Skip to main content

Due Process as a Subject of Special Jurisprudence. The Checklist and Flexible Models of Procedural Due Process

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Understanding Due Process in Non-Criminal Matters

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 97))

  • 190 Accesses

Abstract

The answer to the question of which procedure is provided by the right to due process may have a critical impact on how accessible the civil justice is. With this purpose, in this chapter, first I describe procedural due process as a complex jurisprudential concept and, second, I introduce the analytical framework I will use in what follows with the purpose of studying how procedural due process it is conceived in different jurisdictions: the checklist model and the flexible model. Using an ideal type approach to explain different conceptions of the right to a fair trial from a practical perspective, it will prove to be useful to move to an analysis with normative character on how to reconcile the requirements of procedural fairness with social demands for justice, as expressed by the access to justice movement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Miller (1977), p. 3. See also: Galligan (1996), p. 166.

  2. 2.

    See: Fuller and Winston (1978).

  3. 3.

    See: Tyler (1994).

  4. 4.

    See: Mashaw (1981).

  5. 5.

    Bone (2003), pp. 508–516.

  6. 6.

    Regarding courts role against public authorities’ arbitrariness, see: Scanlon (1977), pp. 94–106.

  7. 7.

    Dworkin (1985), p. 93.

  8. 8.

    According to Dworkin, to determine the procedural rights to which parties are entitled is relevant the moral harm beyond the bare harm, which are related to gains and losses which emerges from utilitarian calculations. That is why its determination would be a matter of principle not policy, because it is a question of an entitlement to a right to win a lawsuit if the law is on the party’s side, even if the society overall loses thereby. See: Dworkin (1985), pp. 89, 92–96.

  9. 9.

    See: Weber (1949), pp. 91–92.

  10. 10.

    Sunstein (2006).

  11. 11.

    Bone (2010), p. 1015.

  12. 12.

    Bone (2003), p. 515.

  13. 13.

    Bone (2003), p. 487.

  14. 14.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 620.

  15. 15.

    Following Ronald Dworkin account for the differences between legal principles and rules. See: Dworkin (1967), pp. 22–29; Dworkin (1977), pp. 22–31.

  16. 16.

    Kennedy (1976), p. 1687.

  17. 17.

    Kennedy (1976), p. 1688.

  18. 18.

    Kennedy (1976), p. 1690.

  19. 19.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 619.

  20. 20.

    On interpretive choices, see: Vermeule (2000), p. 82.

  21. 21.

    Between the relation among the two in its modern conceptions, see: Eskridge (2013).

  22. 22.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 629.

  23. 23.

    Kennedy (1976), p. 1688.

  24. 24.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 629.

  25. 25.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 631.

  26. 26.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 632.

  27. 27.

    Dworkin (1967), pp. 23–29.

  28. 28.

    See: Alexy (2014), p. 68.

  29. 29.

    Braithwaite (2002), p. 50.

  30. 30.

    Raz (1972), p. 838. Notwithstanding, the main difference between rules and principles according to Raz is about the roles each type of norm serve in a legal system. See Raz (1972), pp. 839–843.

  31. 31.

    Dworkin (1967), p. 27; Alexy (2014), pp. 70–79. Raz points out that this conflict solving criteria proposed by Dworkin as defining character of principles. See: Raz (1972), p. 833. Notwithstanding is not my purpose to solve this issue here, and I will use this character to try to define my analytical models, I believe it is important to acknowledge its limitations.

  32. 32.

    Dworkin (1986), p. 52.

  33. 33.

    Regarding, value oriented theories of procedural due process, see: Saphire (1978).

  34. 34.

    See: Mashaw (1981).

  35. 35.

    Redish and Marshals (1986), pp. 474–475. See also: Dworkin (1985), p. 90.

  36. 36.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 633.

  37. 37.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 634.

  38. 38.

    Sunstein (2006), p. 634.

  39. 39.

    Kadish (1957), p. 341.

  40. 40.

    Kennedy (1976), p. 1689.

  41. 41.

    Braithwaite (2002), pp. 52–60.

References

  • Alexy R (2014) Teoría de los derechos fundamentales (trans: Carlos Bernal). Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Bone R (2010) Procedure, participation, rights. Boston Univ Law Rev 90:1011–1028

    Google Scholar 

  • Bone R (2003) Agreeing to fair process: the problem with contractarian theories of procedural fairness. Boston Univ Law Rev 83:485–552

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite J (2002) Rules and principles: a theory of legal certainty. AJLP 27:47–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1967) The model of rules. Univ Chicago Law Rev 35:14–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1985) A matter of principle. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) The law’s empire. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eskridge W (2013) The new textualism and normative canons. Columbia Law Rev 113:531–592

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller L, Winston K (1978) The forms and limits of adjudication. Harv Law Rev 92(2):353–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galligan D (1996) Due process and fair procedures. A study of administrative procedures. Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadish S (1957) Methodology and criteria in due process adjudication. A survey and criticism. Yale Law J 66(3):319–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (1976) Form and substance in private law adjudication. Harv Law Rev 89(8):1685–1778

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mashaw J (1981) Administrative due process: the quest for a dignitary theory. Boston Univ Law Rev 61:885–931

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller C (1977) The forest of due process of law. In: Pennock R, Chapman J (eds) Due process, Nomos, vol XVIII. New York University Press, New York, pp 3–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1972) Legal principles and the limits of law. Yale Law J 8(5):823–854

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redish M, Marshall L (1986) Adjudicatory independence and the values of procedural due process. Yale Law J 95(3):455–503

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saphire R (1978) Specifying due process values: toward a more responsive approach to procedural protection. Univ Pa Law Rev 127(1):111–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (1977) Due process. In: Pennock R, Chapman J (eds) Due process, Nomos, vol XVIII. New York University Press, New York, pp 94–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C (2006) Two conceptions of procedural fairness. Soc Res 73(2):619–646

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyler T (1994) Psychological models of the justice motive: antecedents of distributive and procedural justice. J Pers Soc Psychol 67(5):850–863

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vermeule A (2000) Interpretive choice. New York Univ Law Rev 75(1):74–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1949) The methodology of the social sciences (trans: Shils E). The Free Press, Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lillo Lobos, R. (2022). Due Process as a Subject of Special Jurisprudence. The Checklist and Flexible Models of Procedural Due Process. In: Understanding Due Process in Non-Criminal Matters. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 97. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-95534-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-95534-2_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-95533-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-95534-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics