Skip to main content

Legal Defeasibility: The Limits Between Ductile Law and Arbitrary Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Crisis of the Criminal Law in the Democratic Constitutional State
  • 146 Accesses

Abstract

The claim that legal rules are defeasible means that, according to our legal practices, it may be justified for judges to set aside applicable rules in resolving disputes and to take other considerations into account in their place. In line with this approach, this paper seeks to clarify the types of cases and the conditions in which, according to our established conventions, it is acceptable for judges to deviate from what is commanded in legal rules. Specifically, three different cases of defeasibility are differentiated in the paper: D1 (defeasibility at the level of prescriptions contained in the formulation of rules); D2 (defeasibility at the level of underlying justifications of rules), and D3 (radical defeasibility, relative to the hierarchy of legal reasons). Finally, the paper addresses the question of whether we can regard as legal the alternative considerations to which judges must appeal when they consider that they should set aside prima facie applicable rules. The paper concludes by pointing out that the key to drawing the boundaries between ductile law and arbitrary law lies in the affirmative answer to this last question.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As a starting point for this theoretical approach to the problem of defeasibility I am going to take the manifestations of defeasibility in our legal practice. Therefore, I will not follow the logical approaches inspired by Alchourrón and Bulygin’s conceptual apparatus (Alchourrón and Bulygin 1971; Alchourrón 2010, pp. 77–127, 141–153 and 155–177).  In the wake of this kind of logical approach to the problem of legal defeasibility, see The Logic of Legal Requeriments (Ferrer and Ratti 2012).

  2. 2.

    Article 368 of the current Criminal Code.

  3. 3.

    “Starting from the doctrinal distinction between ‘apparent realization’ and ‘effective realization’ of the criminal conduct of the norm, the Supreme Court introduces the political-criminal principle of ‘exclusive protection of legally protected value’. Thus, the Court refuses to subsume in the generic case of the rule cases in which the conduct of the active subject has not put at risk the value underlying the rule, although this conduct is grammatically perfectly subsumable in the generic case of the norm” (Silva Sánchez 1997, p. 315).

  4. 4.

    For example, cases of entry through an open window located on the ground floor (STS of April 20, 1999), or “at street level” (STS of January 18, 1999), or “when there is no evidence of a special height concerning the ground floor or of a special way in which the defendant has managed to get onto the windowsill that reveals the special ability or effort inherent to climbing” (STS of March 10, 2000).

  5. 5.

    The aforementioned rule referred to “crimes regarding toxic drugs, narcotic drugs or psychotropic substances, that the Criminal Code punishes.”

  6. 6.

    “The domicile is inviolable. No entry or registration may be made in it without the consent of the owner or judicial resolution, except in the case of flagrante delicto.”

  7. 7.

    Atienza and Ruiz Manero have maintained that this characterization of rules as protected reasons is applicable only to one type of rules: mandatory rules, but not to other types of legal statements such as principles—which constitute mere first-order reasons—or power conferring rules—which would be auxiliary reasons (Atienza and Ruiz Manero 2007).

  8. 8.

    Thus, according to Silva Sánchez, “there is an increasingly clear tendency in precedents towards overcoming legalistic positivism, which conceives the application of Law as a merely logical operation, as pure subsumption that applies a syllogism. The requirement in art. 5.1 of the Organic Law of Judicial Power, regarding the ‘interpretation of legal norms in accordance with the Constitution’ may have contributed to some extent to this positivistic tendency. However, it seems to be evident that judges and courts … are aware of the need to adopt a certain evaluative perspective when they proceed to interpret positive law, in such a way that the process of applying law can be correctly characterized as a process of obtaining law. In the case of our Supreme Court, it seems that this evaluative perspective acquires significant teleological features, in such a way that the interpretation of rules is subject to material political-criminal purposes of criminal law, leading to a guarantee-based application of the law” (Silva Sánchez 1997, p. 314).

  9. 9.

    According to Raz, it is possible to distinguish between “reasoning to establishing the content of Law” and “reasoning according to Law.” In the first case, the interpreter makes a reasoning based solely on the sources of law and, therefore, autonomous. But it is possible that the result of such reasoning is the granting of discretion to judges to depart from what the law establishes if relevant moral reasons are given for it. If this were the case, the second type of reasoning, reasoning according to law, would enter the scene and the judge would have the discretion to deviate from the legal guidelines identified according to the sources’ thesis and apply moral reasons (Raz 1994, p. 310).

  10. 10.

    As will be seen shortly, I am going to characterize D1 as defeasibility at the level of prescriptions contained in the formulation of rules, D2 as defeasibility at the level of the justifications underlying rules, and finally, D3 as radical defeasibility or defeasibility of reason provided by law.

  11. 11.

    These legal standards include legal practices that remit to dominant semantic conventions and to interpretative conventions.

  12. 12.

    Or more precisely, some defeasible rules in the third sense of defeasibility or D3.

  13. 13.

    Juan Ruiz Manero has worked on a type of conflict that can illustrate this type of situation in Ruiz Manero (2018), pp. 30 ss.

  14. 14.

    Law of June 18, 1870, modified by Law 1/1988, of January 14 in Articles: 2, 3, 10, 11, 15, 20, 22, 23, 24, 26, 28, 29 and 30.

  15. 15.

    This is how pardon is characterized by the Supreme Court: “pardon is an act with features of atypicality within the framework of the constitutional rule of law… because it involves a certain rejection of the principle of generality of criminal law and of those of independence and exclusivity of the jurisdiction” (ATS of January 18, 2001, Appeal 2940/1997).

  16. 16.

    Article 11 Pardon Law.

  17. 17.

    Ground 8.

  18. 18.

    Ground 8.

  19. 19.

    The expression “ductility of Law” is inspired by the title of the renowned book in the continental legal culture by Gustavo Zagrebelsky El Derecho dúctil. Ley, derechos, justicia (Zagrebelsky 2003).

References

  • Alchourrón C (2010) Fundamentos para una teoría general de los deberes. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón C, Bulygin E (1971) Normative systems. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M, Ruiz Manero J (2007) Las piezas del Derecho. Teoría de los enunciados jurídicos. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayón JC (2000) Derrotabilidad, indeterminación del Derecho y positivismo jurídico. Isonomía 13:87–117

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1995) Positivismo y Derecho. In: La crisis del derecho y sus alternativas. Consejo General del Poder Judicial, Madrid, pp 73–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández TR (2005) Del arbitrio y de la arbitrariedad judicial. Iustel, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrer J, Ratti J (eds) (2012) The logic of legal requirements. Oxford University Press, Oxford, Essays on defeasibility

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1990) Practical reason and norms. Princeton University Press, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1994) On the autonomy of legal reasoning. In: Ethics in the public domain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ródenas A (1998) Entre la transparencia y la opacidad: análisis del papel de las reglas en el razonamiento judicial Doxa. N. 21, vol 1:99–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Ródenas A (2001) En la penumbra: indeterminación, derrotabilidad y aplicación judicial de normas, Doxa. Cuadernos de filosofía del Derecho 24:63–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ródenas A (2012) Los intersticios del Derecho. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Ródenas A (2017) La investigación en Filosofía del Derecho. Lineamientos metodológicos para la investigación jurídica 3:1–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz Manero J (2018) Rule of Law y ponderación. In: Juan Pablo Alonso (coord) Imperio de la ley y ponderación de principios. Astrea, Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1991) Playing by the rules: a philosophical examination of rule-based decision-making in law and in life. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Silva Sánchez JM (1997) Nuevas tendencias político-criminales y actividad jurisprudencial del Tribunal Supremo. In: Romeo Casabona CM (ed) Dogmática Penal, Política Criminal y Criminología en evolución. Centro de Estudios Criminológicos-Universidad de La Laguna, La Laguna

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagrebelsky G (2003) El Derecho dúctil. Ley, derechos, justicia. Trotta, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ródenas, Á. (2023). Legal Defeasibility: The Limits Between Ductile Law and Arbitrary Law. In: Demetrio Crespo, E., García Figueroa, A., Marcilla Córdoba, G. (eds) Crisis of the Criminal Law in the Democratic Constitutional State. Legal Studies in International, European and Comparative Criminal Law, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-13412-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-13413-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics