Skip to main content

An Ethics of Courage and Honesty in Wittgenstein and Heidegger

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Heidegger and his Anglo-American Reception

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 119))

Abstract

I use Heidegger’s early thoughts about anxiety and authenticity to read Wittgenstein’s later work as a kind of performative ethics. Although overt discussions of ethics largely disappear from Wittgenstein’s later writings, these works can be read as exercises in radical philosophical honesty, by exposing the pictures he tacitly relies on to pretend to know more than he does. Being and Time gives up on the traditional ethical project of offering specific recommendations for what to do or how to live, and turns that lack of answers itself into the answer. The one thing we know about morality is that there is nothing to know about morality, at least in the traditional sense of transcendent values; we must honestly and courageously own up to the fact that there are no given answers, that our being remains forever unsettled. In other words, the absence of objective values gives rise to one objective value: the courage to face and face up to this absence. Wittgenstein too seeks an attitude of metaphysical humility, an admission that traditional philosophical questions have no answers, that they must be dissolved instead of solved. The Investigations can be seen as one long confession that his previous philosophizing had not been honest, that he had claimed to know things he didn’t know, deep secrets about truth and reality he couldn’t know because they weren’t there to be known. Much of Wittgenstein’s later work consists in precise descriptions of the mental images and analogies he associates with various phrases which led him to think that he had grasped deep metaphysical truths. His readers, recognizing similar notions occurring in their own thoughts, can then realize what flimsy support their own ideas have, thus exchanging their disguised nonsense for patent. This self-examination can be seen as an exercise in radical philosophical honesty that courageously gives up illusions, clearing up linguistic confusions in service to an ethical endeavor.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Monk 1990, 64.

  2. 2.

    PI §118. See the end of the paper for a list of abbreviations.

  3. 3.

    Stanley Cavell (1982) finds considerable emotional weight in Philosophical Investigations, in particular the worry that we might somehow lose contact with each other, but I have never found this tone of anxiety there, as fruitful as Cavell’s views are. The interlocutors’ worries seem to me the artificial results of confusions rather than genuine concerns.

  4. 4.

    Georg Henrik von Wright claims that “philosophy was an integrated part of his own being” (Johannessen et al. 1994, 165).

  5. 5.

    Fann 1967, 34, 52, 81.

  6. 6.

    As his friend G.H. von Wright notes, “it is surely part of Wittgenstein’s achievement to have made concern for language central to philosophy. But few only of those who shared Wittgenstein’s concern for language also shared the peculiar motivation which aroused his concern for it. One aspect of Wittgenstein’s all too obvious alienation from his times is his feeling that not even those who professed to follow him were really engaged in the same spiritual endeavor as he” (1984, 204–5).

  7. 7.

    I am not alone in noting this discrepancy. Brian McGuinness writes, “he brooded over his own defects and difficulties. He was a fierce critic of failings, especially those of honesty, in others. He came to write a book whose main point (he said himself) was an ethical one. What had the foundations of mathematics in common with propensities like these?” (2005, 77, see also Shields 1993, 1).

  8. 8.

    All abbreviations given above.

  9. 9.

    Z §447. His target is always “a philosophical trouble… an obsession, which once removed it seems impossible that it should ever have had power over us. It seems trivial” (AWL 98, see also CV 11, 48, LC 28, RFM 137, 272, PG 169, RPPI §65, §378, §380, §417, §751, §1015, §1074, PI §§105–6, §§435–6).

  10. 10.

    Malcolm 2001, 93–4, see also ibid., 51–2; Monk 1990, 506–7; McGuinness 2005, 192; Rhees 1984, 77, 94, 172–3, 186; PPO 209, 241; CV 19, 38–9.

  11. 11.

    LRKM 57–8. In 1937, while writing the first part of Philosophical Investigations, he wrote, “but if I am to be REALLY saved, − what I need is certainty – not wisdom, dreams or speculation – and this certainty is faith. And faith is faith in what is needed by my heart, my soul, not my speculative intelligence. For it is my soul with its passions, as it were with its flesh and blood, that has to be saved, not my abstract mind” (CV 33, see also CV 17, 53, 56, 61, 62, RFM 132, 302, PPO 217; Fann 1967, 64, 91, 94). One of his intellectual heroes, Karl Krauss, felt the same way (Janik and Toulmin 1973, 69, 81).

  12. 12.

    CV 16, see also Klagge 2001, 27–8, 177; McManus 2004, 178; Johannessen et al. 1994, 172; McGuinness 2005, 57.

  13. 13.

    Engelmann 1967, 143.

  14. 14.

    T 3.331, 5.132, 5.451–5.452, 5.535, NB 104.

  15. 15.

    See my Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein and Heidegger. MIT Press, 2012; and “Disintegrating Bugbears: Heidegger and Wittgenstein on Basic Laws of Thought.” In Wittgenstein and Heidegger: Pathways and Provocations. Eds. David Egan, Stephen Reynolds, and Aaron Wendland. New York: Routledge, 2013.

  16. 16.

    For example: philosophical questions “are bent, not on increasing an identical stock of propositions, but instead on bringing the one questioning, in his being, to a being and domain of matters…. In this type of questioning, the possibility exists that the answer is an answer precisely when it understands how to disappear in the right way” (Heidegger 2005, 55–6). I take it that the similarity with the Tractarian ladder to be thrown away once claimed is obvious. On Heidegger’s view of philosophical questions and answers, see my “Strange Questions: The Question of the Question in Later Heidegger,” unpublished.

  17. 17.

    See Nietzsche: “whatever has value in our world now does not have value in itself, according to its nature—nature is always value-less, but has been given value at some time, as a present—and it was we who gave and bestowed it. Only we have created the world that concerns man!—But precisely this knowledge we lack” (1974, §301). Or Sartre: “the existentialist… finds it extremely embarrassing that God does not exist, for there disappears with Him all possibility of finding values in an intelligible heaven…. It is nowhere written that ‘the good’ exists, that one must be honest or must not lie, since we are now upon the plane where there are only men” (in Solomon 2005, 211).

  18. 18.

    Thomas Sheehan (2001), for instance, argues that what he calls the existentialist paradigm of Heidegger interpretation was the initial reception, but it was corrected as more texts became available. Lawrence Vogel (1994) considers the existentialist reading of Being and Time “plausible,” by which he means that “a thoughtful reading of the text might yield [such an] interpretation” (7), although he ultimately rejects it (47–8), largely, it seems to me, on the basis of later Heideggerian texts rather than Being and Time itself. See also Aho 2003.

  19. 19.

    BT 168/130, 344/297–8. “Dasein faces himself when he accepts that it is up to him to establish his own priorities in life: that there is no blueprint for how one ought to lead one’s life as a whole” (Vogel 1994, 23, see also Caputo 1988, 258).

  20. 20.

    Authentic Being-one’s-Self does not rest upon an exceptional condition of the subject, a condition that has been detached from the ‘they’; it is rather an existentiell modification of the ‘they’” (BT 168/130).

  21. 21.

    Others have made similar claims about Heidegger. See for instance Olafson: “In Heidegger’s analysis of Dasein, or human existence, there can be no question of an authentication of our projects by reference to preexisting rules or truths of any kind…. Views of this kind would not seem to afford a basis for ethical distinctions among the various kinds of choices that human beings make; but it is apparent from Heidegger’s account that an existential ethic would recognize at least one positive virtue. This would be a capability for living in full awareness and acceptance of one’s ontological situation…. Typically, human beings seek to suppress such self-knowledge… by an illusory sense of there being determinate and preestablished norms that define the individual’s situation and his action for him” (Olafson 1973, 29–30). He calls this virtue “ontological courage” (ibid.). Marjorie Grene writes that for existentialists, “the ultimate value is honesty rather than freedom” (1959, 143).

  22. 22.

    PPO 23, see also PPO 93, 97, 113, 125, 139, 153, 157, 185, 193, 205, 207, 213, 225, 231, PhR 7, PI x, Klagge 2001, 9–10, 163; Rhees 1984, 127, 138; Fann 1967, 74; Johannessen et al. 1994, 173.

  23. 23.

    One example is the time he beat himself up and apologized deeply to friends for not correcting the impression that his parentage was ¼ Jewish and ¾ Christian rather than the reverse proportion (PPO 281, Rhees 1984, 35, 120; Monk 1990, 412). Fania Pascal writes that his less than forthcoming account of having struck a girl in the Austrian school he briefly taught at became a “crisis…burdening his conscience forever” (Rhees 1984, 37–8). Note that it is his not being fully forthcoming, not the act of striking a child, that haunts him.

  24. 24.

    PPO 153, see also PPO 295, 301–3, McGuinness 2012, 233, 326, 332; Monk 1990, 317.

  25. 25.

    Many of his contemporaries comment on the importance of honesty to him. Russell wrote that “no one could be more sincere than Wittgenstein or more destitute of the false politeness that interferes with truth…. He is always absolutely frank…. He is not a flatterer but a man of transparent and absolute sincerity” (quoted in McGuinness 2005, 102). Brian McGuinness writes, “Wittgenstein wanted nothing but honesty” (McGuinness 2012, 4) and says that he was “fiercely concerned about any departure from the truth even for the sake of giving pleasure to others” (McGuinness 2005, 48). Fania Pascal writes that she “never met anyone more incapable of telling a lie” (Rhees 1984, 37). Von Wright speaks of Wittgenstein’s “unconditional veracity and candour” (Johannessen et al. 1994, 165, see also Fann 1967, 57; Malcolm 2001, 26, 60).

  26. 26.

    PPO 125, see also PPO 105, 133, 141, 201, 221.

  27. 27.

    Rhees 1984, 174, see also Johannessen et al. 1994, 172. “No one can speak the truth; if he has still not mastered himself. He cannot speak it;--but not because he is not clever enough yet. The truth can be spoken only by someone who is already at home in it” 9CV 35).

  28. 28.

    McGuinness 2012, 367. “You can’t think decently if you don’t want to hurt yourself” (Monk 1990, 475, see also ibid., 278, 366–7, PPO 297, Malcolm 2001, 93–4).

  29. 29.

    CV 26, see also CV 77, Monk 1990, 371.

  30. 30.

    PPO 155, 181, 211, 247, 404. Wittgenstein praises G.E. Moore for “his love of truth and freedom from vanity” (Fann 1967, 23, see also PPO 301, Malcolm 2001, 56) and says of William James, “that is what makes him a good philosopher. He was a real human being” (Fann 1967, 68).

  31. 31.

    CV 52. “One might say: Genius is talent exercised with courage” (CV 38, see also CV 44, Conv 55). He also proclaims as a general motto: “courage, not cleverness” (CV 38).

  32. 32.

    PI §109. Compare with Heidegger’s claim that attempts to accurately describe Dasein “should capture the Being of this entity, in spite of this entity’s own tendency to cover things up” (BT 359/311, see also BT 61/36, 96/67, 151/115, 155/119, 167/129, 255/212, 265/222, 285/241, 428/376, 439/387, HCT 29, 87, 128–30, 136).

  33. 33.

    As Fania Pascal, one of the recipients, writes, “to make a confession must have appealed to Wittgenstein as the most natural way of relieving his mind of an oppressive burden of guilt” (Rhees 1984, 36, see also ibid., 120; McGuinness 2005, 274).

  34. 34.

    PPO 133, see also Klagge 2001, 177.

  35. 35.

    Rhees 1984, xvi. McGuinness says that “writing was a necessity for him… and its fundamental purpose, as far as he could see it, was to reach a true understanding of, to come to terms with, his life as it actually was: to settle accounts with himself” (2005, 57).

  36. 36.

    AWL 13. “We make many utterances whose role in the investigation we do not understand. For it isn’t as though everything we say has a conscious purpose; our tongues just keep going. Our thoughts run in established routines, we pass automatically from one thought to another according to techniques we have learned. And now comes the time for us to survey what we have said” (CV 64, see also LWL 22, 50, 53, 84, 101, LLVC 77, 153, 248, AWL 43, PG 50, 62–63, 80, 85, 96, BB 15, 25, PO 202, 456, RPPII §417, §603, §736, Z §86, §111, §118, Conv 23–25, RFM 210, LFM 61, 183, PI §150, §199, LC 68, OC §46). For more on this connection with Heidegger, see Braver 2012, 23–34.

  37. 37.

    LWPPI §41, see also LWPPII 46, 86, BB 9–10, 62, PO 214, 222, 235, RFM 75, RPPI §65, RPPII §235, LFM 18, 21; Pears 1988, 426–7; Kenny 1973, 164.

  38. 38.

    LWL 25, see also LWL 45, AWL 77–78, BB 26, 40–1, PhR 82, 172–73, RFM 115, RPPI §498, §824, PI II.xi p. 167; Fann 1967, 47; Fogelin 1995, 109.

  39. 39.

    “What I do think essential is carrying out the work of clarification with COURAGE: otherwise it becomes just a clever game” (CV 19).

  40. 40.

    AWL 61, see also RPPI §889, PI §164, LFM 137.

  41. 41.

    HCT 86, see also HCT 72, 81–5, 112, BT 51–5/28–31, 60/36; Dreyfus and Hall 1992, 96. Both even employ the same metaphor of a symptom of a deeper illness to depict their target (RPPI §292, BT 52/29, HCT 80), as does Austin (1979, 105).

  42. 42.

    PI §435, see also PI §92, §126, §559. Baker and Hacker connect Wittgenstein’s anti-metaphysics with his methodological commitment to description: “philosophy is purely descriptive…. Explanation would be possible only if it made sense to get behind these rules and supply a deeper foundation…. But there is no behind…. This insight shapes the whole of Wittgenstein’s philosophy” (1985, 22).

  43. 43.

    T 6.45. In one of his rare references to the history of philosophy, Wittgenstein acknowledges the long pedigree of this aspiration: “men have always had a presentiment that there must be a realm in which the answers to questions are symmetrically combined—a priori—to form a self-contained system” (T 5.4541). At this point in his career, he does not reject this quest, believing that he has succeeded in it: “that utterly simple thing, which we have to formulate here, is not a likeness of the truth, but the truth itself in its entirety” (T 5.5563).

  44. 44.

    PI §352, see also PI §222, RFM 45–6, 64, 266–9, PO 94, 435, PG 481, LFM 131–2; Wright 1980, 220, 275–6, 312, 372; Baker and Hacker 1985, 236; Dummett 1978, 185.

  45. 45.

    LFM 103–4, see also LFM 137–9, PI §426, PI II.xi, p. 185, 192; PhR 149, 212, 237, PO 94, LC 71, RPPI §139, Edwards 1990, 139.

  46. 46.

    PO 408, see also PO 73. Wittgenstein’s interlocutors worry about cognitive nihilism: “but what becomes of logic now? Its rigour seems to be giving way here” (PI §108, see also OC §108, LC 64). Michael Dummett appears to subscribe to this view: “if Wittgenstein were right, it appears to me that communication would be in constant danger of simply breaking down” (1978, 176–7).

  47. 47.

    RFM 199, see also RFM 102–3, 205, 323.

  48. 48.

    PI §211, see also PI §219, §228, §289, §292, §323, §377, PI §485, AWL 5, OC §358, PO 381, 395, PG 47, RFM 46, 326, 330, 333, 337, 350–51, Z §314, LFM 199, 234, 289, RPPII §314, §402, §453.

  49. 49.

    PI §§105–6, see also PI §107, §§435–6, PhR 52, 61, 188; Harries 1968, 285.

  50. 50.

    Rhees 1984, 82, see also 105.

  51. 51.

    CV 18. “At the end of my lecture on ethics I spoke in the first person. I think that this is something very essential. Here there is nothing to be stated any more; all I can do is to step forth as an individual and speak in the first person” (LWVC 117).

  52. 52.

    He once called Kierkegaard “‘by far the most profound thinker’ of the nineteenth century” (Rhees 1984, xvi), and discusses Kierkegaard’s method of indirect communication in his diaries (PPO 83, 131).

  53. 53.

    Or, if we are cynical, like Jean-Baptiste Clamence in Camus’ The Fall. I am grateful to Onur Karamercan for this suggestion.

  54. 54.

    “One must reveal the source of error, otherwise hearing the truth won’t do any good. The truth cannot force its way in when something else is occupying its place. To convince someone of the truth, it is not enough to state it, but rather one must find the path from error to truth” (PO 119).

  55. 55.

    “What the other person acknowledges is the analogy I am proposing to him as the source of his thought” (PO 165, see also PO 119, PI §464, §524, AWL 90).

  56. 56.

    PPO 301, see also PPO 366. Wittgenstein often said this about G.E. Moore, a man whose mind he didn’t respect but whose character—especially his honesty and humility—he revered.

Abbreviations

AWL:

Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1932–1935, ed. Alice Ambrose

BB:

The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the ‘Philosophical Investigations’

BT:

Being and Time

Conv:

Wittgenstein Conversations 1949–1951

CV:

Culture and Value

HCT:

History of the Concept of Time

LC:

Lectures & Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief

LFM:

Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics: Cambridge 1939

LRKM:

Letters to Russell, Keynes and Moore

LWL:

Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1930–1932, ed. Desmond Lee

LWPPI or II:

Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology (Two Volumes)

LWVC:

Ludwig Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations recorded by Friedrich Waismann

OC:

On Certainty

PG:

Philosophical Grammar

PhR:

Philosophical Remarks

PI:

Philosophical Investigations, 3rd Rev. Ed. 2001

PO:

Philosophical Occasions 1912–1951

PPO:

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Public and Private Occasions

RFM:

Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Rev. Ed.

RPPI or II:

Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology (Two Volumes)

T:

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus

Z:

Zettel

Bibliography

  • Aho, Kevin. 2003. “Why Heidegger is not an Existentialist: Interpreting Authenticity and Historicity in Being and Time.” Florida Philosophical Review. Vol. III, Issue 2, Winter 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. 1979. Philosophical Papers 3rd ed. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Gordon P. and P.M.S. Hacker 1985. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar, and Necessity. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor. 2002. Wittgenstein, Rules & Institutions. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braver, Lee. 2012. Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein and Heidegger. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. “Disintegrating Bugbears: Heidegger and Wittgenstein on Basic Laws of Thought.” In Wittgenstein and Heidegger: Pathways and Provocations. Ed. David Egan, Stephen Reynolds, and Aaron Wendland. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, John. 1988. Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic Project. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, Stanley. 1982. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Harrison Hall, eds. 1992. Heidegger: A Critical Reader. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael. 1978. Truth and Other Enigmas. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, James C. 1990. The Authority of Language: Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Threat of Philosophical Nihilism. University of Southern Florida Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelmann, Paul. 1967. Letters From Ludwig Wittgenstein With a Memoir. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fann, K. T. 1967. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Man and his Philosophy, Dell Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogelin, Robert. 1995. Wittgenstein. 2nd ed. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grene, Marjorie. 1959. Introduction to Existentialism. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harries, Karsten. 1968. “Wittgenstein and Heidegger: The Relationship of the Philosopher to Language.” The Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 2, no. 4, pp. 281-291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. History of the Concept of Time. Trans. Theodore Kisiel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Introduction to Phenomenological Research. Trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Janik, Allan and Stephen Toulmin. 1973. Wittgenstein’s Vienna. Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannessen, Kjell S., Rolf Larsen, and Knut Olav Åmås, eds. 1994. Wittgenstein and Norway. Oslo: Solum Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klagge, James C. 2001. Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, Anthony. 1973. Wittgenstein. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuinness, Brian. 2012. Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents 1911-1951, 4th ed. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Young Wittgenstein: Wittgenstein’s Life 1889-1921. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McManus, Denis. 2004. Wittgenstein and Scepticism. Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, Norman. 2001. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, Ray. 1990. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1974. The Gay Science. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olafson, Frederick A. 1973. Ethics and Twentieth Century Thought. Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pears, David. 1987. The False Prison: A Study of the Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy Volume 1. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. The False Prison: A Study of the Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy Volume 2. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Paradox and Platitude in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rhees, Rush. 1984. Recollections of Wittgenstein. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheehan, Thomas. 2001. “A Paradigm Shift In Heidegger Research.” Continental Philosophy Review 34 (2):183-202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shields, Philip R. 1993. Logic and Sin in the Writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sluga, Hans D., and David G. Stern. 1996. The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert, ed. 2005. Existentialism. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, David G. 1996. “The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy.” In Sluga and Stern 1996, 442-76.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Teghrarian, Souren, Anthony Serafini, and Edward M. Cook. 1990. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Symposium on the Centennial of His Birth. Longwood Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Travis, Charles. 2006. Thought’s Footing: Themes in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, Lawrence. 1994. The Fragile We: Ethical Implications Of Heidegger’s "Being and Time." Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G.H. 1984. Wittgenstein. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1980a. Culture and Value. Trans. Peter Winch. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982a. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume One: Preliminary Studies for Part 2 of “Philosophical Investigations.” Ed. G. H. von Wright and Heikki Nyman. Trans. C. G. Luckhardt and Maximilian A. E. Aue. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume Two: The Inner and the Outer. Ed. G. H. von Wright and Heikki Nyman. Trans. C. G. Luckhardt and Maximilian A. E. Aue. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967. Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Ed. Cyril Barrett. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977a. Letters to Russell, Keynes and Moore, 2nd ed. Ed. G.H. von Wright. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969a. On Certainty. Ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright. Trans. Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: Harper Torchbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. Philosophical Investigations. 3rd ed., rev. trans. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Madsen: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1975a. Philosophical Remarks. Ed. Rush Rhees. Transl. Raymond Hargreaves and Roger White. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Rev. ed. Ed. G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. M. Anscombe. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980b. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I. Ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980d. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume II. Ed. G. H. von Wright and Heikki Nyman. Trans. C. G. Luckhardt and Maximilian A. E. Aue. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982b. Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1932-1935, ed. Alice Ambrose. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. Zettel. Ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969b. The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the ‘Philosophical Investigations’. Madsen: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1975b. Philosophical Remarks. Ed. Rush Rhees. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1976. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics: Cambridge 1939. Ed. Cora Diamond. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977b. Remarks on Color. Ed. G.E.M. Anscombe. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. Ludwig Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations recorded by Friedrich Waismann. Oxford: Basil Blackwell Publisher Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980c. Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1930–1932. Ed. Desmond Lee. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Crispin. 1980. Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lee Braver .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Braver, L. (2022). An Ethics of Courage and Honesty in Wittgenstein and Heidegger. In: Rogove, J., D’Oriano, P. (eds) Heidegger and his Anglo-American Reception. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 119. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-05817-2_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics