Skip to main content

Criminal Law and Legal Theory: Not Just Legal Dogmatics, but Never Without It

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Crisis of the Criminal Law in the Democratic Constitutional State

Abstract

This paper reviews some of the common discussions and criticisms regarding criminal-law dogmatics, some of which are considered less important than their historical weight makes them seem (for example, the debate about their scientific nature) and others are valid in the face of an incorrect practice of dogmatics or, better, in the face of “bad” dogmatics (such as the criticism of the prevalence of the system over the law). A correctly developed dogmatics is claimed, without any pretensions of absolute objectivity, with the positive law as limit and reference, away from an exercise of “art for art’s sake.” A dogmatics that is not isolated from other knowledge nor above them, not hermetic, with respect for the Constitution and fundamental rights and, most especially, focused on the solution of real problems. This kind of solution often does not arise simply from the wording or the language of the positive law. Certain misuses of dogmatics in jurisprudence are reported and the advantages of its correct use for jurisprudence are highlighted. In short, dogmatics is claimed as an important guarantee (not a panacea), with others, of the citizen in avoiding arbitrariness and, therefore, as a limit to punitive power.

This paper belongs to the research projects DER2016-76715-R and PID2019-108567RB-C21 (AEI), as well as to the research tasks of the UIC 166 of Castilla and León. The references related to the topic addressed are endless, so we do not claim to be exhaustive in the citation. In many of the works cited above, there are abundant further references.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Von Kirchmann (1848), especially his well-known sentence “Three corrective words from the legislator and whole libraries become waste paper” (p. 23).

  2. 2.

    It is enough to cite the quotation already made by v. Kirchmann (1848) in Germany; in Spain, to cite only one author and in a work (among many others in which he denies the scientificity of dogmatics) dedicated to the thought of v. Kirchmann, Vives Antón (2017), pp. 233 et seq. with further references.

  3. 3.

    It is important to underline that the school of Vives Antón is integrated by relevant criminal lawyers with serious works (most of whom I have an excellent relationship with), who in my opinion often do dogmatics. For this reason, my mention to its representatives here should in no way be taken as disqualifications, but rather, on the contrary, as opinions to continue the debate. It would be impossible here to mention all the works in which Vives and his followers express criticisms and objections to dogmatics or to the way in which criminal lawyers do it. In some of the following sections, I will especially cite one of the works by Cuerda Arnau (2017) in which further references to others can be found. In any case, I wish to state here for the record that some works by this author [e.g., the most recent (2019), pp. 11 et seq., with very interesting application of her theses to specific problems] in which she insists on the criticisms and on the need (which I fully agree with) not to make dogmatics beyond the law, actually show that our positions are not so far apart and that a “good” dogmatics does not have to incur in the deficiencies that she reports (although it is not possible to demonstrate this here in detail, later on I will offer some example of coincidence). These criticisms are based on Vives Antón’s view of meaningful action (see. the work in which he develops it in a general way: Vives Antón 2011). Vives’ disciples have applied this conception of their teacher to the most diverse subjects in books and works [just to mention one among many, in which quite a few of them have recently written: González Cussac (coord.) (2019)], in many of whom at least misgivings towards dogmatics can be noticed, probably with the exception of Martínez-Buján Pérez, an important developer of Vives Antón’s conception, but admitting the need for dogmatics (based on law), as he acknowledges, I believe, in the foreword to the very interesting book by Martínez-Buján Pérez (2019), foreword in which Vives once again criticizes dogmatics or the way of doing dogmatics and the pretension of its scientificity (pp. 13 et seq.), but he concludes by stating: “In the work of Carlos Martínez-Buján, all these requirements are combined with a special insight to analyze the concepts and a deep knowledge of the existing jurisprudence and dogmatics, so that the reader will find in it a dogmatics that has renounced its complexes and the pretensions of infallibility that arise from them, offering simply, an authentic lesson of Law” (pp. 14 et seq.).

  4. 4.

    For many, summarized in this sense Vives Antón (2017), p. 233.

  5. 5.

    Gimbernat Ordeig (1970), pp. 379 et seq. [1990, pp. 140 et seq.].

  6. 6.

    Nino (1984), p. 103.

  7. 7.

    Atienza (2015), pp. 169 et seq., 189 et seq.

  8. 8.

    And I would even say, although this requires further verification, that some of the criticisms of criminal-law dogmatics [e.g., those of Vives Antón or his disciple Cuerda Arnau, in Spain; see. only Vives Antón (2011), p. 578; Cuerda Arnau (2017), p. 494] are influenced by the use of dogmatics made by a very definite current, that of ultra-normativism of Jakobsian tradition, which here it is not possible to evaluate, but which, in my opinion, differs to a large extent from what dogmatics and its most refined source, the theory of offense, should be, by dissolving the categories of this into others of allocation that are much more vague, general and even manipulable. In this sense, with clarity, among others, Demetrio Crespo (2010), p. 15: “In this way Jakobs has been deconstructing the systematic structure of the theory of offense at its very foundations through the formalism of the categories and the use of vague and imprecise concepts that lack the capacity of subsumption.”

  9. 9.

    Nino (1980), p. 14.

  10. 10.

    Schünemann (2011), p. 447. This author, by the way, continues to vindicate the value of dogmatics and its service to the democratic rule of law. He has done so in multiple works and, recently, citing all of them and many more and in the face of critical positions such as especially those of Vogel (2012), pp. 25 et seq. or Ambos (2016), pp. 177 et seq., in Schünemann (2016), pp. 654 et seq. In these recent works Schünemann has argued that in a liberal constitutional state, criminal-law dogmatics is vital as a “fourth power” against totalitarian pretensions of criminal policy and has even introduced a new paradigm in the global science of criminal law: the paradigm of the analytical-philosophicus mos civitatis iuris, abbreviated as “mapci.”

  11. 11.

    Schünemann (2011), p. 447.

  12. 12.

    Alexy (1991), pp. 326 et seq. [(1997), pp. 255 et seq.]

  13. 13.

    Roxin (2006), § 7 paragraph. 1 (pp. 194 et seq.) [1997, § 7 paragraph. 1, p. 192]. Igual Roxin and Greco (2020), § 7 paragraph. 1 (p. 288).

  14. 14.

    Schünemann (2011), p. 448.

  15. 15.

    Kindhäuser (2009), pp. 963 et seq.

  16. 16.

    Gimbernat Ordeig very clearly states (1970), p. 405 [(1990), p. 158].

  17. 17.

    Cuerda Arnau (2017), p. 485.

  18. 18.

    I cannot discuss this idea here, which would require many aspects, but I would like to express that I do not reject the appeal to principles, but I notice that some references to them together with the idea of weighting hide personal preferences, far removed from the law and the Constitution itself.

  19. 19.

    Cuerda Arnau (2017), pp. 486 et seq.

  20. 20.

    Luzón Peña (2016), Cap. 3 paragraph 2 (p. 29).

  21. 21.

    I personally wrote many years ago: “(…) the evaluations that I believe to be most important are those that can be extracted from the law, trying to make them compatible with those that seem more correct from the point of view of material justice, of political-criminal needs, but always within the maximum limit of the letter of the law itself, of the principle of legality” [Díaz y García Conlledo (1991), p. 35].

  22. 22.

    Roxin (2006), § 7 paragraphs. 1, 3 (pp. 194, 195) [1997, § 7 paragraphs. 1, 2 (pp. 192, 193)]; Roxin and Greco (2020), § 7 paragraphs. 1, 3 (pp. 288, 289).

  23. 23.

    Emphasis added.

  24. 24.

    Very clearly and with multiple references, by many, Silva Sánchez (2004), especially pp. 680 et seq.

  25. 25.

    Geertz (1973), p. 30 [(2003), p. 39].

  26. 26.

    Stated by him in its general lines almost half a century ago: Roxin (1973).

  27. 27.

    It is not possible here, unfortunately, to expose and reply to the relevant critical remarks of a specialist such as Díez Ripollés (2021), passim, on Roxin’s way of understanding criminal policy (for him incorrect), whose influence would have had negative consequences for true criminal policy. It is enough to say here, provisionally and as far as this paper is concerned, that even if the German author were to extend, as Díez Ripollés argues, incorrectly the term criminal policy to all evaluation content used in criminal law, this would not contradict the idea that I hold in the text that dogmatic construction does not need to be “pure” and ignore evaluations. We cannot either evaluate here the important reflections that the mentioned author makes in the aforementioned work, pp. 14 et seq., under the heading “The fagocitate (or absorption) of criminal policy by the dogmatics of liability,” which aims to demonstrate the dogmatic excesses (including “going beyond the legal interpretation” or “highlighting a criminal law in force according to a certain concession of society not necessarily coinciding with that of the legislator”), but, I understand, he does not discuss the need for it (in its, for him, fair terms) either.

  28. 28.

    Interesting and with very extensive subsequent references are the recent considerations regarding the “encounters and misunderstandings” of criminal dogmatics and legal sociology offered by Gómez Martín (2019), pp. 165 et seq. Also, recently Miró Llinares (2020), pp. 279 et seq., avoiding the “old and unfruitful debate on the scientific nature of criminal-law dogmatics” (pp. 279 et seq.), extensively argues the need to open criminal law and dogmatics to other fields of knowledge and the risks of “isolationism.”

  29. 29.

    See only, for example, the considerations in this regard of Latin American criminal lawyers such as Sotomayor Acosta (2008), pp. 148 et seq., 164; Zaffaroni (2017), pp. 245 et seq.; Arias Holguín (2018), pp. 49 et seq.; Moreno Hernández (2018), pp. 82 et seq., 371 et seq., 392 et seq., entre otras; (2020), pp. 311 et seq.

  30. 30.

    In the sense stated, for example, by Silva Sánchez (2004), pp. 679 et seq. It is not possible to explain or discuss here, however, the relationship of “universalization” with the criminal-law categories regarding the importance of the a priori categories that would shape criminal-law knowledge (different from those of other branches of law, which would work in the same way in their field), categories that would not operate based on the positive norm, as García Amado (2020), particularly explains pp. 156 et seq.

  31. 31.

    See regarding the importance of fundamental rights and their relationship with dogmatics, warning of certain “postmodern” risks, recently, Moccia (2020), pp. 289 et seq. In a critical work on different aspects of dogmatics (or its approach to certain problems), Parma (2020) arrives at a conclusion that is (to a large extent) comparable and that points to the importance of human rights [even for a “good” non-hermetic dogmatist, of course! Criminal law must move away from the arcane labyrinths of scholars, avoid the excessive pseudo-university artillery, the promiscuity of populist policies and renounce the media oracles that condemn without trial. It must offer solutions, hold on to the humanization of conflict, aspire to freedom equalizations” (p. 333)].

  32. 32.

    It is enough to recall, among others, the reflections of Schünemann in his work referred to above at the end of n. 10.

  33. 33.

    And it is very true that dogmatists, hiding behind the shield of their “science,” of its “purity” or forgetting central aspects of it (contradicting themselves), have come to do much worse things than not criticizing non-democratic regimes. See only, with further references, the recent reflections of García Amado (2020), especially pp. 158 et seq.

  34. 34.

    He critically warns about the conditions under which the theory of offense (remember: the most refined product of dogmatics) “could be linked in the same way to a conservative, progressive, liberal, social, fascist or communist system” Figueiredo Dias (2019), p. 155.

  35. 35.

    Which also refers Greco (2008), pp. 180 et seq.

  36. 36.

    An example (among many possible ones by other authors) of my dogmatic treatment of these issues is given in Díaz y García Conlledo (1999), pp. 335 et seq.

  37. 37.

    It is not possible to develop here the evident connection of this with the impossibility of automatic subsumption in the law by judges, today widely recognized. I will refer, just as a recent example, to the interesting work of Sánchez-Ostiz Gutiérrez (2019), pp. 325 et seq., warning, however, that I do not necessarily agree with all of his proposals (pp. 336 et seq.).

  38. 38.

    In fact, our Penal Code (unlike others) does not even contain a definition of willful intent (and its classes) and recklessness (and I believe, by the way, that it does well).

  39. 39.

    Among them, of course and inexcusably, those that derive from the positive law itself, such as the fact that, in this case, intentional homicide (even with dolus eventualis) is punished much more harshly than reckless or negligent homicide.

  40. 40.

    Again, as a mere example of dogmatic treatment, this time not mine, of this issue: Luzón Peña (2016), Cap. 16 paragraphs. 54 et seq. (pp. 234 et seq.).

  41. 41.

    A new example of our own treatment can be found in Díaz y García Conlledo (2002), especially pp. 656 et seq.

  42. 42.

    Cuerda Arnau (2017), p. 489. In the following, I do not dispute this author’s assertion that case law is in fact becoming less and less predictable, but that this is due to (correct) dogmatics.

  43. 43.

    Schünemann (2011), pp. 445 et seq.

  44. 44.

    Schünemann (2011), p. 460.

  45. 45.

    See Pantaleón Díaz (2018), p. 105. Different data on judicial statistics (not only criminal) can be obtained in “Justicia Dato a Dato,” an annual publication offered by the General Council of the Judiciary: https://www.poderjudicial.es/cgpj/es/Temas/Estadistica-Judicial/Estudios-e-Informes/Justicia-Dato-a-Dato/. The latest available (2019), contains multiple statistical data, but it is sufficient to refer, for the criminal jurisdiction, to the indicators summary on p. 116.

  46. 46.

    Illustrative, even in his title, and from the hand of a sadly famous case in Spain, the work of Pantaleón Díaz (2018), pp. 103 et seq.

  47. 47.

    Roxin (2015), pp. 242 et seq., 736 et seq.

  48. 48.

    Roxin (2015), pp. 275 et seq.

  49. 49.

    Regarding it, with further references, Díaz y García Conlledo (1991), pp. 349 et seq.

  50. 50.

    See Díaz y García Conlledo (2017), pp. 518 et seq., (2011), 274 et seq.

  51. 51.

    Cuerda Arnau (2019), p. 16.

References

  • Alexy R (1991) Theorie der juristischen Argumentation. Die Theorie des rationalen Diskurses als Theorie der juristischen Begründung, Nachwort. Antwort auf einige Kritiker, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main [(1997) Teoría de la argumentación jurídica. La teoría del discurso racional como teoría de la fundamentación jurídica, trad. Atienza M/Espejo I, Centro de Estudios Constitucionales, Madrid]

    Google Scholar 

  • Ambos K (2016) Zur Zukunft der deutschen Strafrechtwissenschaft: Offenheit und und diskursive Methodik statt selbsbewusster Provinzialität. GA, pp 177–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Arias Holguín DP (2018) Contexto, interdisciplinariedad y dogmática penal en EH-Terradillos. Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia, pp 49–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M (2015) La dogmática jurídica como tecno-praxis, en EH-Carpizo T. IV vol 1 Estado Constitucional, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México. Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas, pp 169–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Consejo General del Poder Judicial (2019) La Justicia Dato a Dato. Año 2019. Estadística Judicial, 2019 (https://www.poderjudicial.es/stfls/ESTADISTICA/FICHEROS/JusticaDatoaDato/Datos%20Anteriores/Justicia%20Dato%20a%20Dato%202019.pdf) (diversos años en https://www.poderjudicial.es/cgpj/es/Temas/Estadistica-Judicial/Estudios-e-Informes/Justicia-Dato-a-Dato/)

  • Cuerda Arnau ML (2017) La función de la dogmática (Una crítica desde la concepción significativa de la acción), en EH-Mir, B de F, Montevideo/Buenos Aires, pp 485–495

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuerda Arnau ML (2019) La concepción significativa de la acción v. las pretensiones sistemáticas, en Vives Antón, T S (Cuerda Arnau M L, compiladora) Pensar la libertad. Últimas reflexiones sobre el Derecho y la Justicia, Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia, pp 11–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Demetrio Crespo E (2010) Crítica al normativismo funcionalista. RDPCrim, 3ª época, 3, pp 13–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz y García Conlledo M (1991) La autoría en Derecho penal. PPU, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz y García Conlledo M (1999) El error de prohibición: pasado, presente y futuro, en LH-Torío, Comares, Granada, 1999, pp 335–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz y García Conlledo M (2002) ¿Es necesaria la cooperación necesaria?, en LH-Cerezo, Comares, Granada, 2002, pp 645–669

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz y García Conlledo M (2011) Der Einfluss der Roxinschen Taterschaftstheorie (insbesondere bretreffend die Mittateschaft) auf die spanische Rechtslehre und Rechtsprechung: kritische Betrachtungen. GA, pp 259–283 [(2011) La influencia de la teoría de la autoría (en especial de la coautoría) de Roxin en la doctrina y la jurisprudencia españolas. Consideraciones críticas. NFP (Colombia) 76, pp 15–48]

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz y García Conlledo M (2017) Actuación en el marco de un aparato organizado de poder: ¿autoría o participación?, en EH-Mir, pp 509–521 [(2017) Das Handeln im Rahmen eines organisatorischen Machtapparates: Täterschaft oder Teilnahme? GA, pp 711–719)

    Google Scholar 

  • Díez Ripollés JL (2021) La política criminal en las ciencias penales: un análisis crítico de la contribución de Roxin. Revista Electrónica de Ciencia Penal y Criminología (RECPC) 23-02:1–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Figueiredo Dias J (2019) Sobre la crisis del paradigma penal, en LH-Jorge vol 1, Universidad Autónoma de Madrid. Servicio de Publicaciones, Madrid, pp 147–163

    Google Scholar 

  • García Amado JA (2020) Neokantismo y derecho penal. Sobre el papel y el sentido de la dogmática penal y sobre el papel de los penalistas, en LH-Luzón vol I, Reus, Madrid, pp 153–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz C (1973) The interpretation of cultures. Selected essays. Basic Books, New York, 1973 [(2003) La interpretación de las culturas, trad. Bixio A L, 12ª reimpr., Gedisa, Barcelona]

    Google Scholar 

  • Gimbernat Ordeig E (1970) Hat die Strafrechtsdogmatik eine Zukunft? ZStW 28:379–410 [(1990) ¿Tiene un futuro la dogmática jurídico-penal?, en: Estudios de Derecho Penal, 3ª ed., 1990, pp 140–161]

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez Martín V (2019) Dogmática penal y Sociología jurídica: encuentros y desencuentros, en LH-Jorge Barreiro vol 1, Universidad Autónoma de Madrid. Servicio de Publicaciones, Madrid, pp 165–180 [(2018) Diritto Penale Contemporaneo 2/2018: pp 149–161]

    Google Scholar 

  • González Cussac JL (coord.) (2019) Lenguaje y dogmática penal. Actas del II Congreso Ibero-Americano de Derecho Penal y Filosofía del Lenguaje, Tiranto lo Blanch, Valencia

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco L (2008) Dos formas de hacer dogmática jurídico-penal. Revista Discusiones 8:177–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kindhäuser U (2009) Die deutsche Strafrechtsdogmatik zwischen Anpassung und Selbstbehauptung. Grenzkontrolle der Kriminalpolitik durch die Dogmatik? ZStW 121:954–964

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchmann JH (1848) Die Werthlosigkeit der Jurisprudenz als Wissenschaft. Ein Vortrag gehalten in der juristischen Gesellschaft zu Berlin, Julius Springer, Berlin [(1961) La jurisprudencia no es ciencia, trad. y escrito preliminar de Truyol y Serra A, 2ª ed. con una nota adicional, Instituto de Estudios Políticos (Colección Civitas), Madrid –reimpr. 1963- (existen otras ediciones)]

    Google Scholar 

  • Luzón Peña D-M (2016) Lecciones de Derecho Penal. Parte General, 3ª ed., Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínez-Buján Pérez C (2019) La autoría en Derecho penal. Un estudio a la luz de la concepción significativa de la acción. Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia

    Google Scholar 

  • Miró Llinares F (2020) Cientismo, dogmatismo y Derecho penal, en LH-Luzón, vol I. Reus, Madrid, pp 279–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Moccia S (2020) El rol de la dogmática penal ante la transformación de la política criminal, en LH-Luzón, vol I. Reus, Madrid, pp 289–300

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno Hernández M (2018) Dogmática Penal y Política Criminal. Ibáñez/Ubijus, México

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno Hernández M (2020) Hacia una dogmática penal latinoamericana más acorde a sus realidades, en LH-Luzón, vol I. Reus, Madrid, pp 311–326

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino CS (1980) Los límites de la responsabilidad penal. Una teoría liberal del delito, Astrea, Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino CS (1984) Consideraciones sobre la dogmática jurídica (con referencia particular a la dogmática penal), Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, México (1ª reimpr. 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pantaleón Díaz M (2018) La utilidad de una buena dogmática para una buena jurisprudencia (y viceversa). El ejemplo de la sentencia de la Sala Segunda del Tribunal Supremo 805/2017, de 11 de diciembre (caso «Madrid Arena»), en: Libertas 7:103–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Parma C (2020) En busca del futuro del Derecho penal, en LH-Luzón, vol I. Reus, Madrid, pp 327–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxin C (1973) Kriminalpolitik und Strafrechtssystem, 2. Aufl. (1., 1970), Walter de Gruyter, Berlin/New York [(1972) Política criminal y sistema del Derecho penal, trad. e introducción de Muñoz Conde F, Bosch, Barcelona]

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxin C (2006) Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil. Band I: Grundlagen. Der Aufbau der Verbrechenslehre, 4. Aufl., C. H. Beck, München [(1997) Derecho Penal. Parte General. Tomo I: Fundamentos. La estructura de la teoría del delito, trad. de la 2ª ed. alemana por Luzón Peña D-M/Díaz y García Conlledo M/de Vicente Remesal J, Civitas, Madrid]

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxin C (2015) Täterschaft und Tatherrschaft, 9. Aufl., Water De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston [Autoría y dominio del hecho en Derecho penal, trad. de Cuello Contreras J/Serrano González de Murillo J L, Marcial Pons, Madrid]

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxin C, Greco L (2020) Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil. Band I: Grundlagen. Der Aufbau der Verbrechenslehre, 5. Aufl., C. H. Beck, München, 2020

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez-Ostiz Gutiérrez P (2019) El mito de la mecánica aplicación judicial de la ley, en LH-Jorge vol 1, pp 325–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Schünemann (2011) Was heiβt und zu welchem Ende betreibt man Strafrechtsdogmatik? Zu Fischer’s These der “fremden seltsamen Welten” anhand aktueller BGH-Urteile zu Begriff und Funktion der “besonderen persönlichen Merkmale” im Strafrecht. GA, pp 445–461

    Google Scholar 

  • Schünemann (2016) Über Strafrecht im demokratischen Rechtsstaat, das unverzichtbare Rationalitätsniveau seiner Dogmatik und die vorgeblich progressive Rückschrittspropaganda. ZIS, pp 654–671 (http://www.zis-online.com/dat/artikel/2016_10_1051.pdf) [(2019) El Derecho penal en el Estado democrático de Derecho y el irrenunciable nivel de racionalidad de su dogmática, trad. de Roso Cañadillas R/Pérez-Sauquillo Muñoz C, Reus/B de F, Madrid/Buenos Aires/Montevideo]

  • Silva Sánchez JM (2004) Straftatsystematik deutscher Prägung: Unzeitgemaβ? GA 2004, pp 679–690

    Google Scholar 

  • Sotomayor Acosta JO (2008) ¿El Derecho penal garantista en retirada? RP 21:148–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Vives Antón TS (2011) Fundamentos del Sistema Penal, 2ª ed., Acción Significativa y Derechos Constitucionales, Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia

    Google Scholar 

  • Vives Antón TS (2017) Reivindicación del pensamiento de un fiscal prusiano, en: EH-Mir, B de F, Montevideo/Buenos Aires, pp 233–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J (2012) Strafrecht und Strafrechtswissenschaft im internationalen und europäischen Rechtsraum. JZ 67:25–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaffaroni ER (2017) ¿Hacia dónde irá la ciencia jurídico-penal?, en: EH-Mir, B de F, Montevideo/Buenos Aires, pp 243–250

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miguel Díaz y García Conlledo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Díaz y García Conlledo, M. (2023). Criminal Law and Legal Theory: Not Just Legal Dogmatics, but Never Without It. In: Demetrio Crespo, E., García Figueroa, A., Marcilla Córdoba, G. (eds) Crisis of the Criminal Law in the Democratic Constitutional State. Legal Studies in International, European and Comparative Criminal Law, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-13412-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-13413-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics