Skip to main content

Non-interventionist Objective Divine Action and Quantum Mechanics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Miracles: An Exercise in Comparative Philosophy of Religion

Part of the book series: Comparative Philosophy of Religion ((COPR,volume 3))

Abstract

Miracle accounts are found in most—if not all—religions, providing a promising topic for a scholarly comparison of religions. My focus is the concept of divine action in Christian theology, in which the idea of miracles is one of the many forms of how Christians such as me think about the diversity of God’s action in creating and redeeming the world. The credibility of miracles was seriously challenged by the rise of the natural sciences and Enlightenment philosophy. This led to a profound split between conservative and liberal Christian theologies in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Conservatives accept miracles as objective events in nature, even if they conflict with science, while liberals seek harmony with science, even if it reduces miracles to subjective interpretations of ordinary natural processes. In this paper I will explore a new approach to divine action based on contemporary quantum mechanics. This approach overcomes the split between conservatives and liberals on divine action. It includes the conservative commitment to viewing miracles as objective events in nature and the liberal commitment to harmony with science. I call this “non-interventionist objective divine action” (NIODA). It depicts God acting objectively in nature to affect the flow of natural processes but in a way that is consistent with the theories of natural science. In this paper I will lay out the arguments in favor of QM-NIODA and respond to a number of important challenges that require further reflection.

This paper arose out of my lecture for “The Comparison Project,” a program in comparative philosophy of religion at Drake University directed by Timothy Knepper. The 2017–2019 series, organized and facilitated by Karen Zwier and David Weddle, explored the theme of miracles from the perspective of different religious traditions and sciences. A previous version of this paper was published in Russell 2018 (which I thank Fortress Press for permission to reuse). The present version is highly edited and includes extensive new material. I thank Karen Zwier and David Weddle for their extensive editorial comments on the previous version of this paper, which have been invaluable to me, and for which I am very grateful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “A portent (miracle), therefore, happens not contrary to nature, but contrary to what we know as nature” (Augustine, 1887 [426], book XX1, ch. 8).

  2. 2.

    For an interpretation of Aquinas by a leading, contemporary, Dominican scholar, see Dodds, 2012, p. 247–258 (especially p. 253).

  3. 3.

    Schleiermacher actually gives an extensive and nuanced discussion of miracles in The Christian Faith in which their dependence on God and the whole of nature is clearly construed (Schleiermacher, 1986, pp. 170, 178–184).

  4. 4.

    Timothy McGrew describes four types of criticism: why should Hume’s definition be privileged over earlier ones, what kind of “natural laws” are being assumed, do such laws actually exist, and what does their violation mean.

  5. 5.

    As Pannenberg writes: “The proleptic character of the Christ event … [signifies that] the resurrection of Jesus is indeed infallibly the dawning of the end of history … the onset of the end had occurred only in a preliminary way, happening in Jesus himself … for the rest of us, the resurrection of the dead, which already happened to Jesus, is still outstanding” (Pannenberg, 1970–1971, vol. 2, p. 24). See also Ted Peters: With the term prolepsis, “the gospel is understood as announcing the preactualization of the future consummation of all things in Jesus Christ…. As prolepsis, he [Jesus Christ] embodies the promise because he anticipates in his person the new life that we humans and all creation are destined to share” (Peters, 2015, p. 608).

  6. 6.

    Dilley’s essay was highly formative for me in the years preceding the Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences / Vatican Observatory series on “scientific perspectives on divine action,” in which I was to create my response “QM-NIODA.”

  7. 7.

    In her analysis of these theologians (on pages 68–74) Murphy is careful to stress the complexity of their views and the fact that they do not fit neatly into a rigid conservative/liberal typology. Nevertheless a typology such as this is useful to give an overview of the problem and its prevalence in modern theology—and in the church communities.

  8. 8.

    Murphy also offers a way forward using the theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, the philosophy of science of Imre Lakatos, and post-foundationalist epistemologies. See Murphy, 1990. Also see Murphy’s contributions to the Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences / Vatican Observatory series on “scientific perspectives on divine action”

  9. 9.

    As I discussed above, I fully believe God can also act in truly miraculous ways, but that is not the subject of this chapter. Still my use of both NIODA and miracles can raise some very important “push-back” questions that I must eventually address. For example, as Karen Zwier wrote in a very helpful comment to an earlier draft of this paper: “If a person (such as you) believes in both ‘truly miraculous’ action and NIODA, how do we know which way God is acting for which types of events. Is there some theory about this? For biblical miracles, are we to understand them as ‘truly miraculous’ (i.e. interventionist) or are they instances of NIODA? What about contemporary Christian claims to miracles, such as healings? What about answered prayers? What kinds of events fall into either category? And why do we need two categories at all?” My short response to these excellent questions is that the term miracles was used in the tradition to refer to especially important and revelatory events of divine action without an adequate stress on their eschatological context, leaving unclarified the distinction between the context of eschatology and the context of creation that most contemporary theologians make. I develop this in terms of miracles as the proleptic domain of the new creation within the context of the current creation. I intend to write more fully on this distinction in the future.

  10. 10.

    Technically Ψ is a complex variable (typically Ψ = x + iy, where x and y are real variables, i = √ (− 1), and its “square” is Ψ*Ψ (where Ψ* = x – iy). Thus Ψ*Ψ = x2 + y2.

  11. 11.

    This move is typically called “inference to the best explanation.” See Douven, 2011.

  12. 12.

    For a readable and reliable discussion of eight interpretations of QM, see Herbert, 1985. For a brief discussion, see Polkinghorne, 2011. For a more technical discussion, see Russell, 1988).

  13. 13.

    Such a possibility is explored in detail in Russell & Moritz, 2018.

  14. 14.

    See Russell, 2001, 2008.

  15. 15.

    A simple example is a Stern-Gerlach apparatus. See http://www.quantumphysicslady.org/glossary/stern-gerlach-device/. Last visited on May 6, 2021.

  16. 16.

    Of course in any finite sample such as this, the actual results can vary from the expected, 50/50 result. This complicates the meaning of “counterfactual” but in ways that would take us too far afield for this short chapter.

  17. 17.

    In 2008 Wesley J. Wildman offered a similar analysis of the aspects of a quantum event and the possibilities for divine action they represent but without reference to Wegter-McNelly’s publication (Wildman, 2008, pp. 158–159; see especially fig. 3, option #1 [“God could initiate measurement events”], and option #3 [“God could select an outcome state”].

  18. 18.

    I am grateful for private conversations with Wegter-McNelly about this point.

  19. 19.

    As Karen Zwier pointed out (private communications) there are plenty of theoretical physicists who do not subscribe to PSR. That is precisely why Copenhagen is the mainstream view. While this is a very important point, it does not mean that no theoretical physicists subscribe to PSR. In fact, William Stoeger, S. J., whom I refer to in later in this paragraph, did subscribe to it and therefore expected that a new non-local hidden variable theory would eventually be found to replace current QM (private communications).

  20. 20.

    Private communications.

  21. 21.

    For example, see Russell, 2012.

  22. 22.

    For details about QM-NIODA, see a longer exposition in Russell, 2001. For an earlier detailed discussion, see Russell, 1988.

  23. 23.

    There is an ongoing debate about the extent to which quantum events are amplified to produce specific effects in the macroscopic world, e.g., Jeffrey Koperski’s work, which I discuss in the next section (13.6).

  24. 24.

    See “Schrödinger’s cat” on p. 332 of the Glossary in Russell, Clayton, Wegter-McNelly, and Polkinghorne, 2011.

  25. 25.

    On “what Nobel physicist Robert Laughlin refers to as ‘protectorates,’” see Laughlin & Pines, 2000, p. 29 (as references in n.9 of Koperski, 2015).

  26. 26.

    According to Koperski, “quantum determination does work as a mechanism for theistic evolution. If that’s all one wants from quantum mechanical randomness, I have no objection. There is, however, a large gap between a mechanism-for-theistic-evolution on one hand and a robust-model-of-divine-action on the other” (Koperski, 2015, p. 381).

  27. 27.

    Before closing this discussion, I would like to return briefly to Koperski’s challenge to the amplification issue and offer a clarifying terminological distinction. I will refer to the kind of amplification about which Koperski cautions as “immediate,” “sudden,” or “vertical” amplification (think again of the example of the eye registering a single photon) and distinguish it from what I call “temporally long-range” or “lateral” amplification (think of the evolution of species on earth over billions of years). Returning to the theological significance of all this, the instances of special providence resulting from vertical amplification might be limited, as Koperski suggests, but this limitation does not seem to apply to special providence resulting from lateral amplification from genetics/molecular biology to macro evolution/speciation as discussed by theistic evolution and as pertaining to the 3.8-billion-year history of the evolution of life on earth.

  28. 28.

    However, in the gospel of Mark a miracle can occur regardless of whether those who witness it already have faith in Jesus. Jesus often commands his disciples to keep his divinity a secret (i.e., the “Messianic Secret”).

  29. 29.

    See Peacocke, 1999.

  30. 30.

    John Polkinghorne discusses a scenario similar to this in Polkinghorne, 1994, pp. 25–26, 77.

  31. 31.

    Let me close this section by stressing that QM-NIODA—indeed, any serious theory of divine action—leads to the challenge of theodicy: the existence of moral and natural evil in the world in which God acts. There simply is no room to explore this challenge here, but many of us in theology and science have written on it in the past, and I for one intend to continue to pursue it in the future. As the reader might guess, my approach is to turn to eschatology to provide a theological framework in which the challenge of theodicy can be adjudicated. See for example, the essays in Murphy et al., 2007, as well as Russell, 2008.

  32. 32.

    I make this point in a variety of publications. See for example, Russell, 1998, 2008.

References

  • Aquinas, T. (1975 [1265]). Summa contra gentiles, book 3: Providence. Trans. V.J. Bourke. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1887 [426]). City of god. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, first series, vol. 2. Trans. Marcus Dods. Ed. Philip Schaff. http://www.newadvent.org/fathers/120121.htm. Accessed 2014, September 3.

  • Clayton, P. (1997). God and contemporary science. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dilley, F. B. (1965). Does the “god who acts” really act? The Anglical Theological Review, 47, 66–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodds, M. J. (2012). Unlocking divine action: Contemporary science and Thomas Aquinas. The Catholic University of America Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/. Accessed 2016, April 25.

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2018). Necessity, purpose, and chance: The role of randomness and indeterminism in nature from complex macroscopic systems to relativistic cosmology. In R. J. Russell & J. M. Moritz (Eds.), God’s providence and randomness in nature: Scientific and theological perspectives (pp. 21–67). Templeton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, N. (1985). Quantum reality: Beyond the new physics. Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2000 [1748]). In T. L. Beauchamp (Ed.), An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kärkkäinen, V.-M. (2015). Creation and humanity: A constructive Christian theology for a pluralistic world (Vol. 3). Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koperski, J. (2015). Divine action and the quantum amplification problem. Theology and Science, 13(4), 379–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laughlin, R. B., & Pines, D. (2000). The theory of everything. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 97(1), 28–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, T. (2010). Miracles. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/miracles/. Accessed 2016, July 19.

  • Murphy, N. (1990). Theology in an age of scientific reasoning. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, N. (1993). Evidence of design in the fine-tuning of the universe. In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy, & C. J. Isham (Eds.), Quantum cosmology and the laws of nature: Scientific perspectives on divine action (pp. 407–436). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, N. (1996). Beyond liberalism & fundamentalism: How modern and postmodern philosophy set the theological agenda. Trinity Press International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, N., Russell, R. J., & Stoeger, W. R. (Eds.). (2007). Physics and cosmology; scientific perspectives on the problem of natural evil. Vatican City State.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pannenberg, W. (1970–1971). Basic questions in theology (2 Vols). Trans. George H. Kehm. Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, A. (1983). Theology for a scientific age: Being and becoming—Natural, divine, and human. Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, A. (1999). The sound of sheer silence: How does god communicate with humanity? In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy, T. C. Meyering, & M. A. Arbib (Eds.), Neuroscience and the person: Scientific perspectives on divine action (pp. 215–247). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, A. (2007). In P. Clayton (Ed.), All that is: A naturalistic faith for the twenty-first century. Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, T. (2015). God—The world’s future: Systematic theology for a new era (3rd ed.). Fortress Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, J. (1989). Science and providence: God’s interaction with the world. Shambhala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, J. (1994). The faith of a physicist: Reflections of a bottom-up thinker. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, J. (2011). Physical process, quantum events, and divine agency. In R. J. Russell, P. Clayton, K. Wegter-McNelly, & J. Polkinghorne (Eds.), Quantum mechanics: Scientific perspectives on divine action (pp. 181–190). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. R. (1988). Quantum physics in philosophical and theological perspective. In R. J. Russell, W. R. Stoeger, & G. V. Coyne (Eds.), Physics, philosophy, and theology: A common quest for understanding (pp. 343–374). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. R. (1998). Special providence and genetic mutation: A new defense of theistic evolution. In R. J. Russell, W. R. Stoeger, & F. J. Ayala (Eds.), Evolutionary and molecular biology: Scientific perspectives on divine action (pp. 191–223). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, R. J. (2001). Divine action and quantum mechanics: A fresh assessment. In R. J. Russell, P. Clayton, K. Wegter-McNelly, & J. Polkinghorne (Eds.), Quantum mechanics: Scientific perspectives on divine action (pp. 293–328). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, R. J. (2008). Cosmology from alpha to omega: The creative mutual interaction of theology and science. Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, R. J. (2012). Time in eternity: Pannenberg, physics, and eschatology in creative mutual interaction. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. R. (2018). What we’ve learned from quantum mechanics about noninterventionist objective divine action in nature—and its remaining challenges. In R. J. Russell & J. M. Moritz (Eds.), God’s providence and randomness in nature: Scientific and theological perspectives (pp. 133–171). Templeton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, R. J., & Moritz, J. M. (Eds.). (2018). God’s providence and randomness in nature: Scientific and theological perspectives. Templeton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schleiermacher, F. (1958 [1799]). On religion: Speeches to its cultured despisers. Trans. John Oman. Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schleiermacher, F. (1986 [1830–1831]). In H. R. Mackintosh & J. S. Stewart (Eds.), The Christian faith. T & T. Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegter-McNelly, K. (2006). Atoms may be small, but they’re everywhere: Robert Russell’s theological engagement with the quantum revolution. In T. Peters & N. Hallanger (Eds.), God’s action in nature’s world: Essays in honour of Robert John Russell (pp. 93–111). Ashgate Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wildman, W. J. (2008). The divine action project, 1988–2003. In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy, & W. R. Stoeger (Eds.), Scientific perspectives on divine action: Twenty years of challenge and progress (pp. 133–176). Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, N. T. (2008). Surprised by hope: Rethinking heaven, the resurrection, and the mission of the church. HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwier, K. R. (2022). Miracles in philosophical analysis. In K. R. Zwier, D. Weddle, & T. D. Knepper (Eds.), Miracles: An exercise in comparative philosophy of religion, 12. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert John Russell .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Russell, R.J. (2022). Non-interventionist Objective Divine Action and Quantum Mechanics. In: Zwier, K.R., Weddle, D.L., Knepper, T.D. (eds) Miracles: An Exercise in Comparative Philosophy of Religion. Comparative Philosophy of Religion, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-14865-1_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics