43. 43.

    Witkowski (1975); Makowski (2011), p. 325.

  44. 44.

    Nussbaum (2000, 2006, 2011).

  45. 45.

    Nussbaum (2011), p. 20.

  46. 46.

    Cruft et al. (2015), p. 15.

  47. 47.

    Nussbaum (2011), p. 11.

  48. 48.

    Nussbaum (2011), p. 31.

  49. 49.

    Nussbaum (2011), pp. 33–34.

  50. 50.

    I put the term dignity in brackets as Nussbaum sometimes makes use of the term dignity, rather than human dignity. Moreover, she explicitly extends her capability approach to animals and considers whether they have animal dignity (2011, ch. 6).

  51. 51.

    Nussbaum (2006), p. 161.

  52. 52.

    Nussbaum (2006), p. 162.

  53. 53.

    Nussbaum (2011).

  54. 54.

    cf. Nussbaum (2011), p. 33 where she speaks about having a life that is not worth living.

  55. 55.

    Cruft et al. (2015), p. 16.

  56. 56.

    Notice that in her work on religious intolerance (2012) she makes use and analyses the concept of human dignity in its meaning starting from international legal documents on human rights.

  57. 57.

    Liao (2015), p. 92.

  58. 58.

    Nussbaum (2006), p. 172.

  59. 59.

    Liao (2015), p. 93; Cruft et al. (2015), p. 15.

  60. 60.

    Liao (2015), p. 92.

  61. 61.

    Nussbaum (2011), p. 32.

  62. 62.

    cf. Sen (1999, 2005) who makes use of this concept in economics and has been the leading figure in the so-called development economics.

  63. 63.

    Nussbaum (2011), p. 32.

  64. 64.

    Miller (2007, 2012) and Renzo (2015).

  65. 65.

    Miller (2007, 2012); Cruft et al. (2015), p. 14.

  66. 66.

    Griffin (2008).

  67. 67.

    Renzo (2015), p. 579.

  68. 68.

    Renzo (2015), p. 579.

  69. 69.

    Cruft et al. (2015), p. 15.

  70. 70.

    Miller (2012), p. 422.

  71. 71.

    Hapla (2018).

  72. 72.

    Hapla (2018), pp. 10–12.

  73. 73.

    Piechowiak (1999, 2019).

  74. 74.

    Piechowiak (1999), pp. 79–85, 110–117.

  75. 75.

    Piechowiak (1999), p. 19.

  76. 76.

    Piechowiak (1999), pp. 226–264.

  77. 77.

    Piechowiak (1999), p. 273.

  78. 78.

    The description of Piechowiak’s second work (2019) is based on a part of my review of Marek Piechowiak’s work (Mazurkiewicz 2020); similar, yet much shorter piece of work was also published (Mazurkiewicz 2019).

  79. 79.

    Piechowiak (2019), pp. 41–42.

  80. 80.

    Griffin (2008) and Waldron (2012, 2015).

  81. 81.

    The recognition of the fact that human existence is an aim in itself is of course incompatible with the totalitarian subordination of human good to the good of the state and is another argument for rejecting Popperian reading of Plato’s political views.

  82. 82.

    Piechowiak (1999, 2019).

  83. 83.

    Piechowiak (1999).

  84. 84.

    Rawls (1999), Pogge (2002), Beitz (2009) and Raz (2010, 2015).

  85. 85.

    Tasioulas (2011), p. 44.

  86. 86.

    Rawls (1999), p. 79.

  87. 87.

    Tasioulas (2011), p. 44.

  88. 88.

    Tasioulas (2011), pp. 44–45.

  89. 89.

    Tasioulas (2011), pp. 44–45.

  90. 90.

    Tasioulas (2011), p. 45.

  91. 91.

    Tasioulas (2011), p. 54.

  92. 92.

    Raz (2010), p. 334.

  93. 93.

    Raz (2010), p. 327.

  94. 94.

    Rawls (1999), p. 65.

  95. 95.

    Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), art. 24.

  96. 96.

    Beitz (2009), p. 197.

  97. 97.

    cf. Fine (1994); Robertson and Atkins (2018).

  98. 98.

    Kment (2017). I believe that there is no need to enter here into the analytic philosophy debate on possible worlds (for a detailed study see e.g. Menzel 2017). Let me just notice that although philosophical interpretation of what possible worlds are vary, they can and rather tend to be understood on a purely semantic level. Following this view, they have nothing to do with what may resemble “parallel universes”.

  99. 99.

    Lewis (1973).

  100. 100.

    Menzel (2017).

  101. 101.

    Robertson and Atkins (2018).

  102. 102.

    Fine (1994).

  103. 103.

    Fine (1994), p. 8.

  104. 104.

    Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), art. 15, art. 25.

  105. 105.

    One may argue that in the past human rights were used to frame arguments supporting the justness of a rebellion against tyrannical monarchs, so they had a political role. For instance, the French Revolution utilised the idea of human rights to fight against the tyrannical monarch. Nonetheless, there was no consensus in international law of that time concerning the role of these rights. Actually quite to the contrary, rebellion was seen as an illegal attack on king’s eternal authority coming from God. Moreover, the conception of international intervention was not needed as war was a legal means in international relations. It should be stressed that the political approach ascribes the essential role of human rights to the international law and politics and not to the thought of scholars. Scholars or political philosophers developed some theories about the role of natural or human rights but these theories were not implemented into the law and practice of international relations.

  106. 106.

    cf. the decisions of Vienna Congress in 1815 that established rules of international order up to the First World War.

  107. 107.

    Rawls (1999), Beitz (2009) and Raz (2010).

  108. 108.

    Rawls (1999).

  109. 109.

    Zajadło (2005, 2010).

  110. 110.

    UN Charter (1945), art. 2.4.

  111. 111.

    UN Charter (1945), art. 51.

  112. 112.

    UN Charter (1945), art. 42–44.

  113. 113.

    Danish Institute of International Affairs (1999), p. 94.

  114. 114.

    Statute of International Court of Justice (1945), art. 38.1(b).

  115. 115.

    UN World Summit Outcome Document (2005), par. 138–140.

  116. 116.

    There is however one version of the political approach that is immune to this argument. This is Rawlsian realistic utopia (1999) where Rawls aims to find the best fundamental rules for a fair international order. Rawls does not build his theory on currently existing international order, consequently his notion of the role of human rights neither refers to contemporary international law nor international relations. Rather it refers to an ideal of just international law or international relations. Thus, my analysis of contemporary international law has nothing to do with his theory. On the other hand, adherents of the political approach after Rawls speak rather of existing, current international law and international politics.

  117. 117.

    Waldron (2013).

  118. 118.

    Waldron (2013), p. 10, p. 12; cf. Rawls (1999), p. 38; Beitz (2009), pp. 105–106.

  119. 119.

    Waldron (2013), p. 10, p. 12.

  120. 120.

    Pogge (2002) and Beitz (2009).

  121. 121.

    Rawls (1999) and Raz (2010).

  122. 122.

    Griffin (2008), p. 2; Tasioulas (2011), p. 27.

  123. 123.

    Rosen (2013).

  124. 124.

    Piechowiak (1999, 2019) and Mikhail (2012).

  125. 125.

    Leiter and Etchemendy (2017) and Papineau (2020).

  126. 126.

    With a minor but notable exception of Mikhail (2012).

  127. 127.

    To mention just a few: Leiter (2007), Pardo and Patterson (2013), Załuski (2009a, b, 2018), Brożek (2012, 2017a, b, 2020) and Brożek et al. (2017).

  128. 128.

    Załuski (2009a, b) and Brożek (2012, 2017c).

  129. 129.

    Plunkett (2012), Gizbert-Studnicki (2015, 2016, 2021) and Chilovi and Pavlakos (2019).

  130. 130.

    Griffin (2008), p. 2; Tasioulas (2011), p. 27.

  131. 131.

    For certain reasons, the concept that is commonly used in metaphysical debates is ontological dependence, rather than metaphysical dependence. I will stick to this terminology.

  132. 132.

    Tahko and Lowe (2016).

References

  • Allen P (1982) A critique of Gewirth’s “Is-Ought”. Deriv Ethics 92:211–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Anthropological Association (1947) Statement on human rights. Am Anthropol 48:539–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beitz C (2009) The idea of human rights. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2012) Normatywność Prawa. Warszawa, Wolters Kluwer

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2017a) On the naturalisation of law. Polish Law Rev 3:13–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2017b) Neuroscience and the ontology of law. Polish Law Rev 3:90–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2017c) Law, normativity and supervenience. In: Brożek B, Rotolo A, Stelmach J (eds) Supervenience and normativity. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 123–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2020) The legal mind. a new introduction to legal epistemology. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B, Stelmach J, Kurek B (eds) (2017) The province of Jurisprudence naturalized. Wolters Kluwer, Warsaw

    Google Scholar 

  • Chilovi S, Pavlakos G (2019) Law-determination as grounding: a common grounding framework for jurisprudence. Legal Theory 25:53–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (2015) Philosophical foundations of human rights: an overview. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 1–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Danish Institute of International Affairs (1999) Humanitarian intervention: legal and political aspects. Copenhagen

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine K (1994) Essence and modality. Philos Perspect 8:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth A (1981) The basis and content of human rights. Nomos 23:119–147

    Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth A (1982) Human rights: essays on justification and application. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Gizbert-Studnicki T (2015) Metafizyka Pozytywizmu Prawniczego. Principia 61:19–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Gizbert-Studnicki T (2016) The social sources thesis, metaphysics and metaphilosophy. In: Banaś P, Dyrda A, Gizbert Studnicki T (eds) Metaphilosophy of law. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 121–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Gizbert-Studnicki T (2021) Social facts and legal facts: Perils of Hume’s Guillotine. In: Spaak T, Mindus P (eds) The Cambridge companion to legal positivism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 419–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (2008) On human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (2015) The relativity and ethnocentricity of human rights. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 555–569

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hapla M (2018) Theory of needs as justification of human rights: current approaches and problems of uncertainty and normativeness. Age Human Rights J 10:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739) A treatise of human nature. John Noon, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kment B (2017) Varieties of modality. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/modality-varieties/

  • Leiter B (2007) Naturalizing jurisprudence: Essays on American legal realism and naturalism in legal philosophy. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B, Etchemendy M (2017) Naturalism in legal philosophy. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/lawphil-naturalism/

  • Lewis D (1973) Counterfactuals. Blackwell Publishers, Harvard University Press, Oxford/Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao SM (2015) Human rights as fundamental conditions for a goof life. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 79–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Makowski P (2011) Gilotyna Hume’a Przegląd Filozoficzny. Nowa Seria 76:317–334

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazurkiewicz S (2019) Review of Marek Piechowiak Plato’s conception of justice and the question of human dignity Sophia. Int J Philos Tradit 59:177–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazurkiewicz S (2020) Marek Piechowiak’s Plato’s conception of justice and the question of human dignity (2019). Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 106:471–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel C (2017) Possible worlds. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/possible-worlds/

  • Mikhail J (2012) Moral grammar and human rights: some reflections on cognitive science and enlightenment rationalism. In: Goodman R, Jinks D, Woods AK (eds) Understanding social action, promoting human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 160–202

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller D (2007) National responsibility and global justice. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller D (2012) Grounding human rights. Crit Rev Int Soc Polit Philos 15:407–427

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2000) Women and human development: the capabilities approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2006) Frontiers of justice: disability, nationality, species membership. The Belknap Press Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2011) Creating capabilities, the human development approach. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge/London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2020) Naturalism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/naturalism/

  • Pardo M, Patterson D (2013) Minds brains and law. The conceptual foundations of law and neuroscience. Oxford, OUP

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piechowiak M (1999) Filozofia Praw Człowieka. Prawa Człowieka w świetle ich Międzynarodowej Ochrony. Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL, Lublin

    Google Scholar 

  • Piechowiak M (2019) Plato’s conception of justice and the question of human dignity. Peter Lang, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D (2012) A positivist route for explaining how. Facts Make Law Legal Theory 18:139–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge T (2002) World poverty and human rights: cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (2002) The collapse of fact/value dichotomy and other essays. Harvard University Press, Harvard-London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The laws of people. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2010) Human rights without foundations. In: Besson S Tasioulas J (eds) The philosophy of international law. OUP, pp 321–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2015) Human rights in the emerging world order life. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 217-236

    Google Scholar 

  • Renzo M (2015) Human needs, human rights. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 570–587

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson T, Atkins P (2018) Essential vs. Accidental Properties. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/essential-accidental/

  • Rosen M (2013) Dignity: the case against. In: McCrdudden C (ed) Understanding human dignity. OUP, Oxford, pp143–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1999) Development and freedom. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (2005) Human rights and capabilities. J Human Dev 6:151–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tahko T, Lowe J (2016) Ontological Dependence. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/dependence-ontological/

  • Tasioulas J (2011) On the nature of human rights. In: Ernst G, Heilinger JC (eds) The philosophy of human rights: contemporary controversies. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 17–59

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (2013) Human dignity and the foundations of human rights. In: McCrdudden C (ed) Understanding human dignity. OUP, Oxford, pp 291–312

    Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (2015) On the foundations of human rights. In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 45–70

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2012) Dignity, rank and rights. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2013) Human rights: a critique of the Raz/Rawls approach NYU School of law. Public Law Res Pap 13:1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2015) Is dignity foundation of human rights? In: Cruft R, Liao SM, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. OUP, Oxford, pp 117–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Witkowski K (1975) The “is-ought” gap: deduction or justification? Philos Phenomenol Res 36:233–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zajadło J (2005) Dylematy Humanitarnej Interwencji: Historia, Etyka, Polityka, Prawo. Gdańsk, Arche

    Google Scholar 

  • Zajadło J (2010) Humanitarian intervention: threat to international order, moral imperative or customary norm in statu nascendi? In: Zajadło J, Sykuna S, Widłak T (eds) Humanitarian interventions. reflection of the Special Workshop at the 23rd IVR World Congress. Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Gdańskiego: Gdańsk, pp 15–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Załuski W (2009a) Evolutionary theory and legal philosophy. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Załuski W (2009b) Ewolucyjna Filozofia Prawa. Wolters Kluwer, Warszawa

    Google Scholar 

  • Załuski W (2018) Law and evil. The evolutionary perspective. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Mazurkiewicz, S. (2023). Contemporary Approaches in the Philosophy of Human Rights. In: Grounding Human Rights in Human Nature. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 142. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-30734-8_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-30734-8_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-30733-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-30734-8

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics