Skip to main content

Boole’s Untruth Tables: The Formal Conditions of Meaning Before the Emergence of Propositional Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Logic in Question

Part of the book series: Studies in Universal Logic ((SUL))

Abstract

This paper studies what can reasonably be regarded as truth-table devices in one of Boole’s late manuscripts as a way of addressing Boole’s relation to modern propositional logic. A careful investigation of the divergences between those table devices and our current conception of truth tables offers an opportunity to reassess the singularity of Boole’s logical system, especially concerning the relation between its linguistic and mathematical aspects. The paper explores Boole’s conception of the compositional structure of symbolic expressions, the genesis of table devices from his method of development into normal forms, and the non-logical origin of the constants 0 and 1 as dual terms. Boole’s system of logic is in this way shown to be chiefly concerned with the problem of the formal interpretability conditions of symbolic expressions, rather than with the truth conditions of logical propositions.

This paper was supported by the Formal Epistemology—the Future Synthesis project, in the framework of the Praemium Academicum program of the Czech Academy of Sciences, to which I am very much indebted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for instance, Gödel’s recently published 1939 logic course at Notre Dame [1], which constitutes a flawless account of the historical, conceptual, and technical significance of truth tables for the understanding and development of propositional logic.

  2. 2.

    See [11] for Grattan-Guinness’s argument in favor of Shosky’s position.

  3. 3.

    Unlike the rest of the names in this list, Russell’s relation to the Boolean tradition was not direct, but mediated in a decisive way by Peano’s original elaboration, which, in turn, explicitly relies on the formulations of Boole, Schröder and Peirce (see Russell’s [14, §2] and Peano’s [15, §§VII, XII, XVI, XVII, XXI]).

  4. 4.

    For Boole’s temporal interpretation of secondary propositions, see [18].

  5. 5.

    It is hardly surprising, from this point of view, that the connection of secondary propositions with the theory of probabilities, which occupies more than a third of LT, appears to the authors as “obscure” [7, p. 414]. For a treatment of Boole’s theory of probabilities, see [19, 20].

  6. 6.

    See the introduction to Sect. 3 below.

  7. 7.

    Extracts from this manuscript were published in 1952 by Rhees in [21], but the editor, manifestly interested above all in Boole’s perspective on the problem of reasoning, skipped the section containing the “tables” in question, mentioning only that “[t]he logical symbolism is the same as in the Laws of Thought” [21, p. 238]. The publication of the entire document had then to await Grattan-Guinness and Bornet’s edition of Boole’s manuscripts in 1997 [22], the same year as Shosky’s paper.

  8. 8.

    Which borrows the form from tables such as (1), as we can infer from the first column of the first of the three tables in the manuscript.

  9. 9.

    For a standard presentation of Boolean algebras and rings, see, for example, [23].

  10. 10.

    Reference to a larger number of works following this approach can be found in [27].

  11. 11.

    Other works in the same direction include [27, 29].

  12. 12.

    See, for instance, [28, p. 178] and [19, p. 147].

  13. 13.

    See, for instance, [2, p. 167].

  14. 14.

    See, for instance, [3, § 5.101].

  15. 15.

    For Gödel’s use of truth tables for the decidability of propositional calculus, see [1, p. 23].

  16. 16.

    See [1, § 1.1.8].

  17. 17.

    For an interesting study putting forward the notion of expression in Lagrange, see [30].

  18. 18.

    This new formal character is here given by the mathematical notion of analytical form, related to the formal use of series expansions, rather than by the traditional “argumenta in forma” of classical logic. For the formal use of series in 18th and early nineteenth century mathematics, see [31, 32].

  19. 19.

    Boole is clear about this point: “We might justly assign it as the definitive character of a true Calculus, that it is a method resting upon the employment of Symbols, whose laws of combination are known and general, and whose results admit of a consistent interpretation.” [16, p. 4].

  20. 20.

    See [17, XI, § 5].

  21. 21.

    For the reduction of hypotheticals to categoricals, see [33].

  22. 22.

    As in this passage, in which truth and falsehood are said to concern only “a branch” of logic: “A denial must be a denial of the truth of a proposition and there is a branch of Logic […] which relates to propositions in their special attributes of truth and falsehood and in the relations flowing from those attributes” [22, p. 59].

  23. 23.

    Boole’s modifications in the treatment of secondary propositions in LT do not significantly change this decisive feature of his approach. See [17, p. 169 sqq.].

  24. 24.

    Indeed, the meaning of uninterpretable algebraic expressions, such as \(\sqrt {-1}\) or non-convergent series expansions, was a common concern for the English algebraists and occasioned the originality of their approach. For an extensive treatment of this problem in the most general terms, see Babbage’s [34].

  25. 25.

    See, for instance, [16, p. 4–5], [17, p. 28, 47], [22, p. 67 sqq.].

  26. 26.

    This reliance on signs is what justifies Boole’s late definition of logic as “noetic” instead of “ostensive” [22, p. 72]. For a condensed overview of Boole’s late articulation of the problems of interpretability and signs, see Rhees’s introduction to [21], especially p. 17 sqq.

  27. 27.

    For all this, see, for example, [31, 32].

  28. 28.

    For example: “Let ϕ(xy) = x(1 − y), then ϕ(10) = 1, ϕ(11) = 0, ϕ(01) = 0, ϕ(00) = 0” [16, p. 74].

  29. 29.

    This definition is, as we now know, full of subtlety and danger. However, Boole adroitly avoids defining 1 as the class of all classes and prevents the confusion between both by attributing to them different semiological status: in Boole’s own terms, while 1 is a “symbol” (as much as x or y), classes are referred to by “letters” such as X or Y. See [16, p. 15].

  30. 30.

    Boole will further associate the fact that the fundamental law of logic is of second degree to the dual nature of logical symbols (since from x 2 = x we can have x(1 − x) = 0, which he interprets as the law of contradiction). Incidentally, this offers him occasion to consider the possibility of the fundamental law being of higher degree, thus explicitly envisaging the existence of logics whose terms would accept more than two possibilities [17, p. 49–50]. However, Boole never explicitly relates the degree and factorization of that fundamental equation to the duality of 0 and 1, which could have been made through their status as roots of that equation.

  31. 31.

    Interestingly, Boole remarks that the first of those two results can lead to 1 = 0, which he interprets as the “nonexistence of the logical Universe,” and indicate the attempt “to unite contradictory Propositions in a single equation” [16, p. 65].

  32. 32.

    Boole explicitly associates the whole procedure with that of solving linear differential equations, “arbitrary elective symbols in the one, occupying the place of arbitrary constants in the other” [16, p.70].

  33. 33.

    For instance, Boole tried to confer a logical signification on the uncomfortable symbols \(\frac {0}{0}\) and \(\frac {1}{0}\), much like in the case of 0 and 1, by associating them with indefiniteness and infinity [17, pp. 90–91]. In the manuscripts he will also refer—no less unconvincingly—to the four coefficients in terms of “logical categories,” now considering \(\frac {1}{0}\) to be the symbol of impossibility [22, pp. 99–100].

  34. 34.

    The text, entitled “On the Foundations of the Mathematical Theory of Logic and on the Philosophical Interpretation of Its Methods and Processes” [22, pp. 63–104], provides a complete overview of his system, insisting on its foundational aspects. It was intended as a preliminary philosophical introduction to the system for the purpose of an application of the theory of probabilities.

  35. 35.

    The presence of this condition can be traced back to MAL, recognizable under the form {ϕ(xy…)}n = ϕ(xy…), which Boole presents as a condition introducing “symmetry into our Calculus” [16, p. 66]. In LT, Boole acknowledges it, under the form V (1 − V ) = 0, as “the condition of interpretability of logical functions,” and devotes a whole chapter to exploring some of its properties [17, p. 93 and ch. X]. In those pages, such a condition inspired, however, a rather convoluted method for reducing every step of a calculation to an interpretable form.

  36. 36.

    For the problem of division in Boole, see [19].

  37. 37.

    In the paragraphs preceding his presentation of the tables, Boole explicitly provides the derivation of conditions for the additive expression [22, p. 92].

References

  1. M. Adzic and K. Dosen. Logic Lectures: Gödel’s Basic Logic Course at Notre Dame. ArXiv e-prints, May 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Emil L. Post. Introduction to a general theory of elementary propositions. American Journal of Mathematics, 43(3):163–185, 1921.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Ludwig Wittgenstein. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Routledge, London-NY, 2001.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Łukasiewicz. Logika dwuwartościowa (two-valued logic). Przeglad Filozoficzny, 23:189–205, 1921.

    Google Scholar 

  5. W. Van Orman Quine. Methods of Logic. Harvard University Press, New York, 1966.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. G.E.M. Anscombe. An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Harper torchbooks: Academy library. Hutchinson University Library, New York, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  7. W.C. Kneale and M. Kneale. The Development of Logic. Clarendon Press, 1971.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. John Shosky. Russell’s use of truth tables. Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies, 17(1), 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Irving Anellis. The genesis of the truth-table device. Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies, 24(1), 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Irving Anellis. Peirce’s truth-functional analysis and the origin of the truth table. History and Philosophy of Logic, 33(1):87–97, 2012.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. I. Grattan-Guinness. Comments on Steven’s review of ‘The Cambridge Companion’ and Anellis on truth tables. Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies, 24(05):185–188, 2004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Irving H. Anellis and Francine F. Abeles. The Historical Sources of Tree Graphs and the Tree Method in the Work of Peirce and Gentzen, pages 35–97. Springer International Publishing, Cham, 2016.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Lewis Carroll. Lewis Carroll’s Symbolic Logic. C.N. Potter Distributed by Crown Publishers, New York, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bertrand Russell. Principles of Mathematics. Routledge, London, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Giuseppe Peano. Selected works of Giuseppe Peano. Allen and Unwin, London, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  16. George Boole. The Mathematical Analysis of Logic : Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. George Boole. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought: On which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Walton and Maberly, London, 1854.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Béatrice Godart-Wendling. The Conceptualization of Time in Boole’s Algebraic Logic, pages 241–255. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, 2000.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Theodore Hailperin. Boole’s logic and probability: a critical exposition from the standpoint of contemporary algebra, logic, and probability theory. North Holland Pub. Co. Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co, Amsterdam, Netherlands, New York, N.Y., U.S.A, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Marie-José Durand-Richard. La réception de la théorie des probabilités de Laplace chez les algébristes anglais 1812–1854). Electronic Journal for History of Probability and Statistics, 8(December 2012):01–28, 2012.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Rush Rhees, editor. Studies in Logic and Probability. Watts & Co., London, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  22. I. Grattan-Guiness and G. Bornet, editors. George Boole: Selected Manuscripts on Logic and its Philosophy. Birkhäuser Basel, Basel, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Steven Givant and Paul Halmos. Introduction to Boolean Algebras. Springer, New York, NY, 2009.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Stanley Jevons. Pure logic or the logic of quality apart from quantity. In Pure Logic and Other Minor Works. MacMillan and Co., London, 1890.

    Google Scholar 

  25. John Corcoran and Susan Wood. Boole’s criteria for validity and invalidity. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 21(4):609–638, 10 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  26. John Corcoran. Aristotle’s Prior Analytics and Boole’s Laws of Thought. History and Philosophy of Logic, 24(4):261–288, 2003.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Frank Markham Brown. George Boole’s Deductive System. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 50(3):303–330, 07 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Theodore Hailperin. Boole’s Algebra Isn’t Boolean Algebra. Mathematics Magazine, 54(4):173–184, 1981.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Stanley Burris. George Boole. In Edward N. Zalta, editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, winter 2014 edition, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Giovanni Ferraro and Marco Panza. Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions and his ideal of purity of method. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 66(2):95–197, Mar 2012.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Giovanni Ferraro. Convergence and formal manipulation in the theory of series from 1730 to 1815. Historia Mathematica, 34(1):62–88, 2007.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Giovanni Ferraro. The rise and development of the theory of series up to the early 1820s. Springer, New York, NY, 2008.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Sriram Nambiar. The Influence of Aristotelian Logic on Boole’s Philosophy of Logic: The Reduction of Hypotheticals to Categoricals, pages 217–239. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, 2000.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Charles Babbage. On the Influence of Signs in Mathematical Reasoning. J. Smith, Cambridge, 1826.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juan Luis Gastaldi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gastaldi, J.L. (2022). Boole’s Untruth Tables: The Formal Conditions of Meaning Before the Emergence of Propositional Logic. In: Béziau, JY., Desclés, JP., Moktefi, A., Pascu, A.C. (eds) Logic in Question. Studies in Universal Logic. Birkhäuser, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-94452-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics