Skip to main content

Epistemology: The Foundations of Scientific Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Science, Technology and Society

Abstract

At the beginning of the twentieth century, science became a specific, circumscribed and autonomous subject of reflection within philosophy. Interest was therefore fuelled to explain the fundamental aspects on which scientific knowledge is based and a series of methodological proposals were put forward to guide the correct construction of the same. The greatest contribution to this undertaking would be made by the movement of logical positivism and by the science philosopher Karl Popper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Forerunners of this movement, among others, are indicated (and not always entirely correctly) including the German physicist Ernst Mach (1838–1916), the Austrian physicist, mathematician and philosopher Ludwig Eduard Boltzmann (1844–1906), the German philosopher and psychologist Hermann Brentano (1838–1917) and the Austrian philosopher Alexius Meinong (1853–1920).

  2. 2.

    Despite sharing the same intellectual perspective, the authors are also very different from each other, whose positions are not always compatible or whose positions are not always compatible or superimposable.

  3. 3.

    Even if the term positivism is rejected by Carnap.

  4. 4.

    Principle that stems from a philosophical conception with a marked mechanistic character, according to which each phenomenon or event of the present is necessarily determined by a historic phenomenon or event.

  5. 5.

    We say former Wittgenstein because thereafter he radically distanced himself from the initial positions expressed in Tractatus.

  6. 6.

    In social sciences, this position has led to the rejection of mentalism and an embracing of behaviourism. Behaviourism rejects the use (for example) of concepts of intelligence, intention, interpretation and so on, to explain human behaviours because concepts (being in the mind) cannot be observed. Behaviourism only focuses on actions, only on observable entities. If in the context of biology all the phenomena of life can be described and explained through physical and chemical laws, in the sphere of psychology, behaviourism theories consider that all the psychic and mental processes must necessarily be reduced to behaviours and must therefore be expressed in neurophysiological terms.

  7. 7.

    If we are consistent with a constructivist approach, we should use the term “attributes” instead of “properties” or “characteristics”. In fact, the properties are elements possessed by the referent (therefore an objectualist position), while the attributes are elements attributed to the referent by an observer. Added to this is the fact that different observers could attribute different elements to the same referent.

  8. 8.

    Paradoxically, this term, with its Latin roots, made up of verum (true) and facere (make, render) seems more akin to a constructivist epistemology.

References

  • Bachelard, G. (1934). Le nouvel esprit scientifique. PUF (transl. The New Scientific Spirit. Beacon Press, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Weltkreis. (transl. The Logical Structure of the World. University of California Press, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1932-33). Über Protokollsätze. Erkenntnis, 3, 215–228. (transl. On Protocol Sentences. Noûs 1987, 21(4), 457–470. https://doi.org/10.2307/2215667).

  • Carnap, R. (1934). Logische Syntax der Sprache. Springer (transl. The Logical Syntax of Language. Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1967.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. M. M. (1906). La théorie physique: son objet et sa structure. Chevalier et Rivière. (transl. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Princeton University Press. 2nd. ed., 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Enriques, F. (1906). Problemi della scienza. Zanichelli. (transl. Problems of Science. The Open Court Pub. Co. 1914).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1935). Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tat- sache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Benno Schwabe. (transl. Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact. Chicago University Press,1979.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1952). Fundamentals of Concepts Formation in Empirical Science. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgarve, A. (1993). Common Sense, Science and Scepticism: A Historical Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1934). Logik der Forschung. Springer. (transl. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Basic Books, 1959).

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1956–57). Realismus und das Ziel der Wissenschaft. (transl. Realism and the Aim of Science. Hutchinson,1983.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1951). The Rise of Scientific Philosophy. University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, C. (2004). Science Based Toxicology: A New Strategy for Toxic Risk Assessment in the 21st Century. Animal Aid.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gobo, G., Marcheselli, V. (2022). Epistemology: The Foundations of Scientific Knowledge. In: Science, Technology and Society. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-08306-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-08306-8_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-08305-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-08306-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics