Skip to main content

Queer Legal Theory

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Feminist Approaches to Law

Part of the book series: Gender Perspectives in Law ((GPL,volume 1))

Abstract

The article explores the understanding of the notion, concept and method of queer legal theory. In other words, what do we mean by “queer legal theory”? If we are to understand it as a theory and practice of liberation and struggle for the rights of LGBT people, it can be subsumed under the general theory of human rights, prohibition of discrimination, equality, and freedom. We can also understand it through different variations of critical legal studies. Understood in this way, queer legal theory is viewed through the prism of “outsider” jurisprudence and has tremendous critical potential. In this sense, the article aims to explore the methodological perspectives for a legal theory which tries to position law “outside” of the traditional streams of legal positivism. That is, the different levels of content and concepts of “queer” and queer legal theory, its methodology, approach, comprehension, as well as understanding of identity. Finally, the aim is to present one’s own reflection on the possible understanding of and interrelationships within the broadly understood field of queer legal theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    More on this: Butler (1994), p. 21.

  2. 2.

    Jagose (1996), pp. 1–2.

  3. 3.

    See also: Unger (1983), Kennedy (2017), Klare (2001) and Gordon (1982/1990).

  4. 4.

    Delgado (1993), p. 743.

  5. 5.

    Legal Information Institute (n.d.).

  6. 6.

    Delgado (1993), p. 744; Unger (1983); Kennedy (2017); Gordon (1982/1990).

  7. 7.

    Legal principles and legal doctrine can be vague in two directions. First, legal rules immanently contain internal gaps, conflicts and uncertainties, whether they are “difficult” or “simple” legal cases. Also, conflict exists in legal principles that support legal norms and are the basis of their interpretation.

  8. 8.

    See more: Delgado (1993), p. 744.

  9. 9.

    Delgado (1993), p. 744.

  10. 10.

    Delgado (1993), p. 745. Narrative scholarship includes chronicles, parables, counter stories and accounts of the writer’s personal experience (Delgado 1993, p. 751). As Delgado continues, narrative works often advance no argument, offer no balanced assessment of different models or approaches to a legal question, and typically aim not at changing doctrine but changing mindset (Delgado 1993, p. 751). Scholars are writing about story-telling in law, employing or analysing “voices” and narratives putting women, race or queer in the centre and treating law as stories and trial as theatre (Delgado 1993, p. 759).

  11. 11.

    The realists were deeply sceptical of the ascendent notion that judicial legislation is rarity. While not entirely rejecting the idea that judges can be constrained by rules (constitution, statutes, bylaws, etc.), the realists argued that judges create new law through the exercise of law-making discretion more often than is commonly supposed. In their view, judicial decision is frequently more guided by political, moral and ideological intuitions about the facts of the case than theorists of legal positivism and natural legal theories are willing to acknowledge.

  12. 12.

    Himma (n.d.).

  13. 13.

    Himma (n.d.).

  14. 14.

    Himma (n.d.).

  15. 15.

    Altman (1986).

  16. 16.

    Himma (n.d.).

  17. 17.

    Himma (n.d.).

  18. 18.

    Dworkin (1986).

  19. 19.

    Altman (1986), p. 189; Corlett (2000), pp. 43–44; Culver (2001). While the realists stress competing rules, the CLSers stress competing, and indeed irreconcilable, principles and ideals. (Altman 1986, p. 189).

  20. 20.

    Altman (1986), p. 191; Corlett (2000), pp. 43–46.

  21. 21.

    Altman (1986), p. 191.

  22. 22.

    Altman (1986), p. 192.

  23. 23.

    Černič (2022).

  24. 24.

    Altman (1986), p. 192.

  25. 25.

    Altman (1986), p. 192.

  26. 26.

    The CLS analyses have demonstrated the deep and pervasive incoherence of doctrine in areas such as constitutional law, labour law, contract law, administrative law, criminal law, etc. (Altman 1986, p. 193). Moreover, as the CLS’s argumentation develops “(…) the authoritative legal materials, in replicating the ideological conflicts of the political arena, contain a sufficient number of doctrines, rules and arguments representing any politically significant ideology that a judge who conscientiously consults the material would find his favoured ideology in some substantial portion of the settled law and conclude that it was the soundest theory of law” (Altman 1986, p. 196).

  27. 27.

    Altman (1986), p. 193.

  28. 28.

    Himma (n.d.).

  29. 29.

    Himma (n.d.).

  30. 30.

    Himma (n.d.).

  31. 31.

    Himma (n.d.).

  32. 32.

    Fineman (2009), p. 2.

  33. 33.

    Fineman (2009), p. 2.

  34. 34.

    Many scholars are concerned with the dismantling of the existing social and legal norms, as well as structures with a goal to reach equality (Fineman 2009, p. 2).

  35. 35.

    Fineman (2009), p. 2.

  36. 36.

    Fineman (2009), p. 2.

  37. 37.

    Delgado (1993), p. 741.

  38. 38.

    Valdes (2009), p. 91.

  39. 39.

    Valdes (2009), p. 91.

  40. 40.

    Delgado (1993), p. 741.

  41. 41.

    Delgado (1993), pp. 741–742.

  42. 42.

    Delgado (1993), p. 742.

  43. 43.

    Delgado (1993), p. 742.

  44. 44.

    Delgado (1993), p. 742; Valdes (2009), pp. 89–90.

  45. 45.

    Valdes (2009), pp. 89–90.

  46. 46.

    Ball (2001), p. 271.

  47. 47.

    Ball (2001), p. 271.

  48. 48.

    Ball (2001), p. 272.

  49. 49.

    Ball (2001), p. 272.

  50. 50.

    Ball (2001), p. 272.

  51. 51.

    Ball (2001), p. 272.

  52. 52.

    Fineman (2009), p. 5.

  53. 53.

    Fineman (2009), p. 5.

  54. 54.

    Fineman (2009), p. 5.

  55. 55.

    Fineman (2009), p. 5; Valdes (2009), p. 92.

  56. 56.

    Fineman (2009), pp. 5–6; Valdes (2009), p. 92; Ball (2001), pp. 272–274.

  57. 57.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  58. 58.

    Valdes (2009), p. 95.

  59. 59.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  60. 60.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  61. 61.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  62. 62.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  63. 63.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  64. 64.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  65. 65.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  66. 66.

    Halley (2009), p. 14.

  67. 67.

    In its contemporary understanding, “queer” has been usually associated with prideful opposition to and transgression of sexual, gender, intimacy and kinship norms (Romero 2009, p. 190). Queer is a relational concept: one thing is queer in relation to something else which is usually dominant (Romero 2009, p. 190).

  68. 68.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6; Ball (2001), pp. 271–282.

  69. 69.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  70. 70.

    Halley (2009), p. 15.

  71. 71.

    Halley (2009), p. 15.

  72. 72.

    Ball (2001), p. 273.

  73. 73.

    Romero (2009), pp. 190–191.

  74. 74.

    Ball (2001), p. 273.

  75. 75.

    Queer theorists emphasise the historical contingency and the incoherence of social constructions, such as polarisation, compartmentalisation and categorisation of men from women, male from female, masculinity from femininity, heterosexual from homosexual etc. (Romero 2009, p. 190).

  76. 76.

    Ball (2001), p. 273.

  77. 77.

    Romero (2009), p. 190.

  78. 78.

    Halley (2009), p. 15.

  79. 79.

    Halley (2009), p. 15.

  80. 80.

    Valdes (2009), p. 92.

  81. 81.

    Valdes (2009), p. 92.

  82. 82.

    Valdes (2009), p. 92.

  83. 83.

    Valdes (2009), p. 93.

  84. 84.

    Valdes (2009), p. 94.

  85. 85.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  86. 86.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  87. 87.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  88. 88.

    Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  89. 89.

    Kepros (1999–2000), pp. 282–283.

  90. 90.

    Kepros (1999–2000), p. 283.

  91. 91.

    Kepros (1999–2000), p. 283.

  92. 92.

    Kepros (1999–2000), p. 283.

  93. 93.

    Romero (2009), p. 190.

  94. 94.

    Kepros (1999–2000), p. 284; Fineman (2009), p. 6.

  95. 95.

    Romero (2009), p. 190.

  96. 96.

    Romero (2009), p. 190.

  97. 97.

    Romero (2009), p. 190.

  98. 98.

    Romero (2009), p. 191.

  99. 99.

    Romero (2009), p. 191.

  100. 100.

    Romero (2009), p. 191.

  101. 101.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  102. 102.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  103. 103.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  104. 104.

    Ball (2001), p. 274.

  105. 105.

    Ball (2001), p. 282.

  106. 106.

    Ball (2001), p. 282.

  107. 107.

    Ball (2001), p. 286.

  108. 108.

    Ball (2001), pp. 286–288.

  109. 109.

    Ball (2001), p. 290.

  110. 110.

    Ball (2001), p. 291.

  111. 111.

    Banović (2021), p. 47.

  112. 112.

    Banović (2021), p. 48.

  113. 113.

    Banović (2021), p. 48.

  114. 114.

    Banović (2021), p. 48.

  115. 115.

    Banović (2021), p. 48.

  116. 116.

    Banović (2021), p. 48.

  117. 117.

    Ball (2001), p. 274.

  118. 118.

    Ball (2001), p. 274.

  119. 119.

    Ball (2001), p. 274.

  120. 120.

    Valdes (1995), p. 344.

  121. 121.

    Valdes (1995), p. 349.

  122. 122.

    Valdes (1995), p. 353.

  123. 123.

    Valdes (1995), p. 354.

  124. 124.

    Valdes (1995), pp. 355–356.

  125. 125.

    Valdes (1995), p. 357.

  126. 126.

    Valdes (1995), pp. 362–372; Romero (2009), pp. 191–192.

  127. 127.

    Romero (2009), p. 192.

  128. 128.

    Romero (2009), p. 192.

  129. 129.

    Romero (2009), p. 192.

  130. 130.

    Romero (2009), p. 193.

  131. 131.

    Romero (2009), p. 193.

  132. 132.

    Halley (2009), p. 26.

  133. 133.

    Halley (2009), p. 26.

  134. 134.

    Halley (2009), p. 197.

  135. 135.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  136. 136.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  137. 137.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

  138. 138.

    Legal theory (n.d.).

References

  • Altman A (1986) Legal realism, critical legal studies, and Dworkin. http://fs2.american.edu/dfagel/www/Class%20Readings/ALCReadings/Altman%20Legal%20Realism.pdf

  • Ball CA (2001) Essentialism and universalism in gay rights philosophy: liberalism meets queer theory. Law Soc Inq 26(1):271–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banović D (2021) Philosophical and legal foundations for LGBT rights. In: Mathis K, Langensand L (eds) Dignity, diversity, anarchy. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 29–51. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozailphilosophie – Beihefte Band 168

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler J (1994) Against proper objects. Differences J Fem Cult Stud 6(2-3):1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Černič LJ (2022) Protection of human dignity, plural democracy and minority rights in the case of the Constitutional Court of Slovenia. In: Krešić M et al (eds) Ethnic diversity, plural democracy and human dignity. Challenges to the European Union and Western Balkans. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett JA (2000) Dworkin’s empire strikes back. Statute Law Rev 21(1):43–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culver K (2001) Leaving the Hart-Dworkin debate. Univ Tor Law J 51(4):367–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delgado R (1993) The inward turn in outsider jurisprudence. William Mary Law Rev 34:741–768. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr/vol34/iss3/6

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s Empire. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman AM (2009) Introduction: feminist and queer legal theory. In: Fineman MA, Jackson JE, Romero AP (eds) Feminist and queer legal theory: intimate encounters, uncomfortable conversations. Routledge. https://ssrn.com/abstract=1516647

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon RW (1982/1990) New developments in legal theory. In: Kairys D (ed) The politics of law. Pantheon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Halley J (2009) Queer theory by men. In: Fineman MA, Jackson JE, Romero AP (eds) Feminist and queer legal theory: intimate encounters, uncomfortable conversations. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma KE (n.d.) Philosophy of law. The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/law-phil/#H3

  • Jagose RA (1996) Queer theory. An introduction. Melbourne University Press, Melbourne

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (2017) Intersectionality and critical race theory: a genealogical note from a CLS point of view. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3014312. Accessed 25 Jan 2022

  • Kepros LR (1999–2000) Queer theory: weed or seed in the garden of legal theory. Law Sex Rev Lesbian Gay Bisexual Transgender Leg Issues 9:279–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Klare K (2001) The politics of Duncan Kennedy’s critique. Cardozo Law Rev 22(3-4):1073–1104

    Google Scholar 

  • Legal Information Institute (n.d.) Critical legal theory. https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/critical_legal_theory

  • Legal theory: critical theory: Queer law (n.d.). https://cyber.harvard.edu/bridge/CriticalTheory/critical5.htm

  • Romero AP (2009) Methodological descriptions: Feminist and Queer legal theories. In: Fineman MA, Jackson JE, Romero AP (eds) Feminist and queer legal theory: intimate encounters, uncomfortable conversations. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger RM (1983) The critical legal studies movement. Harv Law Rev 96(3):561–675

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valdes F (1995) Afterword &(and) prologue: queer legal theory. Calif Law Rev 83:344–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Valdes F (2009) Queering sexual orientation: a call for theory as praxis. In: Fineman MA, Jackson JE, Romero AP (eds) Feminist and queer legal theory: intimate encounters, uncomfortable conversations. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Damir Banović .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Banović, D. (2023). Queer Legal Theory. In: Vujadinović, D., Álvarez del Cuvillo, A., Strand, S. (eds) Feminist Approaches to Law. Gender Perspectives in Law, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-14781-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-14781-4_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-14780-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-14781-4

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics