Skip to main content

Egalitarian Collective Decisions as ‘Good’ Corporate Governance?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Advances in Collective Decision Making

Part of the book series: Studies in Choice and Welfare ((WELFARE))

  • 205 Accesses

Abstract

Value-neutral (Robbinsian) economic science cannot directly address substantive normative issues. Economics can, however, provide analytical and empirical methods that make implications and consequences of normative premises (more) transparent and thereby indirectly contribute to normative opinion formation. To this effect, we translate substantive normative premises of stakeholder value approaches into operational axioms that characterize a class of collective decision mechanisms. If such implications seem less attractive to stakeholder theorists than the high-minded values from which they started in criticism of shareholder value approaches, they should come up with alternative collective decision mechanisms or a modified set of values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In a normative welfare economic perspective, they would, to secure Pareto efficiency, also be normatively obliged to follow market signals. This fairly common assumption among economists—apparently including Friedman himself—is, however, not in line with a privilege of ownership that conceptualizes the owner as ‘sovereign’ in disposing of private property within the limits of law: the competitive market may provide extrinsic motives to choose in ways conducive to the attainment of efficiency—as defined in terms of the game form—but the intrinsic motive to act accordingly need not prevail and neither be seen as a morally binding precept to further the common weal.

  2. 2.

    We do not claim to present an interpretation true to what Kant could have meant. We speak of Kantian ideals of equal interpersonal respect in opposition to utilitarian (aggregationist) ideals of the common weal. This is the spirit in which Rawls and also Buchanan are often seen as being part of the Kantian camp of moral philosophy and, say, Harsanyi of the utilitarian.

  3. 3.

    This in turn demands acknowledging a. that prescriptive statements cannot be derived from sets of exclusively descriptive statements and b. that prescriptive statements cannot corroborate or falsify descriptive ones.

  4. 4.

    For the value-neutral conception of technological research in applied science, see (Albert, 1985) and (Albert, 2010, 2022).

  5. 5.

    We use the concept of the game-form as familiar from social choice theoretical debates basically for the objective rules of the game. The Game as an object of common knowledge arises once subjective aspects—subjective preferences and beliefs are factored in. The latter are like the game-form also beyond choices within plays of the Game and in this sense part of the ‘rules of the Game’ along with its game-form.

  6. 6.

    MacIntyre (1984) who provides this apt characterization of a narrow conception of reason is an ardent critic of it.

  7. 7.

    Obviously, even in case of several Pareto improvements, not all need be maximally advantageous to each separate individual so that even then inter-individual conflict concerning which of several improvements should be realized prevails.

  8. 8.

    In Buchanan’s scheme of things, the diagnosis that an alternative is a potential Pareto improvement is a hypothetical that must be corroborated (‘ratified’) by unanimous agreement to bringing it about. Unanimous agreement of the actors themselves rather than the external diagnosis of Pareto inferiority is the legitimation.

  9. 9.

    Substantive restrictions to Pareto improvements on the diagnostic level and to unanimity requirements on the level of mechanisms may as a matter of fact be desired by particular persons. Yet, according to value-neutrality as a constitutive methodological norm of Robbinsian economics, the theorist has a reason to (re-)search exclusively such suggestions if those requiring her advice as a matter of fact demand to receive exclusively advice concerning Pareto superior moves.

  10. 10.

    Which party will prevail is ultimately a matter of the ability to get ones way rather than a matter of argument. Of course, the fact that economic counsel concerning instruments may or may not be private information to the counseled party is relevant here, too. To avoid this, economists routinely assume that information is common knowledge—or at least subject to a process of dissemination that will approach common knowledge.

  11. 11.

    As in the medical case, in case of management, partisanship rather than impartiality is the basis of the trust relationship between counselor and client.

  12. 12.

    So-called consumer sovereignty is just one example of this sovereignty in matters that are by constitutional politics put beyond in period politics.

  13. 13.

    Böhm (1966), an influential German constitutional lawyer, uses this expression to characterize markets as a subsystem of the economic order of a free western society. Like other members of the so-called ordo liberal Freiburg School, he strongly sympathized with the values of the Mont Pelerin society among whose ‘noble’ members were besides its founder F. A. v. Hayek, scholars like G. Becker, J. M. Buchanan, M. Friedman, V. Smith.

  14. 14.

    By assumption, the relevant specification of law is assumed to comply with ‘the three fundamental rules of justice’ which rule such a positive law obligation out, likewise, by assumption the value-neutral practice of science leaves no room for justifying moral responsibilities as conclusions of science.

  15. 15.

    A more detailed presentation of this argument can be found in Kliemt (2022).

  16. 16.

    Article 2 of Bentham (1843).

  17. 17.

    Even if we would assume that there is objective knowledge of what is ethically right and/or wrong this would as such still not explain the existence of rights as parts of legal and/or moral institutions. As it stands, Freeman’s list of stakeholders is no more than a personal wish list.

  18. 18.

    For more on this strand of ‘normative economics’, see Brennan and Kliemt (2019) and Kliemt (2011).

  19. 19.

    That participation in interactions in regular markets can be operationalized in implementable ways is, to put it mildly, not the least advantage of this social ‘technology’. But it is ruled out in the group participation framework endorsed by Freeman.

  20. 20.

    See (Buchanan (1999), vol. 1), passim and for further discussion of some specific aspects (Brennan and Kliemt, 2018).

  21. 21.

    Only in case of commonly known \(v_1 (m)+\cdots {}+v_n (m)=S(m)\) underbidding incentives would not exist.

  22. 22.

    The so-called “hold out problem”, that this gives rise to, probably motivates many scholars to reject the unanimity requirement. It should not be neglected, though, that some stakeholders i with \(v_i (m)<0\) for some \(m\in {}M\) may get compensated when moderately underbidding in terms of \(b_i (m)<v_i (m)\). In that case, m may still be acceptable and possibly implemented by management. In any event, the interest of guaranteeing that \(m\in {}M_a\) applies will recommend to exercise some moderation in strategic underbidding.

  23. 23.

    This neglects bidding by which one bids for m also in order to prevent the implementation of another plan \(\tilde{m}\ne {}m\). In such cases, under-, respectively, overbidding incentives can depend on the expected bids after plan \(\tilde{m}\) for which property (O) may not be true.

  24. 24.

    It can be shown that some such mechanisms can be fully characterized by requiring that they be “envy-free” and meeting requirement (E) with respect to overt bids; see Güth (2011).

  25. 25.

    Using, for instance, the revelation principle would require the highly restrictive common knowledge assumption of game theoretic equilibrium analysis.

  26. 26.

    This point has been rightly emphasized by adherents of stakeholder conceptions from the start. It can be supported by many findings of psychology and experimental economics. Starting from Hume’s well-known remark “that, in contriving any system of government, and fixing the several checks and controls of the constitution, every man ought to be supposed a knave and to have no other end, in all his actions, than private interest”. (Hume 1777, Essay VI, 42). Bowles (2016) provides an excellent overview over relevant experimental results concerning the validity of the behavioral assumptions underlying mechanism design in relation to ‘moral motives’.

  27. 27.

    In an explorative experimental study (Alberti et al., 2022) that implemented “stakeholder participation as egalitarian bidding”, bounded bid shading and even some systematic overbidding could in fact be observed. It seems that some stakeholders did not want to block a plan that might be ‘good for the firm’ even though affecting themselves negatively. Obviously more research concerning effects of fairness perceptions and intrinsic motivation based on procedurally fair bidding is necessary before stronger evidence-based claims can be made.

  28. 28.

    In the spirit of Alchian (1950).

References

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on critical reason. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, M. (2010). Critical rationalism and scientific competition. Analyse and Kritik, 32, 247–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, M. (2022). How to escape from model platonism in economics: Critical assumptions, robust conclusions, and approximate explanations. Homo Oeconomicus, forthcoming

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberti, F., Güth, W., & Tsutsui, K. (2022). Experimental effects of institutionalizing co-determination by a procedurally fair bidding rule. Journal of Business Ethics, forthcoming

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchian, A. A. (1950). Uncertainty, evolution, and economic theory. Journal of Political Economy, 58, 211–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1843). Anarchical fallacies. In J. Bowring (Ed.), The works of Jeremy Bentham (Vol. 2, pp. 489–534). William Tait

    Google Scholar 

  • Böhm, F. (1966). Privatrechtsgesellschaft und Marktwirtschaft. ORDO: Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 17, 75–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. (2016). The moral economy: Why good incentives are no substitute for good citizens. Yale University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Kliemt, H. (2018). The constitution of markets. In R. E. Wagner (Ed.), James M. Buchanan: A theorist of political economy and social philosophy (pp. 807–838). Palgrave Macmillan

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Kliemt, H. (2019). Kantianism and political institutions. In R. D. Congleton, B. Grofman, & S. Voigt (Eds.), Oxford handbook of public choice (pp. 796–813). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1979). Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications. In G. Brennan, H. Kliemt, & R. D. Tollison (Eds.), The collected works of James M. Buchanan (1999, Vol. 1, The logical foundations of constitutional liberty, pp. 45–59). Liberty Fund

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999). The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. In G. Brennan, H. Kliemt, & R. D. Tollison (Eds.), The collected works of James M. Buchanan (1999). Liberty Fund

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (1984). Stakeholder theory of the modern corporation. In W. M. Hoffman, R. E. Frederick, & M. S. Schwartz (Eds.), Business ethics: Readings and cases in corporate morality (pp. 184–191). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1984). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. In W. M. Hoffman, R. E. Frederick, & M. S. Schwartz (Eds.), Business ethics: Readings and cases in corporate morality (pp. 180–183). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Güth, W. (2011). Rules (of bidding) to generate equal stated profits: an axiomatic approach. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 167, 608–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature (2nd edition 1978). Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1777). Essays IV and XII. In E. F. Miller (Ed.), Essays: Moral, political, literary (1985, based on the 1777 ed., pp. 32-36 and 87–96). Liberty Fund

    Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (2011). Bukantianism—Buchanan’s philosophical economics. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 80, 275–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (2022). What should moral managers do? Management Revue, forthcoming

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. C. (1932). The nature and significance of economic science. Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. C. (1938). Interpersonal comparisons of utility: A comment. Economic Journal, 48, 635–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vining, D. R. (1956). Economics in the United States of America: A review and interpretation of research. UNESCO

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federica Alberti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Alberti, F., Güth, W., Kliemt, H., Tsutsui, K. (2023). Egalitarian Collective Decisions as ‘Good’ Corporate Governance?. In: Kurz, S., Maaser, N., Mayer, A. (eds) Advances in Collective Decision Making. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-21696-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics