Abstract
The aim of the work is to critically reflect on retributionism as the end of punishment in the constitutional state of law. Taking German idealism (Kant and Hegel) as a starting point, the most recent reformulations of this apparently outdated current of thought are analyzed. A first approach to the methodological distinction between the term’s retribution, reprobation, and revenge is proposed to defend a secularized theory of punishment.
This work is part of the Research Project Crisis of the Criminal Law of the Rule of Law: Manifestations and Trends (SBPLY/17/18501/000223) granted by the Junta de Comunidades de Castilla - La Mancha and co-financed by the European Regional Development Fund (ERDF), under the direction of Prof. Drs. Eduardo Demetrio Crespo, Alfonso J. García Figueroa and Gema Mª Marcilla Córdoba [https://blog.uclm.es/proyectocresta/].
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
- 2.
Pérez del Valle (2020).
- 3.
Mañalich (2015).
- 4.
Klug (1968), pp. 36 et seq.
- 5.
- 6.
Hruschka (2010), pp. 493 et seq.
- 7.
Klug (2002), pp. 31 et seq.
- 8.
Ibíd., p. 32.
- 9.
It is worth reproducing them here (Kant 1989, pp. 165 et):
Criminal law is the right which the sovereign has, with respect to him who is subject to him, to impose a penalty for his crime. (…) The judicial penalty (poena forensis), distinct from the natural penalty (poena naturalis), by which the vice punishes itself and which the legislator does not take into account at all, can never serve simply as a means to promote another good, either for the offender himself or for civil society, but must be imposed on him only because he has committed a crime (…). Before any thought can be given to deriving any benefit from this penalty for himself or for his fellow citizens, he must have been judged worthy of punishment. The criminal law is a categorical imperative and woe betide him who crawls through the sinuosities of the doctrine of happiness to find something that will exempt him from punishment, or even only from a degree of it, for the advantage it promises, following the Pharisaic motto “it is better that one man die than that the whole people perish”. For if justice perishes, it is of no value that men should live on Earth. (…).
But what is the type and degree of punishment that public justice adopts as a principle and as a pattern? None other than the principle of equality (in the position of the faithfulness) of the scales of justice): not to lean more to one side than to the other. Therefore, whatever undeserved harm you inflict on another in a town, you do to yourself (…). Only the law of talion (ius talionis) can safely offer the quality and quantity of punishment, but well understood that in the bosom of the tribunal (not in your private trial); all others fluctuate from one side to the other and cannot be adequate to the opinion of pure and strict justice, because other considerations intrude (…). But if he has committed murder, he must die (…).
This equality of penalties, which is only possible by the sentence of death by the judge, according to the strict law of talion, is manifested in the fact that only in this way the death sentence is pronounced on all in proportion to the internal wickedness of the criminals (even if it was not a murder, but another crime of State that only death can erase).
- 10.
Klug (2002), p. 34.
Also (Hegel 1968, pp. 107 et seq.):
In the positive legal science of modern times, the theory of punishment is one of the subjects that has been the worst delved into, since in it the intellect is not sufficient, since it is essentially about the concept.
If crime and its overcoming, as what is subsequently determined as punishment, is generally considered only as evil, it can certainly be judged as irrational to want an evil merely because another evil already exists.
In the various theories of punishment, this superficial character of evil is presupposed as the main element: the theory of prevention, intimidation, punishment, correction, etc., and what, on the contrary, must result as good, is determined precisely in a superficial way. (…).
In this discussion what is of interest is only that the crime must be denied not as the production of an evil, but as the violation of Law as Law, and then, what is the existence that the crime has, and what must be annulled; that is the true evil that must be uprooted and the essential point is where this existence is. As long as the concepts on this point are not strictly recognized, disorder must dominate in the consideration of punishment.
The violation that affects the offender is not only just in itself - as just is, at the same time, his will, which is in itself and the existence of his freedom, the Right - but it is also a Right imposed on the offender himself, that is, in his existing will, in his action. Because in his action, as the action of a rational entity, a universal is implicit: (…)
The overcoming of crime is punishment, because according to the concept it is the violation of the violation and according to the existence, crime has a qualitatively and quantitatively determined extension; therefore, its negation, as existence, has another existence. However, this identity that is based on the concept is not equality in the specific, external nature of the violation, but in what it is in itself according to the value of the same.
- 11.
Klug (2002), pp. 34 et seq.
- 12.
Ibíd., p. 36.
- 13.
Hruschka (2010), pp. 494 et seq.
- 14.
Kant (1989), p. 165.
- 15.
Klug (1981), p. 150.
We deviate here slightly from the translation by which the article has been cited, which is why the passage is taken from the German version that appeared in 1981.
- 16.
Hruschka (2010), p. 495.
- 17.
Feijoo Sánchez (2014), pp. 110 et seq.
- 18.
Cf. Duff (2015), pp. 151 et seq. on the “communitarian dream or Macintyre’s nightmare.”
- 19.
Feijoo Sánchez (2014), p. 117.
- 20.
Feijoo Sánchez (2014), p. 118.
- 21.
Pawlik (2016), pp. 33 et seq.
- 22.
Ibíd., p. 43.
- 23.
Ibíd., p. 46.
- 24.
Ibíd., p. 50.
- 25.
Ibíd., p. 51.
- 26.
Ibíd., p. 52.
- 27.
Ibíd., pp. 56–57.
- 28.
Ibíd., p. 57.
- 29.
Demko (2017), pp. 227 et seq.
- 30.
Hörnle (2015), pp. 33 et seq.
- 31.
Pérez Barberá (2014), p. 3.
- 32.
- 33.
Pérez Barberá (2014), p. 6.
- 34.
Ibíd., p. 6.
Cf., among other references, Robinson (2012), pp. 40–41 on the terms “deontological deservedness” and “empirical deservedness”; von Hirsch (1998), pp. 31 et seq. on the relationship between “censorship and proportionality”; and Sánchez Lázaro (2016), pp. 48 et seq. on the “normative structure of proportionality.”
- 35.
- 36.
Pérez Barberá (2014), p. 10.
- 37.
Walter (2016), pp. 7 et seq.
- 38.
Ibíd., pp. 8 et seq.
- 39.
In detail, as a scientific and ideological problem, see Demetrio Crespo (1999), pp. 73 et seq. [2016, pp. 70 et seq.].
- 40.
In detail, as a scientific and ideological problem, Vid. Demetrio Crespo (1999), pp. 73 ff. [2016, pp. 70 et seq].
- 41.
On feelings and punishment, see, for example, Rodríguez Horcajo (2016), pp. 134 et seq.
- 42.
Walter (2016), p. 12.
- 43.
Vid. in this regard, with multiple references, Demetrio Crespo (1999), pp. 187 et seq.; 215 et seq. (2016), pp. 225 et seq., 273 et seq.
- 44.
Walter (2016), p. 12.
- 45.
Ibíd., p. 13.
- 46.
In this regard, with multiple references, Demetrio Crespo (2020), pp. 65 et seq.
- 47.
In this direction, e.g., Roxin/Greco: “Am deutlichsten werden diese Gefahren bei Walter: Geht es bei der Vergeltung um ein Urbedürfnis des Menschen, das deshalb, weil “die wenigsten die Kraft haben, ihren Drang nach Vergeltung aufzulösen (unterdrücken nützt nichts)”, von der Gesellschaft abgefangen und kontrolliert werden muss, gibt es keinen Grund, weshalb einen Schuldunfähigen in gewissen Sonderfällen von Strafe verschonen sollte” (Roxin and Greco 2020, pp. 133–134).
- 48.
Demetrio Crespo (2020), esp. pp. 109 et seq., 187 et seq.
- 49.
Greco (2009), pp. 303 et seq.
- 50.
- 51.
Schünemann (2019), p. 15.
- 52.
Roxin and Greco (2020), p. 128.
- 53.
Ibíd., pp. 21–22.
- 54.
Ibíd., pp. 22–23.
On the problem of the “defitional barrier” in the philosophical discussion according to which any pre-theoretical definition of the concept of punishment entails the risk of prejudging the spectrum of relevant justificatory theories, see Mañalich (2015), p. 8 and note 25.
- 55.
Roxin and Greco (2020), pp. 128–129.
- 56.
- 57.
Ferrajoli (1995), pp. 27, 354 et seq.
- 58.
Corcoy Bidasolo (2017), pp. 297 et seq.
- 59.
Frisch (2017), p. 580.
- 60.
See, for example, Rosanvallon, who explains that populism is a phenomenon that revolutionizes the politics of the twenty-first century, although we have not yet fully appreciated the transformation to which it has given rise and we do not have a theory of the phenomenon (Rosanvallon 2020, Introduction).
- 61.
Ferrajoli (1995), p. 225.
- 62.
Ibíd., p. 254.
Puig also explained in his famous Introduction to the Bases (published in 1976) the following: “The fact that absolute theories have not found a place in criminal law, and instead in Christian ethics, is perfectly appropriate to the different functions of both orders. Criminal law, like every sector of law, cannot claim to establish absolute justice on earth, and the contrary would be to confuse its boundaries with those of morality” (Mir Puig 2003, p. 52).
- 63.
Callies (1974), pp. 35 et seq.
- 64.
- 65.
Roxin (1976), pp. 12 et seq.
- 66.
On this, Demetrio Crespo (1999), pp. 61 et seq.
- 67.
Thus, e.g., Mañalich clarifies the following: “to that extent, the categorical character of the criminal law by virtue of whose application the penalty is judicially imposed determines that it must necessarily be executed, without this practical necessity being relativized by prudential considerations of utility” (Mañalich 2018, p. 512). In the same sense pronounce Byrd and Hruschka: “Kant accepts no utilitarian calculus when it comes to the criminal law as a categorial imperative” (Byrd and Hruschka 2010, p. 268).
- 68.
Pérez del Valle (2020), pp. 220 et seq.
- 69.
Ibíd., pp. 224 et seq.
- 70.
Demetrio Crespo (2017), pp. 19 et seq.
- 71.
Hörnle (2013), pp. 49 et seq.
- 72.
Demetrio Crespo (2011), pp. 694 et seq.
- 73.
Demetrio Crespo (2017), pp. 75 et seq.
- 74.
Ibíd., pp. 90–91.
- 75.
Ferrajoli (1995), pp. 257–258.
- 76.
García Amado (2018), pp. 323 et seq.
- 77.
Of “institutionalized revenge,” even if it is called “justice,” he speaks, e.g., Corcoy Bidasolo (2017), p. 285.
- 78.
- 79.
This argument, in the present text only sketched due to space limitations, should, however, be the subject of further development, due to the complexity of this type of theories, ranging from the so-called retributive theories of bonding, through the new approaches of the expressive theories mentioned above, to the preventive theories of bonding. (Vid. Roxin and Greco 2020, pp. 145–160).
- 80.
Vid. however, among many other references, Stratenwerth (1995), p. 20.
References
Alonso Álamo M (2019) Polisemia del término retribución y pena retributivo-preventiva. In: Cancio Meliá M et al (eds) Libro Homenaje al Profesor Dr. Agustín Jorge Barreiro. Servicio de Publicaciones UAM, Madrid, pp 1291–1307
Blom P (2010) Böse Philosophen. Carl Hanser, München
Bruckmann P (2019) Sinn und Unsinn gegenwärtiger Vergeltungstheorien – überholt, hilfreich oder notwendig zur Legitimation staatlicher Strafe? KriPoZ 2:105–118
Byrd S, Hruschka J (2010) Kant’s doctrine of right. A commentary. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Callies RP (1974) Theorie der Strafe im demokratischen und sozialen Rechtsstaat. Ein Beitrag zur strafrechtsdogmatischen Grundlagendiskussion. Fischer Taschenbuch, Frankfurt am Main
Chiesa LE (2020) Selective incompatibilism, free will, and the (limited) role of retribution in punishment theory. RULR 71(4):101–125
Corcoy Bidasolo M (2017) Prevención limitada vs. neoretribucionismo. In: Silva Sánchez JMª et al (Coord.) Estudios de Derecho Penal. Homenaje al profesor Santiago Mir Puig BdeF, Montevideo – Buenos Aires, pp 285–297
Demetrio Crespo E (1999) Prevención general e individualización judicial de la pena, 1ª ed. Ediciones USAL, Salamanca [(2016), 2ª ed. BdeF, Buenos Aires-Montevideo]
Demetrio Crespo E (2011) Schuld und Strafzwecke. In: Heinrich M et al (Hg.) Strafrecht als Scientia Universalis. Festschrift für Claus Roxin zum 80. Geburtstag. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 689–703
Demetrio Crespo E (2017) Fragmentos sobre Neurociencias y Derecho Penal. BdeF, Montevideo-Buenos Aires
Demetrio Crespo E (2020) El Derecho penal del Estado de Derecho entre el espíritu de nuestro tiempo y la Constitución. Reus, Madrid
Demko D (2017) Hegels Straftheorie im Lichte gegenwärtiger expressiver Straftheorien. In: Kubiciel M et al (Hg.) Hegel’s Erben?. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 277–300
Donna EA (2019) Persona y Derecho. Rubinzal – Culzoni, Buenos Aires
Duff A (2015) Sobre el castigo. Por una justicia penal que hable el lenguaje de la comunidad. Siglo XXI Editores, Buenos Aires
Escamilla Castillo M (2010) The purposes of legal punishment. Ratio Juris 23(4):460–478
Feijoo Sánchez B (2007) Retribución y prevención general. Un estudio sobre la teoría de la pena y las funciones del Derecho penal. BdeF, Montevideo-Buenos Aires
Feijoo Sánchez B (2014) La legitimidad de la pena estatal. Un breve recorrido por las teorías de la pena estatal. Iustel, Madrid
Ferrajoli L (1995) Derecho y Razón. Teoría del garantismo penal. Trotta, Madrid
Frisch W (2017) Von theokratischem zu säkularem Strafrecht. Zum Zusammenhang von Staatstheorie und Strafrecht. In: Saliger F et al (Hg.) Rechtsstaatliches Strafrecht. Festschrift für Ulfrid Neumann zum 70. Geburtstag. C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, pp 575–586
García Amado JA (2018) Retribución y justificación del castigo. In: Portilla Contreras G et al (Dir.) Un juez para la democracia: Libro Homenaje a Perfecto Andrés Ibáñez. Dykinson, Madrid, pp 323–340
Greco L (2009) Lebendiges und Totes in Feuerbachs Straftheorie. Ein Beitrag zur gegenwärtigen strafrechtlichen Grundlagendiskussion. Duncker & Humblot, Berlín
Grosse-Wilde T (2017) Erfolgszurechnung in der Strafzumessung. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen
Hegel GF (1968) Filosofía del Derecho, Prólogo de Carlos Marx, 5ª ed. Editorial Claridad, Buenos Aires
Hörnle T (2013) Kriminalstrafe ohne Schuldvorwurf. Ein Plädoyer für Änderungen in der strafrechtlichen Verbrechenslehre. Nomos, Baden-Baden
Hörnle T (2015) Teorías de la pena. Universidad Externado de Colombia, Bogotá
Hruschka J (2010) Die “Verabschiedung” Kants durch Ulrich Klug im Jahre 1968: Einige Korrekturen. ZStW 122(3):494–503
Kant I (1989) La Metafísica de las Costumbres, traducción y notas de A. Cortina Orts y J. Conill Sancho. Tecnos, Madrid
Klug U (1968) “Abschied von Kant und Hegel”. In: Baurmann J (Hg.) Programm für ein neues Strafgesetzbuch. Fischer, Frankfurt am Main, pp 36–41 [también en: Id. (1981), Skeptische Rechtsphilosophie und humanes Strafrecht, Band 2. Materielle und formelle Strafrechtsprobleme. Springer-Verlag, Berlin. Heidelberg. New York, pp 149–154 [≥ (2002), “Despedida de Kant y Hegel (Una crítica jusfilosófica básica)”, en Id., Problemas de la Filosofía y de la Pragmática del Derecho, 2ª reimp. Fontamara, México D.F, pp 31–36 (trad. Jorge Mª Seña)]
Mañalich JP (2015) Retribucionismo consecuencialista como programa de ideología punitiva. InDret 2:1–32
Mañalich JP (2018) Respeto y retribución: la pena jurídica en La metafísica de las costumbres. Revista de Ciencia Política 38(3):507–526
Mir Puig S (2003) Introducción a las bases del Derecho penal. BdeF, Montevideo-Buenos Aires
Pawlik M (2016) Ciudadanía y Derecho penal. Fundamentos de la teoría de la pena y del delito en un Estado de libertades. Atelier, Barcelona
Pérez Barberá G (2014) Problemas y perspectivas de las teorías expresivas de la pena. Una justificación deontológica de la pena como institución. InDret 4:1–43
Pérez del Valle C (2020) Poena forensis y retribución. Propuesta para la restauración de una teoría. InDret 3:214–259
Rawls J (1955) Two concepts of rules. Philos Rev 64(1):3–32
Robinson PH (2012) Principios distributivos del Derecho penal: a quién debe sancionarse y en qué medida. Marcial Pons, Madrid-Barcelona-Buenos Aires-São Paulo
Rodríguez Horcajo D (2016) Comportamiento humano y pena estatal: disuasión, cooperación y equidad. Marcial Pons, Madrid-Barcelona-Buenos Aires-São Paulo
Rosanvallon P (2020) El siglo del populismo. Galaxia Guternberg, Barcelona
Roxin C (1976) Sentido y límites de la pena estatal. En Id., Problemas básicos del Derecho penal. Reus, Madrid, pp 11–36
Roxin C, Greco L (2020) Strafrecht. Allgemeiner Teil. Band I. Grundlagen. Der Aufbau der Verbrechenslehre, 5. Auflage. C.H. Beck, München
Sánchez Lázaro FG (2016) Una teoría principialista de la pena. Marcial Pons, Madrid-Barcelona-Buenos Aires-São Paulo
Schünemann B (2019) El Derecho penal en el Estado democrático de Derecho y el irrenunciable nivel de su dogmática. BdeF, Madrid: Reus/Montevideo-Buenos Aires
Stratenwerth G (1995) Was leistet die Lehre von den Strafzwecken? Walter de Gruyter, Berlin-New York
Teixeira A (2018) Las teorías retributivas en el pensamiento angloamericano contemporáneo. Letra: Derecho Penal, Año IV 7:35–77
von Hirsch A (1998) Censurar y castigar. Trotta, Madrid
Walter T (2016) Strafe und Vergeltung – Rehabilitation und Grenzen eines Prinzips. Nomos, Baden-Baden
White MD (ed) (2011) Retributivism. Essays on theory and policy. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zaibert L (2006) Punishment and retribution. Ashgate, Aldershot
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Demetrio Crespo, E. (2023). Review on Retribution as Punishment Purpose. In: Demetrio Crespo, E., García Figueroa, A., Marcilla Córdoba, G. (eds) Crisis of the Criminal Law in the Democratic Constitutional State. Legal Studies in International, European and Comparative Criminal Law, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_2
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13413-5_2
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-031-13412-8
Online ISBN: 978-3-031-13413-5
eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)