Skip to main content

Miracles and the Uniformity of Nature

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Miracles: An Exercise in Comparative Philosophy of Religion

Part of the book series: Comparative Philosophy of Religion ((COPR,volume 3))

  • 229 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter looks critically at the prevailing modern understanding of miracle, adapted from David Hume, where a miracle is a transgression by the Deity of a law of nature. I suggest that this stock understanding informs the widespread secular naturalism of our day, where the metaphysical concept of laws of nature becomes, in effect, the benchmark of reality. I question the utility of this view for establishing a meaningful view of nature and of the natural sciences, and look again at David Hume’s philosophy of induction. This leads me to highlight the ‘uniformity of nature’ as a more flexible concept by which to unify the sciences and to define miracle. I use the example of contemporary earth science to discuss how uniformity has informed scientific practice and scientific unity, and I suggest some ways in which the concept of miracle is both transformed and is transformative in this view.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Clark (2016, p. 1), for instance, warns, “It is impossible to offer a single precise definition of ‘naturalism.’” Nevertheless, Clark’s ensuing discussion makes it clear that, while there are many kinds of naturalism, they tend to be characterized by a distancing of religious categories such as “supernatural” alongside an embracing of the natural sciences as providing the most secure path to knowledge. Similarly, Flanagan (2006, pp. 430–431) offers 15 meanings of the term “naturalism,” all of which appear to exclude the supernatural (either explicitly or implicitly) and to take a positive stance towards scientific forms of enquiry. And as a final example, Slagle (2016, pp. 31–33) cites the common threads of “any type of naturalism or physicalism or materialism,” all of which work to place the modern natural sciences and their methods at the forefront of our description of reality.

  2. 2.

    For instance, Taliaferro and Evans (2011, p. 4) contest naturalism on the grounds that all of its various forms either assume or assert that theism is false.

  3. 3.

    Fodor’s (1974) ironic use of the “disunity of science as a working hypothesis” as a challenge to the dominant Oppenheim and Putnam view is an early example of resistance to reductionism as the unifier of the sciences, although Fodor still wanted to retain a looser sense of unity for the sciences. Dupré’s is probably the best-known voice advocating a fully pluralist approach to the sciences. Other solutions exist, such as those that make a unifying virtue out of pluralism (e.g. Breitenbach & Choi, 2017). A useful review of the area is provided by Cat (2017).

  4. 4.

    Section X, “Of Miracles,” in Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, first published 1748.

  5. 5.

    And when I refer to “Enquiry,” I mean the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding.

  6. 6.

    The interpretation of Hume’s thought on causation has become a complex and controverted area in modern philosophy, but since I am concerned especially with miracle the issues are somewhat simplified by being able to focus on Enquiry alone. This allows me to adopt the “skeptical realist” reading of Hume here (Beebee, 2012, pp. 143–144).

  7. 7.

    And indeed, in his discussion of miracles, Hume uses the terms “uniform experience” and the “common course of nature” in parallel to his use of the laws of nature. All three kinds of term operate as yardsticks of our common experience, for Hume to stand against miracle (Enquiry X.12).

  8. 8.

    It is important to note that the modern earth sciences are a very diverse set of subjects, some of which (e.g., mineral physics) are more like typical laboratory-based sciences. Overall though, the classic core areas of geology, such as petrology, stratigraphy, and palaeontology, are overwhelmingly focused on interpreting evidence of the past, usually gathered in the field, even if analyzed in a laboratory afterwards.

  9. 9.

    The main point is that the Grand Canyon exposes most of the last 2 billion years of North American geological history almost perfectly; it provides one of the earth’s most complete geological columns.

  10. 10.

    This controversy was an important precursor to the Darwin debates of the second half of the nineteenth century, and, like the Darwin debates, is also susceptible to being represented (inaccurately) as an example of the conflict of science versus religion (Bowler, 1984, pp. 103–104).

  11. 11.

    Many historians are important here, but the magisterial overviews of Martin Rudwick are particularly notable (Rudwick, 2005, 2008, 2014).

  12. 12.

    The main contender at present incorporates very large-scale volcanic eruptions into the scenario, eruptions that are known to have occurred at the time in India’s Deccan Traps (Keller et al., 2009).

  13. 13.

    It is, for instance, now widely accepted that much of the earth’s geological history is episodic and evolutionary, rather than smooth and cyclical (as Lyell’s original brand of uniformitarianism would have it).

  14. 14.

    Note that this is much the same point as that made by the multiverse riposte to theistic interpretations of fine tuning. The gist here is that when there are many, many universes we do not need to call upon a Creator to explain fine tuning since one of the universes is bound to turn out right for life, even with the tiny probabilities involved. Geology is considerably more secure than cosmology though: the multiverse is (currently) an untestable hypothesis, whereas the immensity of geological time is one of the most secure empirical facts in the whole of science.

  15. 15.

    While some commentators have concluded that these models “explain away” the miraculousness of the story, others argue that they confirm the historicity of the story and heighten its sense of miracle. Whether a miracle is to be acknowledged or not depends on many more factors—some of them subjective—than whether the event is deemed “impossible” in naturalistic terms or not. This last point is explored in the next section.

References

  • Ager, D. V. (1993a [1973]). The nature of the stratigraphical record. John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ager, D. (1993b). The new catastrophism: The importance of the rare event in geological history. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, L. W., Alvarez, W., Asaro, F., & Michel, H. V. (1980). Extraterrestrial cause for the cretaceous-tertiary extinction. Science, 208, 1095–1108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2012). Causation and necessary connection. In A. Bailey & D. O’Brien (Eds.), The continuum companion to Hume (pp. 131–145). Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1984). Evolution: The history of an idea. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breitenbach, A., & Choi, Y. (2017). Pluralism and the unity of science. The Monist, 100, 391–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2017). The unity of science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/scientific-unity/. Accessed 2020, May 15.

  • Clark, K. J. (2016). Naturalism and its discontents. In K. J. Clark (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to naturalism (pp. 1–15). Wiley Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2011). Philosophical issues in natural history and its historiography. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 44–62). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (2004). Introduction: The nature of naturalism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 1–17). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2004). The miracle of monism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 36–58). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2006). Varieties of naturalism. In P. Clayton & Z. Simpson (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of religion and science (pp. 430–452). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frodeman, R. (2000). Preface. In Earth matters: The earth sciences, philosophy, and the claims of community (pp. vii–xiii). Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1965). Is uniformitarianism necessary? American Journal of Science, 263, 223–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregersen, N. H. (2014). Naturalism in the mirror of religion: Three theological options. Philosophy, Theology and the Sciences, 1, 99–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gretener, P. E. (1967). Significance of the rare event in geology. American Association of Petroleum Geologists Bulletin, 51, 2197–2206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gretener, P. E. (1984). Reflection on the “rare event” and related concepts in geology. In W. A. Berggren & J. A. Van Couvering (Eds.), Catastrophes and earth history: The new uniformitarianism (pp. 77–89). Princeton University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hallam, T. (2004). Catastrophes and lesser calamities: The causes of mass extinctions. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, M. J. (2007). How did Moses part the Red Sea? Science as salvation in the Exodus Ttadition. In A. Graupner & M. Wolter (Eds.), Moses in biblical and extra-biblical traditions (pp. 5–31). de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooykaas, R. (1959). Natural law and divine miracle: A historical-critical study of the principle of uniformity in geology, biology and theology. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsü, K. J. (1989). Catastrophic extinctions and the inevitability of the improbable. Journal of the Geological Society, 146, 749–754.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2007 [1748]). In P. Millican (Ed.), An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inkpen, R. (2011). The philosophy of geology. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 318–329). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffares, B. (2008). Testing times: Regularities in the historical sciences. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39, 469–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, G., Sahni, A., & Bajpai, S. (2009). Deccan volcanism, the KT extinction and dinosaurs. Journal of Biosciences, 34, 709–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosso, P. (2011). Philosophy of historiography. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 9–25). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmer, R. (2011). Miracles, divine agency, and the laws of nature. Toronto Journal of Theology, 27, 267–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, A. E. (2006 [2002]). A scientific theology. Vol. 1: Nature. T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2007). Introduction. In D. Hume (Ed.), An enquiry concerning human understanding (pp. ix–lvi). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2011). Twenty questions about Hume’s “Of Miracles”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 68, 151–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). Unity of science as a working hypothesis. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 2, 3–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, M. J. S. (2005). Bursting the limits of time: The reconstruction of geohistory in the age of revolution. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, M. J. S. (2008). Worlds before Adam: The reconstruction of geohistory in the age of reform. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, M. J. S. (2014). Earth’s deep history: How it was discovered and why it matters. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G. G. (1975). Uniformitarianism. An inquiry into principle, theory, and method in geohistory and biohistory. In C. C. Albritton (Ed.), Philosophy of geohistory: 1785–1970 (pp. 256–309). Dowden, Hutchinson & Ross.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slagle, J. (2016). The epistemological skyhook: Determinism, naturalism, and self defeat. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2004). The charm of naturalism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 21–35). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taliaferro, C., & Evans, J. (2011). Introduction. In C. Taliaferro & J. Evans (Eds.), Turning images in philosophy, science, and religion: A new book of nature (pp. 1–4). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2013). Historical geology: Methodology and metaphysics. In V. R. Baker (Ed.), Rethinking the fabric of geology: Geological Society of America Special Paper 502 (pp. 11–18). Geological Society of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, K. (2002). Believing in miracles. Zygon, 37, 741–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Harris .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Harris, M. (2022). Miracles and the Uniformity of Nature. In: Zwier, K.R., Weddle, D.L., Knepper, T.D. (eds) Miracles: An Exercise in Comparative Philosophy of Religion. Comparative Philosophy of Religion, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-14865-1_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics