Skip to main content

From the “Still Covered” to the “Pure Primordial” Phenomena and Back: The External World in the Phenomenology of Conrad-Martius

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Hedwig Conrad-Martius

Part of the book series: Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences ((WHPS,volume 8))

  • 82 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter addresses the two questions HCM poses at the opening of her first great treatise, “On the Ontology and Doctrine of Appearance of the Real External World” (HCM, 1916): “In which real mode are perceived “essences (Washeiten)” given to us, in more or less big definiteness (Bestimmtheit)? And where do we encounter them in their concrete realization?” (HCM, 1916, 356). These questions initiate the problematization of the given and thus pose a clear limit between the immediate appearance of the external world and its real being, which in HCM’s opinion are not identical (HCM, 1916, 427). The philosopher deals with the first through a careful investigation of what she calls “feeling givenness” (Empfindungsgegebenheit) and the second through a keen observation of the givenness of “manifest-appearance”. These two tracks are woven together, and thus, the phenomenology of the external world moves simultaneously in two opposing directions: by following the line from the “still covered” to the “pure primordial” phenomena we are looking for the ideal reality that brings about the reality of things. This reality does not manifest itself on the phenomenal level but transpires as covering or hiding reality as such. However, since the phenomenon of the external world is not an idea, while moving from the “primordial” to the “covered”, we search for the reality that transcends its ideal boundaries—a transcending that is embodied in the fundamental essence of reality achieving external dimensions. The real transcendence of the external world to human consciousness is revealed in these opposing directions, and thus, the reality of the phenomenon of the external world is confirmed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for example: Husserl (1970a/1900, 168; 1984a/1901, 10). Much has been written about this statement, which became phenomenology’s slogan. See, for instance: (Seifert, 1995, 92–98; Kuhn, 1969, 397–399). The Circle was composed of a group of philosophers the first generation of phenomenologists, whose prominent members were: Alexander Pfänder, Johannes Daubert, Moritz Geiger, Theodor Conrad, Adolf Reinach, Dietrich von Hildebrand, Maximilian Beck, Max Scheler, Jean Hering, Alexander Koyré, Roman Ingarden, Edith Stein, and Hedwig Conrad-Martius. For further reading about the circle, see: Avé-Lallemant (1975).

  2. 2.

    The Munich Circle philosophers drew their inspiration from Husserl’s struggle, in Logical Investigation, against psychologism, relativism, and various forms of reductionism Husserl (1970a/1900, §23 51, §31 74; 1975, §23 82, §31 117), and especially from his fundamental argument that it is possible to observe the conditions of consciousness and to study them in isolation from the thinking subject Husserl (1970b/1901, 10–13, 1984a/1901, 240–245). See also (Walther, 1955, 190; Schmücker, 1956, 31). HCM declares the influence of Logical Investigation on her current study, see: HCM (1916, 355 n. 1). The principles of observation directed at the object were formulated by Hering. See: Hering (1921, 496). HCM stated her agreement with Hering’s approach, see HCM (1923, 162). For a detailed discussion of the object-directed approach in the Munich Circle, see (Avé-Lallemant, 1959, 89–105; Schmücker, 1956, 3–8).

  3. 3.

    Heinemann argues that the disturbance in the process of the appearance also involved the disintegration of the foundation layer of the spirit, which as such “rises from the phenomenon and returns and sinks into it in order to embody itself there”. Thus, restoring the phenomena naturally involves an appropriate understanding of the spirit (Heinemann, 1960, 184). Indeed, one of the most important achievements of HCM’s realistic phenomenology deals with the formation of a realistic perception of transcendentalism. This perception requires a separate discussion that exceeds the scope of this article.

  4. 4.

    See also HCM (1965c, 377; 1965d, 347). For further discussion regarding the issue of the phenomenological method of essence intuition, with particular emphasis on the role of the realistic school within it, see (Reinach, 1913, 1921b; Pfänder, 1913, 2005, 1–13; Schmücker, 1956, 1–33; Ebel, 1965, 1–25).

  5. 5.

    The Circle’s members often wrote about the unique essence intuition that guided them. See Avé-Lallemant (1988, 69; Walther, 1955, 21; Reinach, 1951, 21–73; Schapp, 1910, 12; Pfänder, 1913; Ebel, 1965, 1–25; Schmücker, 1956, 1–33).

  6. 6.

    See here also Husserl (2002, 63–65; 1952b, 58–59). For the realistic phenomenologists, the main difficulty in a defining approach concerns the lack of certainty regarding the actual meeting with the object. On the differences between essence intuition and a defining approach, see: Ebel (1965, 15–19).

  7. 7.

    HCM explains that it is a mistake (common in positivistic literature) to identify between an “existence independent of consciousness” and the real external world, see: HCM (1916, 391).

  8. 8.

    HCM clarifies the title “Doctrine of Appearance” as referring to the realm of the object between “nature” and “the essence of life” that stands in relation to the perceiving subject that has existence within it HCM (1916, 352–354 n. 1). However, nature as such is not discussed in Doctrine of Appearance and remains, to a great extent, a hidden layer that would only be developed in her later writings see in particular HCM (1965b/1961). Doctrine of Appearance is a development of the first chapter in an early essay from 1912, “The Epistemological Elements of Positivism” HCM (1920a/1912, 10–24). This essay was awarded a prize by the Philosophy Faculty of Gottingen University and was later termed the “prize essay” (Preisschrift). The subtitle of Doctrine of Appearance—“Regarding the Criticism of Positivistic Theories” and the polemic with positivism that appears throughout the discussion HCM (1916, 345–347, 352, 357–358, 361–365, 378, 382–386, 390–391, 398–400, 423, 425)—clearly indicate its roots in the essay that preceded it. On 3 July 1912, an expanded version of the first chapter of the prize essay was printed and submitted as a dissertation in a form almost identical to Doctrine of Appearance and recognized as a doctorate by Pfänder at Munich see Avé-Lallemant (1965/1966, 212). In the Postscript added to a special printing of the essay in 1920, HCM established her shift to ontology-oriented studies and seems to know that her original plan to develop the rest of the chapters in her essay on positivism will not be realized HCM (1920b, 130). See here also: Avé-Lallemant (1971, 213). Avé-Lallemant, her assistant, the curator of her estate, and the editor of her writings, told me in conversation with him (4 July 2003, Munich) that Doctrine of Appearance received positive responses upon its publication.

  9. 9.

    Heinemann expressed very similar ideas to HCM’s in his article on concrete phenomenology. He mentions her article “Phänomenologie und Spekulation” HCM (1965c/1956), see Heinemann (1960, 185 n. 2). However, he does not refer to her most relevant treatise to his discussion, Doctrine of Appearance, with which he was undoubtedly familiar.

  10. 10.

    This argument also applies to studies dealing with HCM’s perception of the world, such as Ales Bello (2004). Exceptions to this statement include Schmücker, who mentioned Doctrine of Appearance once in his dissertation, defining the essay as a “decisive breakthrough” Schmücker (1956, 39 n. 1), and Ebel (1965, 16 n. 42, 17, 22 n. 48, 42). However, both these researchers lack a systematic and comprehensive discussion on the range of issues handled in the essay.

  11. 11.

    Regarding the “semblance of reality (Aussehen einer Realität)” typical of objects of representation, see HCM (1916, 356, 441 n. 1).

  12. 12.

    Helmut Kuhn (1969, 399) well described it as follows: The things to which the gaze is directed are always known in advance. We do not start from the zero point. They show themselves to us, but they are covered. They are placed before us as known but also as riddles, and force upon us a distinction between what the things are in their origin and the essence that reveals the observation that penetrates them. In this context, see also Husserl’s “The principle of all principles” Husserl (1952a/1913, §24; 2012/1913, §24), in which alongside establishing the value of the primordial givenness there is also recognition of the fact that things are given to use under certain restrictions.

  13. 13.

    For more on the phenomenological given, see Spiegelberg (1984).

  14. 14.

    In Doctrine of Appearance, HCM refers critically to skepticism in various contexts in which she discusses positivism. See, for example: HCM (1916, 358, 398).

  15. 15.

    See especially: HCM (1916, 355, 370, 398, 407, 413, 418, 423, 446, 496, 500, 513). Husserl understood skepticism as a denial of the apodictism, meaning the necessary and universal truths essential for a theory to have meaning. He distinguished between three forms of skepticism: logical, “noetic”, and metaphysical; see: Husserl 1970a/1900, 134–143, Husserl (1975/1900, 214–226; 1970a/1900, 134–141). Husserl, and like him, HCM in Doctrine of Appearance considered metaphysical skepticism to be the most problematic. For further discussion of the issue of skepticism in phenomenology, see Wachterhauser (1996). On certainty in Husserlian phenomenology, see Kołakowski (1975).

  16. 16.

    The distinction between these two types of objects has important implications for the issue of the I: the overt objects require the restricting and restraining of the I, while the covert objects necessitate its active involvement. As mentioned, the issue of the I exceeds the scope of this paper.

  17. 17.

    HCM continued to deal with the relation between the object’s thusness and its selfness in her other writings. See, for example, HCM (1957, 57). In this context, see the critique of Ebel (1965, 42) regarding the realistic direction in phenomenology, including that of HCM, which he did not believe could posit true realism: reality becomes a mere “phenomenon” of reality for them, and therefore, it is precisely not real Ebel (1965, 2). More favorable approaches to this school appear in Seifert (1995, 97–98), who focused their contribution on the thusness-experience (Soseinserfahrung), and Heinemann (1960), who noted the importance of focusing on the appearance.

  18. 18.

    Hermann Krings, who was professedly influenced by HCM, explains that focusing on the object as existing real reality is not simply equivalent to reversing the Kantian beginning in which the existing is directed in its self to consciousness. The premise here is that there exists a real relation between the existing and the essence referring to it; however, this assumption does not include an argument regarding the possibility of consciousness. See Krings (1960, 193–195).

  19. 19.

    Like HCM, Spiegelberg too addressed the justification of relying on sensory data within a realistic perception. In his opinion, a critical phenomenological examination of the immediate phenomena of reality themselves could remove the most common objections regarding the reliability of perception mediated by the senses. See Spiegelberg (1975, 153).

  20. 20.

    Spiegelberg explains that the phenomenon and reality do not exclude each other, meaning that what is real exists within itself and from itself, and it can be presented to us in its very reality. This means that actual things in the world can remain exactly as they are even when they enter into relations with us and are presented to us. Spiegelberg calls the phenomena in which we are involved “subjectival”, not in the sense that they do not have real existence or that they are deceptive, but that they are objective parts of the subject and of his world, see: Spiegelberg (1975, 134–135). Moreover, in his opinion, the reality of the subjectival phenomena is completely certain Spiegelberg (1975, 149). In any case, the subjectival reality constitutes only a very small part of our total reality and of reality as a whole Spiegelberg (1975, 135).

  21. 21.

    Like HCM, Spiegelberg also emphasizes that what can be referred to as the “claim” for reality entailed in real existence. In this context, he defines a “phenomenon of reality” as one where the phenomenal object presents itself along with the argument about its being real. Therefore, a reality-phenomenon is one that is both positioned as real and distinguished from “mere phenomena” that do not claim reality. See Spiegelberg (1975, 133).

  22. 22.

    In “Real Ontology” (Realontologie), in her discussion of materiality, HCM returns to the concept of the “surface”. Her argument in principle is that the material entity has depth and internality, but only its surface reaches sensory appearance. What is outside is the lighted part, and what is inside, in the depths, is the dark and closed part. She states that there is a causal relation between these two components of the material entity, so that just because there is depth there is also a surface. See HCM (1923, §55–§56 205–206). In this essay, she refers to the concept of the surface also in other places, see: HCM (1923, §37 194; §57–§61 206–209; §72 214; §107 235–236).

  23. 23.

    Spiegelberg explains that the very lack of dependence on the subject is “a very fundamental and essential consequence of reality” (except for cases of real actions of the subject, which of course depend upon him); see: Spiegelberg (1975, 132 n. 2).

  24. 24.

    See here the discussion of the matter in the introductory section and in: HCM (1951, 10–11).

  25. 25.

    Spiegelberg (1975, 148) presents objects’ lack of probe-resistance to our will as a hallmark, sometimes significant, of their reality.

  26. 26.

    HCM clarifies that the innovation is not in such a perception being capable of misleading, but in the foundation of this experience not “really” being in faith, that the material feltness has direct relations with the external world HCM (1916, 433), but that these relations actually exist.

  27. 27.

    At this point too, Heinemann’s position is very similar to that of HCM. In his opinion, the primordial phenomenon of the human being is not consciousness but appearance, meaning the entry of appearance and change within appearance (humans live within pictures before they know it). In contrast, consciousness is an epiphenomenon or a phenomenon in retrospect, which, as such, denotes a reflective action that takes place only after the appearances collapse. Thus, he determines that the meaning of phenomenology is “the doctrine of appearance”. See Heinemann (1960, 186–187).

  28. 28.

    Spiegelberg characterizes the peripheral field of our perception as “marginal openness” (Spiegelberg 1975, 147), meaning that this field is never sharply cut like its boundaries. However, he stresses that peripherality does not denote unreality. What we perceive at the periphery of the perceptual filed is not just vague configurations but usually well-defined structures subject to reduced clarity. We can still see the phenomenon itself, through these modifications, and understand its structure prior to it being subjected to influences. More importantly, the structural openness of what exists in the periphery of our perceptual field indicates that reality does not reach its end in accordance with the end of our field, meaning that it does not cease at its periphery but continues beyond it. Thus, openness shows, in his opinion, that the phenomena of reality are self-standing.

  29. 29.

    One of the typical arguments of the realistic phenomenological approach deals with the temporal gap between the real way in which the thing exists and the way in which it is perceived (see: Geiger, 1930, 170). Spiegelberg claims that the situation is identical for any sensory perception, which, in his opinion, “can never give what is present, but only what has just passed. And since the past no longer exists, we can never see the original object itself but only its “trace”, which means its cast or likeness” (Spiegelberg, 1975, 157).

  30. 30.

    In order to reach greater accuracy in presenting the felt, one should tackle questions that exceed her main discussion in Doctrine of Appearance, such as what is the nature of the I that allows itself to be framed (einrahmt) through the body-entity (körperlich Entität), so that it is really restricted by it? And how do the relations between the I and the living body describe themselves phenomenally? (HCM, 1916, 541–542).

  31. 31.

    The discussion will revolve only around existences that appear in a strict objective manner and not around what HCM calls “the loose givenness of a sensorially manifest material”, which she grants marginal space in Doctrine of Appearance (HCM, 1916, 504–505).

  32. 32.

    In this context, see also: Husserl (1970b, 17–18; 1984a, 253–255).

  33. 33.

    In the literature, the “quale” denotes the contents of the subjective experience of mental states, usually excluding any intersubjective aspect. Thomas Nagel characterized the quale as “feeling itself in a certain way” Nagel (1974). Unlike HCM, some philosophers deprived the qualia of existence Dennett (1993), but most philosophers and natural scientists believe that the existence of the contents of the subjective experience is undoubted (see: Beckermann, 2001, 358). This puzzling term has appeared in the philosophical discourse already since Descartes, has been repeated by Locke and Hume, and has frequently been mentioned in the twentieth century. See in particular: Lewis (1991, 89 ff.).

  34. 34.

    We should distinguish between the term “play” here, which does not express detracting from the reality of the appearance, and “playing with the reality of objects”, which is typical of the perceptual state and expresses the weakness of the dimension of reality within it (see: HCM, 1916, 379).

  35. 35.

    See here also HCM’s references to “an appropriate ‘receptacle’ (Gefäβ)” of the real thing HCM (1923, 215, 217, 219).

  36. 36.

    Spiegelberg, who characterized the sensory organs as “phenomena of reality in themselves”, is helpful in illuminating the problematic HCM handles here as follows: “Is there a way back, as it were, from the retina via the cortex and mental processes to the original object outside which supposedly started the whole chain of physical and physiological processes?” Spiegelberg (1975, 150). He adds that this problem is meaningful only if you assume that the physical objects, as conditioned by our sense perception, our sensory organs, and the physiological processes involved in them, are proven realities, and that one can know real objects Spiegelberg (1975, 151).

  37. 37.

    HCM argues that these aspects of the sensorially manifest appearing are similar to those reflected in primitive observation. Yet, apparently due to their assumed diminished sophistication or even manipulation by consciousness, she finds them as revealing a correct façade of the sensorially manifest appearance (see: HCM, 1916, 478–479).

References

  • Ales Bello, A. (2004). The Controversy about the Existence of the World in Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenological School: A. Reinach, R. Ingarden, H. Conrad-Martius, E. Stein. In Analecta Husserliana (ANHU) (Vol. 79, pp. 97–115).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ales Bello, A. (2008). Forward. Axiomathes, 18, 395–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. (1959). Der kategoriale Ort des Seelischen in der Naturwirklichkeit: Eine Untersuchung auf der Grundlage der realontologischen Arbeiten von Hedwig Conrad-Martius. Dissertation, Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. (1971). Phänomenologie und Realität, Vergleichende Untersuchungen zur ‘München-Göttinger’ und ‘Freiburger’ Phänomenology. München: Habilitationsschrift.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. (1975). Die Antithese Freiburg-München in der Geschichte der Phänomenologie. In H. Kuhn, E. Avé-Lallemant, & R. Gladiator (Eds.), Die Münchener Phänomenologie, Vorträge des Internationalen Kongresses in München 13–18 April 1971 (Phaenomenologica 65) (pp. 19–38) (H. Kuhn, E. Avé-Lallemant, and R. Gladiator, Eds.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. (1988). Die phänomenologische Bewegung: Ursprung, Anfänge und Ausblick. In H. R. Sepp (Ed.), Edmund Husserl und die phänomenologische Bewegung, Zeugnisse in Text und Bild (pp. 61–75). Freiburg and München: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, U. (1965 [1966]). Hedwig Conrad Martius. Jahrbuch der Evangelischen Akademie Tutzing, XV, 203–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckermann, A. (2001). Analytische Einführung in die Philosophie des Geistes (2nd ed.). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1916). Zur Ontologie und Erscheinungslehre der realen Außenwelt. In Jahrbuch—für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung III (pp. 345–542). Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1920a [1912]). Die erkenntnisstheoretischen Grundlagen des Positivismus. Bergzabern: Heinrich Müller. (Private print).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1920b). Nachwort. In Die erkenntnisstheoretischen Grundlagen des Positivismus (pp. 130–131). Bergzabern: Heinrich Müller. (Private print).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1923). Realontologie, Buch I: Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung (Vol. VI, pp. 159–333). Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1951). Vorwort. In A. Reinach (Ed.), Was ist Phänomenologie? Mit einem Vorwort von Hedwig Conrad-Martius (pp. 5–17). München: Kösel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1957). Das Sein. München: Kösel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1959a [1958]). Die transzendentale und die ontologische Phänomenologie. In H. L. van Vreda & Jacques Taminiaux (Eds.), Edmund Husserl 1859–1959—Recueil Commémoratif Publié A L’occasion De Centenaire De La Naissance Du Philosophe (Phaenomenologica 4) (pp. 175–184). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. (Reprinted in: HCM 1965a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1959b). Phenomenology and Speculation. Philosophy Today, III(1–4), 43–51. (Translation of: HCM 1965c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1964 [1950]). Naturwissenschaft und Naturphilosophie. In Schriften zur Philosophie (Vol. II, pp. 23–46). München: Kösel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1965a [1958]). Die transzendentale und die ontologische Phänomenologie. In Schriften zur Philosophie (Vol. III, pp. 393–402). München: Kösel. (Printed also in: HCM 1959a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1965b [1961]). Die Wahrheit der Dinge. In Schriften zur Philosophie (Vol. III, pp. 421–444). München: Kösel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1965c [1956]). Phänomenologie und Spekulation. In Schriften zur Philosophie (Vol. III, pp. 370–384). München: Kösel. (English translation: HCM 1959b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1965d [1956]). Über das Wesen des Wesens. In Schriften zur Philosophie (Vol. III, pp. 335–356). München: Kösel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1993). Quining Qualia. In A. Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science (pp. 42–77). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebel, G. (1965). Untersuchungen zu einer Realistischen Grundlegung der phänomenologischen Wesensschau. Dissertation, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geiger, M. (1930). Die Wirklichkeit der Wissenschaften und die Metaphysik. Bonn: F. Cohen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinemann, F. (1960). Erscheinen und Sein—Prolegomena zu einer konkreten Phänomenologie. In R. Wisser (Ed.), Sinn und Sein, Ein philosophisches Symposion (pp. 183–219). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. (1921). Bemerkung über das Wesen, die Wesenheit und die Idee. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung VI (pp. 495–543). Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1952a [1913]). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und Phänomenologischen Philosophie. In E. Buch (Ed.), Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Haag: Martinus Nijhoff. (English translation: Husserl 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1952b). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. In Z. Buch (Ed.), phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. Marly Biemel, Husserliana IV. Haag: Martinus Nijhoff. (English translation: Husserl 2002).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970a [1900]). Logical Investigations (Vol. I, J. Findlay, Trans.). London and New York, NY: Routledge. (Translation of: Husserl 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970b [1901]). Logical Investigations (Vol. II, J. Findlay, Trans.). London and New York, NY: Routledge. (Translation of: Husserl 1984a and Husserl 1984b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1975 [1900]). Logische Untersuchungen, Prolegomena zur reinen Logik, Husserliana XVIII. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. (English translation: Husserl 1970a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984a [1901]). Logische Untersuchungen, Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis, Husserliana XIX (1). The Hague, Boston, MA and Lancaster: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. (English translation: Husserl 1970b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984b [1901]). Logische Untersuchungen, Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis, Husserliana XIX (2). The Hague, Boston, MA and Lancaster: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. (English translation: Husserl 1970b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002). Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband Erster Teil: Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. In U. Melle (Ed.), Untersuchung und zur Vorrede für die Neuafulage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913) Husserliana XX (1). Dordrecht, Boston, MA and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2012 [1913]). Ideas, General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology (W. R. Boyce Gibson, Trans.). London: Routledge. (Translation of: Husserl 1952a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kołakowski, L. (1975). Husserl and the Search for Certitude. New Haven, CT and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krings, H. (1960). Studie über Vorstellung und Sein. In R. Wisser (Ed.), Sinn und Sein, Ein philosophisches Symposion (pp. 193–208). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, H. (1969). Phänomenologie und Realität. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 23(3), 397–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1991). Mind and World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What Is It Like to Be a Bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfänder, A. (1913). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnung. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung I (Vol. 1, pp. 325–404). Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeiffer, A. (2005). Hedwig Conrad-Martius, Eine phänomenologische Sicht auf Natur und Welt. Würzburg: Orbis Phenomenologicus, Königshausen and Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1913). Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung I (Vol. 2, pp. 685–847). Halle: Max Niemeyer. (Reprint of: Reinach 1921; English translation: Reinach 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1921a [1914]). Vortrag über Phänomenologie. In A. Reinach (Ed.), Gesammelte Schriften (pp. 379–405). Halle: Max Niemeyer (Reprint of: Reinach 1951; English trans.: Reinach 1968; Reinach 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1921b). Die Apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes. In A. Reinach, Gesammelte Schriften (pp. 166–350). Halle: Max Niemeyer. (Reprint of: Reinach 1913; English translation: Reinach 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1951 [1914]). Was ist Phänomenologie? Mit einem Vorwort von Hedwig Conrad-Martius. München: Kösel. (Published also in: Reinach 1921a. English trans: Reinach 1968; Reinach 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1968 [1914]). What is Phenomenology? (D. Kelly, Trans.). Philosophical Forum, 1(2) (New Series), 231–256. (Translation of: Reinach, 1921, Reinach, 1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1969 [1914]). Concerning Phenomenology (W. Dallas, Trans.). The Personalist, 50(2), 194–221. (Translation of: Reinach, 1921, Reinach, 1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1983 [1913]). The Apriori Foundations of Civil Law (J. Crosby, Trans.). Aletheia, 3, 1–142. (English translation of: Reinach, 1913, Reinach, 1921b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schapp, W. (1910). Beiträge zur Phänomenologie der Wahrnehmung. Göttingen: Kaestner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmücker, F. G. (1956). Die Phänomenologie als Methode der Wesenerkenntnis, unter besondere Berücksichtigung der Auffassung der München-Göttinger Phänomenologenschule. Dissertation, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seifert, J. (1995). Was ist Philosophie? Die Antwort der realistische Phänomenologie. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 49(3), 92–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1975). Doing Phenomenology: Essays on and in Phenomenology (Phaenomenologica 63). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1984). Three Types of the Given: The Encountered, the Search-Found, and the Striking. Husserl Studies, 1, 69–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wachterhauser, B. R. (1996). Introduction: The Shipwreck of Apodicticity? In James M. Edie & Brice R. Wachterhauser (Eds.), Phenomenology and skepticism: Essays in honor of James M. Edie (pp. 1–62, 227–238). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. (Notes).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walther, G. (1955). Phänomenologie der Mystik. Olten und Freiburg im Breisgau: Walter-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Miron, R. (2023). From the “Still Covered” to the “Pure Primordial” Phenomena and Back: The External World in the Phenomenology of Conrad-Martius. In: Hedwig Conrad-Martius. Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-25416-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics