Skip to main content

Intellectual Virtues, Epistemic Democracy, and the Wisdom of “the People”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Engaging Populism

Abstract

Epistemic democrats argue that democratic governance is justified in part by superior epistemic performance. Although recent work on the subject has engaged formal models and some empirical evidence, epistemic democrats have yet to engage the intellectual virtue literature. In this chapter, I explore this possibility, and pursue two theses. The first thesis, what I call the Obvious Conclusion, contends that intellectual virtues improve the epistemic functioning of a democracy. Although there are good reasons to think this, the Obvious Conclusion admits of complexity and involves some important caveats. Second, certain kinds of partisan populist movements, what I call “Manichean populisms,” can be corrosive of those institutions necessary for the cultivation and sustenance of intellectual virtues. Because of this, Manichean populisms are often detrimental to the health of democratic institutions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    If greater specificity is desired, the scope of “relevant to policymaking” could be restricted to policies impacting human rights and/or human well-being. Such specificity has advantages but also raises issues—environmental well-being, for instance, is left out of such a definition.

  2. 2.

    It might be thought that SEP-N is simply a normative criterion and not an epistemic one, but the premise here is that the identification of correct norms for a polity is, at least in part, epistemic in character, especially in the case of identification of proximate goals. One need not be a moral realist to suppose this, as long as there can be identified polity level norms, some of which are better than others.

  3. 3.

    I leave for now the definition of epistemic judgment open, but I take it to include judgments concerning the truth or falsity of a proposition, the likelihood that a given belief is true, the decision to not completely discount a contrasting belief, the judgment that an argument is reasonably strong, the judgment that some argument is not a defeater to a currently held commitment, the judgment that some proposal is worthy of further investigation, and so on.

  4. 4.

    It might be thought that Philip Tetlock’s (2005) study of policy experts would apply here. Tetlock found that experts in fields such as political science and economics typically performed much worse in predicting political and economic events than simply relying on existing regression analyses typically published in scientific papers. While such experts performed better in their predictions than untrained undergraduates, they were not significantly different than well-read amateurs. Tetlock’s analysis is important, but it does not account for the presence or absence of intellectual virtues, and it focuses only on prediction (forecasting) rather than (say) judgments of what counts as good or right action for a community. In the case of forecasting, virtues may or may not be necessary in particular cases, but they are also clearly not sufficient to successfully forecast. Indeed, the intellectually humble scholar would be one who would refuse to forecast when unable to do so, a character trait that might have been lacking in Tetlock’s population.

  5. 5.

    Much more could be said about the relation of intellectual virtues to normative political judgment. Any given individual will have intellectual virtues developed to varying degrees, and any two individuals may possess different intellectual virtues. Although we might expect that such differences disappear at the population level in a way that contributes to the wisdom of crowd, this might not hold in all cases. Different professions and cultural institutions may lend themselves to the development of different intellectual virtues and vices, and these differences may appear at the regional if not necessary national level.

  6. 6.

    As an example, the 6th Wave of the World Values Survey asks individuals to what extent they trust individuals belonging to another religion. In Sweden 75% affirm that they “Trust Completely” or “Trust Somewhat,” compared to only 35% in Turkey. https://www.worldvaluessurvey.org/WVSDocumentationWV6.jsp.

References

  • Achen, Christopher H., and Larry M. Bartels. 2016. Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alemán, Eduardo, and Yeaji Kim. 2015. The democratizing effect of education. Research & Politics 2 (4): 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2006. The epistemology of democracy. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3 (1): 8–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1951. The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Harvest Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1998. Politics. Translated by Ernest Barker and R.F. Stalley. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, Kenneth. 1963. Social choice and individual values. 2nd ed. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barro, Robert, and Johng Wha Lee. 2013. A new data set of educational attainment in the world, 1950–2010. Journal of Development Economics 104: 184–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castanho Silva, Bruno, Federico Vegetti, and Levente Littvay. 2017. The elite is up to something: Exploring the relation between populism and belief in conspiracy theories. Swiss Political Science Review 23 (4): 423–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1986. An epistemic conception of democracy. Ethics 97 (1): 26–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, Antonio. 1994. Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David M. 2008. Democratic authority: A philosophical framework. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, James S. 2009. When the people speak: Deliberative democracy and public consultation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankish, Keith. 2010. Dual-processing and dual-system theories of reasoning. Philosophy Compass 5 (10): 914–926.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gobet, Fernand, Jean Retschitzki, and Alex de Voogt. 2004. Moves in mind. New York: Psychology Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, Joshua D. 2008. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Moral psychology, Vol 3, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haerpfer, Christian W., Patrick Bernhagen, Ronald F. Inglehart, and Christian Welzel. 2009. Democratization. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, Jonathan. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108: 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, Kirk, and Levente Littvay. 2016. Contemporary US populism in comparative perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, Benedikt, Christian Thoni, and Simon Gäcther. 2008. Antisocial punishment across societies. Science 319: 1362–1366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, Lu, and Scott E. Page. 2004. Groups of diverse problem solvers can outperform groups of high-ability problem solvers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 101 (46): 16385–16389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houlou-Garcia, Antoine. 2017. Sagesse collective, diversité et mauvais usage des mathématiques. Revue française de science politique 67 (5): 899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, Robert A. 2020. The role of populist attitudes in explaining climate change skepticism and support for environmental protection. Environmental Politics 29 (6): 959–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jessen, Nathan. 2019. Populism and conspiracy: A historical synthesis of American countersubversive narratives. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 78 (3): 675–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Jonathan. 2019. Populist politics and vaccine hesitancy in Western Europe: An analysis of national-level data. European Journal of Public Health 29 (3): 512–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, Gary. 1998. Sources of power: How people make decisions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2017. Democratic reason: Politics, collective intelligence, and the rule of the many. Princeton, NJ and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Robert E. Goodin. 2001. Epistemic democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet jury theorem. Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (3): 277–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 2003. Two treatises of government and a letter concerning toleration. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margetts, Helen, Peter John, Scott A. Hale, and Taha Yasseri. 2016. Political turbulence: How social media shape collective action. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, Lilliana. 2018. Uncivil agreement: How politics became our identity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, Hugo, and Hélène Landemore. 2012. Reasoning is for arguing: Understanding the successes and failures of deliberation. Political Psychology 33 (2): 243–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1991. Considerations on representative government. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muchnik, L., S. Aral, and S.J. Taylor. 2013. Social influence bias: A randomized experiment. Science 341 (6146): 647–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mudde, Cas, and Cristóbal Rovira Kaltwasser. 2013. Populism. In The Oxford handbook of political ideologies, ed. Michael Freeden, Lyman Tower Sargent, and Marc Stears. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mutz, Diana C. 2006. Hearing the other side: Deliberative versus participatory democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, Darcia. 2010. Moral complexity: The fatal attraction of truthiness and the importance of mature moral functioning. Perspectives on Psychological Science 5 (2): 163–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newcomb, Theodore Mead. 1943. Personality and social change: Attitude formation in a student community. Dryden, IL: Hinsdale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newcomb, Theodore M., Kathryn E. Koenig, Richard Flacks, and Donald P. Warwick. 1967. Personality and change: Bennington College and its students after twenty-five years. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, Richard. 2003. The geography of thought: How Asians and Westerners think differently … and why. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pérez, Efrén O., and Margit Tavits. 2017. Language shapes people’s time perspective and support for future-oriented policies. American Journal of Political Science 61 (3): 715–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Gregory R. 2015. Can one love the distant other? Empathy, affiliation, and cosmopolitanism. Philosophy, Theology, and the Sciences 2 (1): 4–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Scientific practice and democratic virtues. In Virtue and the practice of science, ed. Celia Deane-Drummond, Thomas A. Stapleford, and Darcia Narvaez. South Bend, IN: Center for Theology, Science, and Human Flourishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Beyond the two cultures: Democratic virtues and the case for a model of mutuality. Administrative Theory & Praxis 42 (3): 279–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert D. 2000. Bowling alone: The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert D., Robert Leonardi, and Raffaella Nanetti. 1993. Making democracy work: Civic traditions in modern Italy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, William H. 1988. Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1987. On the social contract. Translated by Donald A. Cress. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schkade, David, Cass R. Sunstein, and Reid Hastie. 2010. When deliberation produces extremism. Critical Review 22 (2–3): 227–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sirin, Cigdem V., Nicholas A. Valentino, and José D. Villalobos. 2016. Group empathy theory: The effect of group empathy on US intergroup attitudes and behavior in the context of immigration threats. The Journal of Politics 78 (3): 893–908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sternberg, Robert J., and Karin Sternberg. 2009. Cognitive psychology. 6th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tessman, Lisa. 2005. Burdened virtues: Virtue ethics for liberatory struggles. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, Philip E. 2005. Expert political judgment: How good is it? How can we know? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, Mark E., and Hilary Pearse, eds. 2008. Designing deliberative democracy: The British Columbia citizens’ assembly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregory R. Peterson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Peterson, G.R. (2022). Intellectual Virtues, Epistemic Democracy, and the Wisdom of “the People”. In: Peterson, G.R., Berhow, M.C., Tsakiridis, G. (eds) Engaging Populism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-05785-4_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics