Skip to main content

Evolutionary Causation and Teleosemantics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Life and Mind

Part of the book series: Interdisciplinary Evolution Research ((IDER,volume 8))

Abstract

Disputes about the causal structure of natural selection have implications for teleosemantics. Etiological, mainstream teleosemantics is based on a causalist view of natural selection. The core of its solution to Brentano’s Problem lies in the solution to Kant’s Puzzle provided by the Modern Synthesis concerning populational causation. In this paper, I suggest that if we adopt an alternative, statisticalist view on natural selection, the door is open for two reflections. First, it allows for setting different challenges to etiological teleosemantics that arise if a statisticalist reading of natural selection is right. Second, by providing a different solution to Kant’s Puzzle based on individual causes of evolution, statisticalism promotes a different answer to Brentano’s Problem, what I label as Agential Teleosemantics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is relevant to remark that the connection between causation and misrepresentations takes place within teleosemantics’ aim of naturalizing intentionality. In this sense, teleosemantics was born against two classical approaches to representational content. One is the idea that the content of a representation is determined by its relation with other representations – known as intensionalist theories. The difficulty of this attempt is naturalism, insofar as we cannot be naturalists and simultaneously anchor intentionality in other intentional stuff. In this view, misrepresentation cannot be a problem of causation insofar as content is not determined by reference but by how representations relate with each other. Teleosemantics opposes this view; it provides a referentialist theory of content. However, the second theory that teleosemantics rejects is the causalist one, which is also referentialist. Even if causalist theories of content pursue a naturalistic view of intentionality, they seem incapable of dealing with misrepresentations. In this sense, teleosemantics emerged as the attempt to solve misrepresentation and simultaneously accept the causalist view of intentional explanations defended by causalist theories. Therefore, misrepresentation becomes primarily an issue of causation once we stress the commitment of teleosemantics to naturalism. I thank an anonymous review for noting the importance of this clarification.

  2. 2.

    Certainly, there could be a non-naturalist teleosemantic project. For instance, if we adopt a theological view of organism design, we can define the function of representational systems but in this case not from a scientific perspective. Moreover, as pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, there might be an attempt to solve Brentano’s Problem from the notion of biological function with any specific solution to Kant’s Puzzle, for instance, claiming that the notion of function is fundamental. As the reviewer recognizes, the teleosemantic project that departs from such a position may not be considered naturalist.

  3. 3.

    Other figures of the Causalist School are Abrams (2012), Millstein (2006), Pence (2021), Pence and Ramsey (2013), Ramsey (2016), Reisman and Forber (2005), and Stephens (2004).

  4. 4.

    I thank an anonymous review for comments on this point.

  5. 5.

    Note that Neander’s example concerns the current frequency of a trait achieving or not its function. However, this scenario can also be presented in relation to past, historical frequencies. Let’s appeal to the case of sperm, used by Millikan. Rightly, she points out that the current frequency of a trait function does not lead us directly to its proper function—sperms perform their proper function at a very low frequency. However, this argument applies not only to current frequencies but also to historical frequencies (its frequency during selection processes): it is not necessary that in selection processes a trait must have a high frequency to be selected for. Sperms could perform their proper function infrequently and nonetheless be selected to perform such function. I thank an anonymous review for comments on this point.

  6. 6.

    Certainly, one can take a midterm position and argue for both individual and populational causes of evolution. As Walsh noted (2003, 2019), this view defends a two-force model (cf. Sect. 4): evolutionary forces come from two different sources. However, as it was remarked above, this view is not endorsed by statisticalists insofar as it blurs the nature of populational explanations based on trait fitness. There are not two forces but two different levels of explanation (cf. Walsh (2019) for details).

References

  • Abrams M (2012) Measured, modeled, and causal conceptions of fitness. Front Genet 3:196

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought. Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A (2003) Ernst Mayr’s’ ultimate/proximate’distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biol Philos 18(4):553–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Lewontin R (2004) The confusions of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 55(2):347–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashby R (1991) Principles of the self-organizing system. In: Klir GJ (ed) Facets of systems science. Springer, Boston, MA, pp 521–536

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Author (2021) Biosemiotics at the bridge of eco-devo and representational theories of mind. Ital J Philos Language 15(2):59–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Author (2022) Agential Teleosemantics. PhD Thesis. Autonomous Universtiy of Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran X, Di Paolo E, Rohde M (2009) Defining agency: individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and Spatio-temporality in action. Adapt Behav 17(5):367–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson P, Gluckman P (2011) Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy LV (1969) General system theory: foundations, development, applications. George Braziller, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard M (2000) Information and representation in autonomous agents. Cogn Syst Res 1(2):65–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard M (2003) The biological emergence of representation. In: Brown T, Smith L (eds) Reductionism and the development of knowledge. Psychology Press, pp 115–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard M (2009) Interactivism: a manifesto. New Ideas Psychol 27(1):85–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boogerd F (2007) Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Bromberger S (1966) Why-questions. In: Colodny R (ed) Mind and cosmos. University of Pittsburgh Press, pp 86–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B, Pocheville A, Griffiths P (2020) Signals that make a difference. Br J Philos Sci 71(1):233–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camazine S, Deneubourg J, Franks NR et al (eds) (2003) Self-organization in biological systems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R (1975) Functional analysis. J Philos 72(20):741

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species: by means of natural selection or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo EA (2005) Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 4(4):429–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1998) Concepts. Where cognitive science went wrong. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J, Piattelli-Palmarini M (2010) What Darwin got wrong. Profile, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson J, Papineau D (2019) Teleosemantics, selection and novel contents. Biol Philos 34(3):36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S, Epel D (2015) Ecological developmental biology: the environmental regulation of development, health, and evolution. Sinauer Associates, Inc. Publishers, Sunderland, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin B (2001) How the leopard changed its spots. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb G (1997) Synthesizing nature-nurture: prenatal roots of instinctive behavior. Taylor Francis Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (2013) Lehrman’s dictum: information and explanation in developmental biology. Dev Psychobiol 55(1):22–32

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (2016) Proximate and ultimate information in biology. In: Couch M, Pfeifer J (eds) The philosophy of Philip Kitcher. Oxford University Press, pp 74–97

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (2017) Genetic, epigenetic and exogenetic information in development and evolution. Interface Focus 7(5):20160152

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P, Pocheville A, Calcott B et al (2015) Measuring causal specificity. Philos Sci 82(4):529–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P, Stotz K (2013) Genetics and philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamburger V (1980) Embryology and the modern synthesis in evolutionary biology. In: Mayr E, Provine W (eds) The evolutionary synthesis. Perspectives on the unification of biology. Harvard University Press, pp 97–112

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb M (2005) Evolution in four dimensions : genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (1993) The origins of order: self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2002) The century of the gene. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. London

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2010) The mirage of a space between nature and nurture. Duke University Press, Durhnam, NC

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R (2001) The triple helix: gene, organism, and environment. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald G, Papineau D (2006) Introduction: prospects and problems for teleosemantics. In: Macdonald G, Papineau D (eds) Teleosemantics. Clarendon Press, pp 1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 99(2):55–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H, Varela F (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition. Springer, Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology: kinds of causes, predictability, and teleology are viewed by a practicing biologist. Science 134(3489):1501–1506

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1974) Teleological and teleonomic, a new analysis. In: Cohen R, Wartofsky M (eds) A portrait of twenty-five years, Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 133–159

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1991) The ideological resistance to Darwin’s theory of natural selection. Proc Am Philos Soc 135(2):123–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Michel G, Moore C (1995) Developmental psychobiology: an interdisciplinary science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories: new foundations for realism. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1989) In Defense of proper functions. Philos Sci 56(2):288–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2000) Naturalizing intentionality. Philosophy Documentation Center 9(83):83–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2017) Beyond concepts: unicepts, language, and natural information. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. Br J Philos Sci 57(4):627–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell M (2009) Complexity: a guided tour. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno A, Mossio M (2015) Biological Autonomy. Springer, Netherlands

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moss L (2003) What genes can’t do. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio M, Saborido C, Moreno A (2009) An organizational account of biological functions. Br J Philos Sci 60(4):813–841

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller G, Newman S (eds) (2003) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual Analyst’s Defense. Philos Sci 58(2):168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1995) Misrepresenting and malfunctioning. Philos Stud 79(2):109–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2017a) A mark of the mental. MIT Press Ltd, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2017b) Functional analysis and the species design. Synthese 194(4):1147–1168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2008) The music of life: biology beyond genes. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee J, Laland K, Feldman M (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (1985) The ontogeny of information, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, Durhnam, NC

    Google Scholar 

  • Pence C (2021) The causal structure of natural selection. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pence C, Ramsey G (2013) A new foundation for the propensity interpretation of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 64(4):851–881

    Google Scholar 

  • Pittendrigh CS (1958) Adaptation, natural selection, and behavior. Behav Evol 390:416

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik A (2017) Idealization and the aims of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Prado Salas JG (2018) Whose purposes? Biol Teleol Intentionality Synthese 195(10):4507–4524

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey G (2016) The causal structure of evolutionary theory. Australas J Philos 94(3):421–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisman K, Forber P (2005) Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philos Sci 72(5):1113–1123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert JS (2006) Embryology, epigenesis and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting CD, Pigliucci M (1998) Phenotypic evolution: a reaction norm perspective. Sinauer Associates Incorporated

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder T (2004) New norms for teleosemantics. In: Clapin H, Staines P, Slezak P (eds) Representation in mind. Elsevier, pp 91–106

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2018) Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press, NY

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1980) Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philos Sci 47(3):350–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2013) Trait fitness is not a propensity, but fitness variation is. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C: Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 44(3):336–341

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C (2004) Selection, drift, and the “forces” of evolution. Philos Sci 71(4):550–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz K (2006) With ‘genes’ like that, who needs an environment? Postgenomics’s argument for the ‘ontogeny of information’. Philos Sci 73(5):905–917

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz K (2017) Why developmental niche construction is not selective niche construction: and why it matters. Interface Focus 7(5):20160157

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz K (2019) Biological information in developmental and evolutionary systems. In: Uller T, Laland K (eds) Evolutionary causation: biological and philosophical reflections. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 323–344

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sultan S (2015) Organism and environment: ecological development, niche construction, and adaption. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sultan S, Moczek AP, Walsh D (2022) Bridging the explanatory gaps: what can we learn from a biological agency perspective? BioEssays 2100185:1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G (2014) Homology, genes, and evolutionary innovation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2000) Chasing shadows: natural selection and adaptation. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 31(1):135–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2003) Fit and diversity: explaining adaptive evolution. Philos Sci 70(2):280–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74(3):281–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2010) Two neo-darwinisms. Hist Philos Life Sci 32(2):317–339

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2014) Function and teleology. In: Thompson P, Walsh D (eds) Evolutionary biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 193–216

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2015) Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2019) The paradox of population thinking: first order causes and higher order effects. In: Uller T, Laland K (eds) Evolutionary causation: biological and philosophical reflections. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 227–246

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69(3):429–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank the useful comments and suggestions of an anonymous reviewer. I am grateful to Sergio Balari for the discussion of the ideas presented here and for his help to make the language of this paper closer to readable English. This work has received the support of the Spanish Government through grant FFI2017-87699-P and the National Agency of Investigation and Innovation (Uruguay) through grant POS_EXT_2018_1_154759.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tiago Rama .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rama, T. (2023). Evolutionary Causation and Teleosemantics. In: Viejo, J.M., Sanjuán, M. (eds) Life and Mind. Interdisciplinary Evolution Research, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-30304-3_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics