Skip to main content

Strategic Voting and Strategic Candidacy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Advances in Collective Decision Making

Part of the book series: Studies in Choice and Welfare ((WELFARE))

  • 203 Accesses

Abstract

Models of strategic candidacy analyze the incentives of candidates to run in an election. Most work on this topic assumes that strategizing only takes place among candidates, whereas voters vote truthfully. In this article, we extend the analysis to also include strategic behavior on the part of the voters. We also study cases where only candidates or only voters are strategic. We consider a setting in which both voters and candidates have single-peaked preferences and the voting rule is majority-consistent, and we analyze the type of strategic behavior that is required in order to guarantee desirable voting outcomes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Manipulating the result of an election by not participating in the voting process is reminiscent of the “no-show paradox” (Fishburn & Brams, 1983; Moulin, 1988), which is concerned with voters’ participation incentives.

  2. 2.

    When the number of voters is even, a Condorcet winner is not guaranteed to exist even if preferences are single-peaked. However, in this case there will always be at least one weak Condorcet winner. The results in Sect. 5 extend to the setting with an even number of voters, with the role of the Condorcet winner taken over by one of the weak Condorcet winners, namely the one in whose favor the tie is broken.

  3. 3.

    For results without this assumption, see, e.g., Dutta et al. (2001, 2002).

  4. 4.

    This assumption is common in the literature on strategic candidacy, where it is often referred to as self-preference (Dutta et al., 2001, 2002) or self-supporting candidate preferences (Lang et al., 2013; Obraztsova et al., 2015, 2020; Polukarov et al., 2015). Without it, scenarios can arise where no candidate has an incentive to run.

  5. 5.

    If \(C(s)=\emptyset \), define \(o_f(s)= \top \). We assume that each candidate prefers herself to the outcome \(\top \). This assumption ensures that at least one candidate will run whenever candidates act strategically.

  6. 6.

    Subgame-perfect equilibria are guaranteed to exist if one allows for mixed strategies and extends the preferences of players to the set of all probability distributions over \(C \cup \{\top \}\) in an appropriate way.

  7. 7.

    If the order is not part of the input, it can be computed in polynomial time (Bartholdi & Trick, 1986; Escoffier et al., 2008).

  8. 8.

    We often simplify examples with single-peaked preference profiles by specifying the peak distribution only. This piece of information is clearly sufficient to identify both the Condorcet winner and, in the absence of ties, the plurality winner.

  9. 9.

    In particular, note that Theorem 1 does not make any assumptions on the preferences of candidates (other than self-supportedness).

  10. 10.

    Sertel and Sanver (2004) prove a similar result in the (standard) setting where all candidates are assumed to run. A further strengthening of part (ii) of Theorem 1 was pointed out to us by François Durand: instead of requiring that voters play a strong V-equilibrium for every subset of running candidates, it is sufficient to require voters to play a strong V-equilibrium only in those subgames that actually allow strong V-equilibria (and to not make any assumptions on voter behavior otherwise).

  11. 11.

    Veto does not only violate majority-consistency, but also the weaker property defined after Theorem 1.

  12. 12.

    Note that the voter v with \({\text {top}}(R_v)=a\) plays a weakly dominated strategy, because c is her least preferred alternative. This can be avoided by introducing a fourth candidate d with \(c \mathrel {\triangleleft } d\) and \(V_R(d)=\emptyset \).

References

  • Bartholdi, J., III., & Trick, M. (1986). Stable matching with preferences derived from a psychological model. Operations Research Letters, 5, 165–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T., & Coate, S. (1997). An economic model of representative democracy. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 85–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56, 23–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brill, M., & Conitzer, V. (2015). Strategic voting and strategic candidacy. In Proceedings of the 29th AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI) (pp. 819–826).

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sinopoli, F. (2000). Sophisticated voting and equilibrium refinements under plurality rule. Social Choice and Welfare, 17, 655–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demange, G. (1982). Single-peaked orders on a tree. Mathematical Social Sciences, 3, 389–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, B. (1981). Individual strategy and manipulation of issues. Mathematical Social Sciences,1, 169–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, B., Jackson, M. O., & Le Breton, M. (2001). Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica, 69, 1013–1037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, B., Jackson, M. O., & Le Breton, M. (2002). Voting by successive elimination and strategic candidacy. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 190–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, B., & Laslier, J.-F. (2010). Costless honesty in voting. Presented at the 10th International Meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, B., & Pattanaik, P.-K. (1978). Strategic manipulation of issues in group decision making. In P.-K. Pattanaik (Ed.), Strategy and group choice (pp. 168–183). North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehlers, L., & Weymark, J. A. (2003). Candidate stability and nonbinary social choice. Economic Theory, 22, 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elkind, E., Lackner, M., & Peters, D. (2017). Structured preferences. In U. Endriss (Ed.), Trends in computational social choice (pp. 187–207). AI Access.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eraslan, H., & McLennan, A. (2004). Strategic candidacy for multivalued voting procedures. Journal of Economic Theory, 117, 29–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Escoffier, B., Lang, B., & Öztürk, M. (2008). Single-peaked consistency and its complexity. In Proceedings of the 18th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence (ECAI) (pp. 366–370).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1977). Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 33, 469–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. J. (1983). Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56, 207–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41, 587–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lang, J., Maudet, N., & Polukarov, M. (2013). New results on equilibria in strategic candidacy. In Proceedings of the 6th International Symposium on Algorithmic Game Theory (SAGT) (pp. 13–25).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mbih, B., Moyouwou, I., & Ndiaye, A. A. (2009). Parliamentary voting rules and strategic candidacy. Economics Bulletin, 29, 1371–1379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meir, R., Polukarov, M., Rosenschein, J. S., & Jennings, N. R. (2010). Convergence to equilibria in plurality voting. In Proceedings of the 24th AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI) (pp. 823–828).

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1980). On strategy-proofness and single peakedness. Public Choice, 35, 437–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1988). Condorcet’s principle implies the no show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 53–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. B., & Weber, R. J. (1993). A theory of voting equilibria. American Political Science Review, 87, 102–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ndiaye, A. A. (2013). Forte stabilité et vainqueur de Condorcet. Revue d’Economie Politique, 123, 793–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Obraztsova, S., Elkind, E., Polukarov, M., & Rabinovich, Z. (2015). Strategic candidacy games with lazy candidates. In Proceedings of the 24th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI) (pp. 610–616).

    Google Scholar 

  • Obraztsova, S., Markakis, E., & Thomson, D. R. M. (2014). Plurality voting with truth-biased agents. In Proceedings of the 6th International Symposium on Algorithmic Game Theory (SAGT) (pp. 26–37).

    Google Scholar 

  • Obraztsova, S., Polukarov, M., Elkind, E., & Grzesiuk, M. (2020). Multiwinner candidacy games. In Proceedings of the 19th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS) (pp. 957–965).

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, M. J., & Slivinski, A. (1996). A model of political competition with citizen-candidates. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 111, 65–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, D., & Lackner, M. (2020). Preferences single-peaked on a circle. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 68, 463–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polukarov, M., Obraztsova, S., Rabinovich, Z., Kruglyi, A., & Jennings, N. R. (2015). Convergence to equilibria in strategic candidacy. In Proceedings of the 24th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI) (pp. 624–630).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, K. W. S. (1977). Voting over income tax schedules. Journal of Public Economics, 8, 329–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodríguez-Álvarez, C. (2006a). Candidate stability and voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 27, 545–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodríguez-Álvarez, C. (2006b). Candidate stability and probabilistic voting procedures. Economic Theory, 27, 657–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samejima, Y. (2005). Strategic candidacy, monotonicity, and strategy-proofness. Economic Letters, 88, 190–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samejima, Y. (2007). Strategic candidacy and single-peakedness. Japanese Economic Review, 58, 423–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10, 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1966). A possibility theorem on majority decisions. Econometrica, 34, 491–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sertel, M. R., & Sanver, M. R. (2004). Strong equilibrium outcomes of voting games are the generalized Condorcet winners. Social Choice and Welfare, 22, 331–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sui, X., Francois-Nienaber, A., & Boutilier, C. (2013). Multi-dimensional single-peaked consistency and its approximations. In Proceedings of the 23rd International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI) (pp. 375–382).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, D. R. M., Lev, O., Leyton-Brown, K., & Rosenschein, J. (2013). Empirical analysis of plurality election equilibria. In Proceedings of the 12th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS) (pp. 391–398).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tideman, T. N. (1987). Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 4, 185–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A previous version of this article has appeared in the Proceedings of the 29th AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (Brill & Conitzer, 2015). We would like to thank John Duggan, François Durand, Alexander Mayer, and the anonymous reviewers for helpful comments. This work was supported by NSF and ARO under grants CCF-1101659, IIS-0953756, CCF-1337215, W911NF-12-1-0550, and W911NF-11-1-0332, by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft under grant BR 4744/2-1, and by a Feodor Lynen research fellowship of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus Brill .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Brill, M., Conitzer, V. (2023). Strategic Voting and Strategic Candidacy. In: Kurz, S., Maaser, N., Mayer, A. (eds) Advances in Collective Decision Making. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-21696-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics