Skip to main content

Modulation to a New Key in The Syntax of Time: Peter Byrne Manchester and Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka’s Common Telos of the All

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Posthumanism and Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 125))

  • 300 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter explores foundational issues in the philosophy of time and space by comparing the phenomenological contributions of Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Peter Byrne Manchester. Each of these two philosophers have revived an ancient paradigm for thinking about problems of continuity in the philosophy of space and time. Peter Byrne Manchester’s 2005 book, The Syntax of Time: The Phenomenology of Time in Greek Physics and Speculative Logic from Iamblichus to Anaximander—the second in the Brill series Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition—traces Husserl’s phenomenology of inner time-consciousness back through Plotinus to Aristotle’s philosophy of time, and thereby reconnects its problematic to the most archaic origins of philosophy in the Presocratics. Through the philosophical reconstruction of an ancient worldview on the basis of an insight about the ordering principle of time as a logical syntax, Peter Manchester uncovers a neglected ancient doctrine called spherics (sphairikē, or sphairikon logon), which has deep implications not only for time but for all the dimensions of experience. He names his guiding figure the Sphere of the All, a formulation belonging to his ancient sources. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka’s phenomenology of life also recognizes a previously unnoticed syntax. For her, it is the intrinsic functioning of life, which she elaborates in her phenomenology of life as ontopoietic process. Her extensive account of life’s inner-workings yields a phenomenological cosmology of multiple spheres of being grounded in a “great vision of the All” (Tymieniecka 2000, 643), much like Manchester’s spherics. The convergence to similar frameworks arrived at independently by these two philosophers is a philosophical synchronicity due to the teleology at play in their phenomenological thought, common to multiple philosophical cosmologies, but what is more remarkable is the convergence of their specific functional systems and metrological terms. This convergence arises from the pursuit of an ancient and perennial cosmology rooted in a deep synthesis of order and measure. The ancient intuition that the language of God is the language of mathematics plays a special role in classical phenomenology, and the recovery of the doctrine of the spheres represents a new contribution to the synthetic and geometrical side of this intuition. By arriving at a synthesis of the most fundamental ontological units in these two systems, a new paradigm of speculative cosmology and transcendental logic emerges from the paradigm of the sphere.

Thought builds on time… on many scales.

(Peter Manchester, Unpublished Introduction to The Syntax of Time)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Tymieniecka engages the autopoietic theory in Analecta Husserliana volumes 60, and 100, and other contributors to Analecta Husserliana have also compared ontopoiesis with autopoiesis, for instance Daniela Verducci and Elisa Tona. See also my own study on the topic of the calculus occluded by Maturana and Varela’s theory, “Ontopoiesis, Autopoiesis, and a Calculus Intended for Self-Reference,” forthcoming in Analecta Husserliana.

  2. 2.

    World order: the constant, intrinsic pattern of organization, whose presence is arrived at conjecturally through “structurally rooted indications concerning the relations… to the world order” (Tymieniecka 1966, 21).

  3. 3.

    The technical details of the mathesis synthesis are inspired by two systems: George Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form and Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s “original geometry.” The right-angle bracket of the ‘marked state’ operator (the ‘mark’ or the ‘cross’) in George Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form (Spencer-Brown 2008) guides a unified mathesis, but this consideration is beyond the scope of this presentation. The iconic logic of Spencer-Brown’s calculus of indications is a void-based system that begins by drawing a distinction (“the first distinction”) in an otherwise unmarked state. The initial consequences of this fundamental operation of crossing the void yield the two laws of form, the calculus of indications. These indications of the first distinction are signs that synthesize the construction of a universe, called the marked state, or simply the form. The laws at this level are called the primary arithmetic. The next level is distinguished by the introduction of variables, and this is called the primary algebra. Within the primary algebra a new calculus grows inside the calculus, and this is the re-entry of the form into itself, which we experience as the fifth crossing or fifth eternal order. The five eternal orders correspond to the four dimensions of experience, plus the void. Husserl’s early work on manifolds and syntaxes sought just such a universal laws of form in the context of the widest sense of a mathesis universalis. Husserl’s theory of formal manifolds and Tymieniecka’s work on the universal world-order is vindicated by this achievement of a void-based eidetics.

  4. 4.

    The other system is Fichte’s “original geometry.” In his geometry, the archaic construction “UnendlichEk” is rendered by David W. Wood as “infinite polygon” (Wood 2012), but it could also be translated ‘unending angle,’ comparable to Mahnke’s allmittelpunkt. Fichte’s “living and active self-consciousness” replaces a perceived “rigid and lifeless formalism” (4) of analytic geometry, and we shall follow the same spirit here. The working-out of a rigorous deductive system of geometrical elements gives the prototypical form of a general spherics in a way that is, I imagine, more in line with Proclus’ noetic theory of the geometricals than Euclid’s lost Sphaerica (judging by the formalism of the Elements) because it expresses the geometry of life. Seeing a point from another point cannot get to the heart of being a point, on account of the extension of experience. As Spencer-Brown puts it, being seeing being seeing being seeing being cannot see itself without going half-blind, the blind side being the future. The ontological procession of dimensionality characterizes living processes, that is, all experience. Inter-objective relations give no insight as to the synthesis of life, and neither does pure analysis. Scaled to our world, a living geometry calls on us to find a way to explore other dimensions and other worlds—the other spheres of being.

  5. 5.

    Manchester’s work on the noetic triad (Manchester 1992) as prefiguring the doctrine of the trinity and expressing the schema of participation of the one and the many should be researched along with his insights about the noetic circle in The Syntax of Time (Manchester 2005, 149), yielding a real “engine of participation” (134; Manchester 2002, 81), the engine of the vehicle of the soul, the ochema pneuma. For my own part, triangles and circles are never alone, always dynamic, and the schema ochema is the circular activity of the original angle, which is not a closed form without the circle, but always indicates three values anyway; the marked state, the unmarked state, and the distinction. The construction of stereometric form in the Timaeus (53d–55c) can be seen as a sphere-packing operation if the constituent triangles are understood to be the angles signifying the centers, radii, and intercoherence of spheres.

  6. 6.

    See Gaiser (1963). For an overview of this doctrine with original sources, see Hans Joachim Krämer’s (1990) Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents (trans. John R. Catan), and the 2012 volume, The Other Plato: The Tübingen Interpretation of Plato’s Inner-Academic Teachings (ed. Dmitri Nikulin; Nikulin 2012).

References

  • Gaiser, Konrad. 1963. Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre. Studien zur Systematischen und Geschichtlichen Begründung der Wissens. Stuttgart: Klett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, James G. 2009. Who One Is: Book 1, Meontology of the “I”: A Transcendental Phenomenology. Bloomington: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, Joseph Ehrenfried. 1957. The History of Mathematics. Trans. Gaynor, Frank, and Henrietta O. Midonick. New York: Philosophical Library, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, Burt C. 2010. The Philosophy of Husserl. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. The Origin of the Logic of Symbolic Mathematics: Edmund Husserl and Jacob Klein. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1969. Formal and Transcendental Logic. Trans. Dorian Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2003. Philosophy of Arithmetic. Trans. Allas Willard. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1974. Logic. Trans. Robert Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz. New York: Bobbs-Merrill Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, Hans Joachim. 1990. Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics. A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock, Stephen W., and James G. Hart, eds. 1986. Essays in Phenomenological Theology. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1964. The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahnke, Dietrich. 1937. Unendliche Sphäre und Allmittelpunkt: Beiträge zur Genealogie der Mathematischen Mystik. Saale: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manchester, Peter. 1987. Eternity. In The Encyclopedia of Religion, ed. Mircea Eliade, vol. 5. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. The Noetic Triad in Plotinus, Marius Victorinus, and Augustine. In Neoplatonism and Gnosticism, ed. Rickhard T. Wallis. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Teleology Revisited: A Neoplatonic Perspective in Environmental Biology. In Neoplatonism and Contemporary Thought, Part One, ed. R. Baine Harris. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Syntax of Time: The Phenomenology of Time in Greek Physics and Speculative Logic from Iamblichus to Anaximander. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. n.d. Unpublished Introduction to The Syntax of Time. Stony Brook: The Estate of Peter Byrne Manchester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merlan, Philip. 1960. From Platonism to Neoplatonism. Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nikulin, Dmitri, ed. 2012. The Other Plato: The Tübingen Interpretation of Plato’s Inner-Academic Teachings. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Meara, Dominic. 1998. The Structure of Being and the Search for the Good. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 2000. Timaeus. Trans. Donald J. Zeyl. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poulet, Georges. 1966. The Metamorphoses of the Circle. Trans. Carley Dawson and Elliott Coleman. Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer-Brown, George. 2008. Laws of Form. London: Allen and Unwin, 1969. Leipzig: Bohmeier Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa. 1964. Leibniz’ Cosmological Synthesis. Netherlands: Van Grocum, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1965. Conjectural Inference and Phenomenological Analysis. In Contributions to Logic and Methodology in Honor of J. M. Bochenski, ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka. Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. Why is there Something Rather than Nothing? Prolegomena to the Phenomenology of Cosmic Creation. Asse: Van Grocum, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. Analecta Husserliana. The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research, The Phenomenological Realism of the Possible Worlds. The ‘A Priori,’ Activity and Passivity of Consciousness, Phenomenology and Nature. Vol. 3. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2000. Impetus and Equipoise in the Life-Strategies of Reason. Logos and Life, Book Four. Vol. 70. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Fullness of the Logos in the Key of Life, Book One. The Case of God in the New Enlightenment. Vol. 100. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Phenomenology and Existentialism in the Twentieth Century, Book Three: Heralding the New Enlightenment. Vol. 105. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Phenomenology/Ontopoiesis Retrieving the Geo-Cosmic Horizons of Antiquity: Logos and Life, Part One. Vol. 110. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Phenomenology and the Human Positioning in the Cosmos. The Life-World, Nature, Earth: Book Two. Vol. 114. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, David W. 2012. “Mathesis of the Mind”: A Study of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre and Geometry. Amsterdam: Rondopi.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Dible, R. (2023). Modulation to a New Key in The Syntax of Time: Peter Byrne Manchester and Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka’s Common Telos of the All. In: Hornbuckle, C.A., Smith, J.S., Smith, W.S. (eds) Posthumanism and Phenomenology. Analecta Husserliana, vol 125. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-10414-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics