Skip to main content

Lessons from Inferentialism and Invariantism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Priority of Propositions. A Pragmatist Philosophy of Logic

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 475))

  • 167 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I explain what is at issue in the debate on the meaning of the logical constants, exposing some weaknesses of the standard way in which logicians approach this subject. I present and discuss the two families of proposals that have been most successful: invariantism, which derives from (Tarski. History Philos Logic, 7, 143–154, 1986), and inferentialism, which derives from (Gentzen. Am Philosoph Quart 1(4), 288–306 1935/1964) and whose more philosophical aspects have been developed by Dummett, Hacking and Prawitz (Dummett M (1973) Frege. Philosophy of Language. New York, Harper and Row Publishers; Dummett M (1991) The logical basis of metaphysics. Cambridge, MA., Harvard University Press; Hacking. J Philos 76, 285–319 (1979); Prawitz. Synthese 148, 507–524 (2006)). I show that neither of these two approaches gets the set of logical constants right. Both have been accused of overgenerating, i.e. including notions that intuitively are not logical constants, and of undergenerating, i.e. leaving out of the picture some notions that clearly are logical constants. The constraints that their supporters have proposed to make them extensionally adequate point in the direction of taking on board the pragmatic roles that these notions play in communication. The last section of this chapter is devoted to explaining how a pragmatist account helps us to overcome the difficulties that more formalist approaches present, be they purely syntactic or semantically guided.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Belnap, N. (1962). Tonk, plonk and plink. Analysis, 22(6), 130–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, D. (2002). Relevance and linguistic meaning. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, D. (2011). On the descriptive ineffability of expressive meaning. Journal of Pragmatics, 43(14), 3537–3550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonnay, D. (2014). Logical constants, or how to use invariance in order to complete the explication of logical consequence. Philosophy Compass, 9(1), 54–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1984). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1937). Logical syntax of language. The International Library of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Došen, K. (1989). Logical constants as punctuation Marks. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 30(3), 362–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege. New York, Harper and Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2014). The Undergeneration of permutation invariance as a criterion for logicality. Erkenntnis, 79(1), 81–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (1983). The doctrine of logic as form. Linguistic and Philosophy, 6, 319–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (1988). Tarski on truth and logical consequence. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 52(1), 51–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (1990). The concept of logical consequence. Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferferman, S. (1999). Logic, logics, Logicism. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 40(1), 31–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, B. (1990). An approach to discourse markers. Journal of Pragmatics, 4(3), 383–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, a formula language, modeled upon that of arithmetic, for pure thought. In Jean van Heijenoort (1967), from Frege to Gödel. A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931 (pp. 1–82). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1935). Investigation into logical deduction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1(4), 288–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2002). The problem of logical constants. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 8, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2007). Constantes Lógicas. In M. J. Frápolli (Ed.), Filosofía de la Lógica (pp. 179–205). Madrid.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2005). Formal philosophy? A Plea for Pluralism. Five Questions on Formal Philosophy. VIP Press, Vincent Henricks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1979). What is logic? Journal of Philosophy, 76, 285–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Sandu, G. (2007). What is logic? In D. Jaquette (Ed.), Philosophy of logic (pp. 13–39). North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, F. (1872/1893). A comparative review of recent researches in geometry. Bulletin of the New York Mathematical Society, 2(1892–1893), 215–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klima, G. (2006). In K. Brown (Ed.), Syncategoremata. Elsevierʼs Encyclopedia of language and linguistic (Vol. 12, 2nd ed., pp. 353–356). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2015a). Proof-theoretic semantics, a problem with negation and prospects for modality. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(6), 713–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2015b). What is wrong with classical negation? Grazer Philosophische Studien, 92(1), 51–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2019). Proof and falsity: A logical investigation. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf, P. (1996). On the meanings of logical constants and the justifications of the logical laws. Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1(1), 11–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. (2006). Meaning approached via proofs. Synthese, 148, 507–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1960). The roundabout inference-ticket. Analysis, 21, 38–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1970). Philosophy of logic. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1954). Dilemmas. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffrin, D. (1987). Discourse markers. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1991). The bounds of logic. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2003). A characterization of logical constants is possible. Theoria, 18(2), 189–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1936). On the concept of following logically. Translation from the polish and German by Magda Stroiska and David Hitchcock. History and Philosophy of Logic, 23(3), 155–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions? History and Philosophy of Logic, 7, 143–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. A Bradford Book. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Warmbrod, K. (1999). Logical constants. Mind, 108(431), 503–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. In C. K. Ogden (Ed.), Prepared with assistance from G. E. Moore, F. P. Ramsey, Wilhelm Ostwald, and Wittgenstein. Routledge & Kegan Paul. Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung (1st ed., p. 14). Annalen der Naturphilosophie.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to María José Frápolli .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frápolli, M.J. (2023). Lessons from Inferentialism and Invariantism. In: The Priority of Propositions. A Pragmatist Philosophy of Logic. Synthese Library, vol 475. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-25229-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics