Skip to main content

Libertarian Freedom in an Eternalist World?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Powers, Time and Free Will

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 451))

Abstract

My students sometimes worry that if eternalism is true then they can’t have libertarian freedom. They aren’t alone, as this sentiment is also expressed, albeit typically briefly, by various philosophers. However, somewhat surprisingly, those working within the free will literature have largely had nothing to say about libertarianism’s relationship to time, with this also being similar in the case of those working in the philosophy of time, apart from some work which has mainly focused on nonlibertarian views of freedom. In this short paper I note why I’m currently unconvinced that there’s an incompatibility between eternalism and libertarianism, and in doing so one will see why I think they are compatible.

My thanks to James Read, Robin Le Poidevin, Tim Mawson, Damiano Costa, and an anonymous referee for comments on an earlier draft of this paper. I also wish to acknowledge my students for interesting discussions on this topic, which provided inspiration for writing something on this subject.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For additional references, see Oaklander (1998).

  2. 2.

    Apparently, some have no interest in the matter either, with Koperski writing that ‘Timpe [who specialises in the philosophy of free will] has said that he is not terribly concerned about the metaphysics of time (private conversation).’ (2015, 115).

  3. 3.

    Note that throughout the paper I will speak of time-slices. I do this since I find it easier to think and speak about the block being ‘sliced’ up in this way. One big slice after another. I take it that nothing substantial rests on this, and one can translate my talk into events or entities if one prefers. It may even be that translating this talk into events is preferable since, as my colleague James Read informs me, ‘the Gödel universe isn’t foliable into hypersurfaces of constant time --- but we can still (the thought typically goes) be eternalists about it through thinking about it in terms of events.’ (in personal Correspondence) I let the reader do so if they wish.

  4. 4.

    There might be some slightly harder varieties of eternalism to classify, such as Maudlin’s (2007, ch.4), and perhaps Koons’s (2022), but I take it that the vast majority will fit comfortably into my classification. In any case, what I will largely be concerned with is the claim of ENTITY EVERYWHENISM, and this is one all eternalists seem to embrace.

  5. 5.

    Rather than the other type of incompatibilists, hard determinists, who think agents can’t act freely.

  6. 6.

    One could read Petkov as thinking this, as he writes that four-dimensionalism, by which I take him to mean eternalism, implies that our actions are ‘predetermined’ (2005, 152). Similarly Rietdijk (1966), who seems to think that all time-slices exist, claims that because of this there is no indeterminism, a view Putnam (243–247) also seems to hold. There is a little ambiguity, however, in what both mean when they speak of determinism, with Rietdijk saying that ‘we may conclude that there is determinism (which is, of course, not the same thing as causality)’ (1967, 343). Perhaps then what is meant is not causal determinism, but that events in the future are ‘set’ or what I will call later ‘fixed’, and it is for this reason that they call them determined. However, if this is all they mean I see no reason why this would imply that there couldn’t be an indeterministic link between two time-slices, even though it is set or fixed what will occur in our future.

  7. 7.

    For instance, my actions, since I take it that my actions do not exhaust the time-slice. There are, after all, your actions as well.

  8. 8.

    Instead of entities you could read this as parts of the time slices.

  9. 9.

    Defining determinism in terms of possible worlds makes this clear. Such as Clarke’s definition, where ‘one event is taken to deterministically cause another just in case, in every possible world in which the actual laws of nature obtain and in which the first event occurs, it causes the second.’ (2003, 4).

  10. 10.

    Assuming that the laws of nature were the only determining factor.

  11. 11.

    PAP sometimes includes a claim about moral responsibility, however here I just mean it to refer to having alternative possibilities.

  12. 12.

    Note that there are also sourcehood versions of compatibilism (Timpe, 2017), but I focus on libertarianism here.

  13. 13.

    This position is also attributed to Clarke in Fischer (1999, 129, footnote 66).

  14. 14.

    In fairness, and unlike others, Koperski (2015, 115) does mention this, although he moves past it fairly promptly.

  15. 15.

    Timpe (2013, 155–161), for instance, has suggested that narrow-sourcehood does require PAP. If he is correct, then it isn’t a viable option and this way to make eternalism and libertarianism compatible fails. By contrast Shabo thinks all sourcehood accounts should reject PAP (2010, 350, n.4). Who is in fact right about this, I leave undiscussed here.

  16. 16.

    This is what O’Connor and Franklin call the categorical analysis of PAP.

  17. 17.

    Another way PAP is sometimes put is in terms of agents having the power to act otherwise than they in fact do. Since I take it that powers are inherently modal, with reductive analyses failing, this will also make PAP inherently modal.

  18. 18.

    I understand ‘access’ talk, the way van Inwagen does, as providing ‘a way of organizing our talk about unexercised abilities by reference to unrealized possibilities: an unexercised ability is treated as an ability to realize some unrealized possibility.’ (1983, 87).

  19. 19.

    I have spoken here, and will speak elsewhere in this paper, of possible worlds. I take it that whilst modal realism might be seen as a natural analogue to eternalism, eternalism by no means requires it. In fact I see no reason why eternalism would require any specific view on the metaphysical status of possible worlds. Given this, and since I want eternalism and libertarianism to be compatible with as many views as possible, I take no particular view on the ontology of possible worlds and therefore one can understand them as they wish.

  20. 20.

    Hinchliff (2000) also seems to give some views of presentisms relationship to relativity which would also allow me to tell a similar story.

  21. 21.

    I would also add sourcehood which I will turn to shortly.

  22. 22.

    This is also related to the problem of logical fatalism, which I don’t intend to contribute to here. The argument I’m responding to is sometimes purposefully distinguished from fatalism and as such is taken to be distinct (Koperski, 2015, 113–116). Nevertheless, let me say that some of the moves I make here, also speak against fatalism (Merricks, 2009, 2011) and that some have argued that eternalism grants additional resources for responding to fatalism (Finch & Rea, 2008).

  23. 23.

    Some might think that this requires eternalism, but it doesn’t and is compatible with presentism. See Leftow (2018, 1991, esp. 230–245).

  24. 24.

    Anselm, for instance seems to say just this in his De Concordia (The Compatibility of God’s Foreknowledge, Predestination, and Grace with Human Freedom), whilst also thinking that our actions are still free (Davies & Evans, 1998, 435–474).

  25. 25.

    This relation might be causal, with Tahira’s acts having a causal effect on what God believes. Some theists might worry about this. However, my purpose here isn’t to provide an orthodox theism but rather just to show that a closed future is compatible with free action. Nevertheless, a suggestion which may make what I say here non-causal is found in Merricks (2009, 41, 54–55; 2011, 574–579, 584, n.11) and Leftow (1991, 243–244, 255–265).

  26. 26.

    Le Poidevin (2013, 540–542) also provides a response to this worry.

  27. 27.

    See Clarke (2003, 34). Or we could perhaps say is reducible to events (O’Connor & Franklin, 2020).

  28. 28.

    As it’s been argued this type of causation is compatible with timeless worlds (Baron and Miller, 2014, 2015; Tallant, 2019) it would seem it ought to be compatible in eternalist worlds.

  29. 29.

    This is not to say that event-causal accounts must be reductive. If they are not, then another response will need to be given.

  30. 30.

    I can also produce an argument from authority for the claim libertarianism is compatible with eternalism. Van Inwagen is a contemporary defender of libertarianism, and yet he also doesn’t seem to be at all a fan of dynamic theories of passage (2015, ch.4). Yet never, as far as I’m aware, has he suggested that the negation of dynamic theories rules out libertarianism.

  31. 31.

    I do not mean to imply here that those who adopt a powers view must be agent-causalists.

  32. 32.

    I assume here that STR is compatible with simultaneous causation, but for some pushback on this see (Hansson Wahlberg, 2017).

  33. 33.

    At present there has been little published on how powers relate to time. Of what has been published, Vetter (2015, 290–299) thinks a powers theorist should prefer eternalism over presentism, whilst Backmann (2019) thinks the opposite.

  34. 34.

    Lockwood’s comment is also related to a powers theory of causation noted above and will be addressed further below. It is therefore also worth pointing out that many power theorists will deny that powers turn from being potentially X to being actually X. Instead they think of a power manifesting as jumping from being actually X to being actually Y (Mumford & Anjum, 2011; Bird, 2007). Whether they should do so, however, is another matter, since it might be that this theory denies change since it gives rise to the notorious always packing never travelling worry (Armstrong, 1997, 80).

  35. 35.

    Or in other words they do not ‘persist’.

  36. 36.

    This is ‘worm theory’ or standard perdurance. One could also adjust what I say here for ‘stage-theory’ if they wished. For more on this distinction see Hawley (2020).

  37. 37.

    This isn’t to say that I think this is in fact the case.

  38. 38.

    This view of powers isn’t prey to the always-packing-never-travelling worry (Marmodoro, 2017, 60–62).

  39. 39.

    Of course, the whole time-slice doesn’t depend on what they do, since it contains much besides the agent. But I take it you get the picture.

  40. 40.

    Obviously if libertarianism does not require endurantism and is compatible with other theories of persistence, then this objection will be overcome more easily.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Backmann, M. (2019). No time for powers. Inquiry, 62, 979–1007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2014). Causation in a timeless world. Synthese, 191, 2867–2886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2015). Causation “Sans” Time. American Philosophical Quarterly, 52, 27–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2019). An introduction to the philosophy of time. Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2007). Free will in the block universe. Philosophia, 35, 207–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckareff, A. A. (2019). Time, leeway, and the Laws of nature. Metaphysica, 20, 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian accounts of free will. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, D. (2020). Mereological endurantism defined. Inquiry, 1–12. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1851759?journalCode=sinq20

  • Davies, B., & Evans, G. R. (1998). Anselm of Canterbury: The major works. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, L. W. (1998). Causation, and the consequence argument. Synthese, 115, 333–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finch, A., & Rea, M. (2008). Presentism and Ockham’s way out. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, 1, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (1999). Recent work on moral responsibility. Ethics, 110, 93–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannini, G. (2021). Powers, processes, and time. Erkenntnis, 1–25. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10670-020-00327-z

  • Hansson Wahlberg, T. (2009). Endurance per se in B-time. Metaphysica, 10, 175–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson Wahlberg, T. (2017). Meso-level objects, powers, and simultaneous causation. Metaphysica, 18, 107–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2003). Persistence through time. In M. J. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2009). Metaphysics and relativity. In R. Le Poidevin, P. Simons, A. McGonigal, & R. P. Cameron (Eds.), The Routledge companion to metaphysics. Routedge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2020). Temporal parts. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encylopedia of philosophy. URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/temporal-parts/

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2012). The universe as we find it. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hinchliff, M. (2000). A defense of presentism in a relativistic setting. Philosophy of Science, 67, S575–S586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2002). Freedom from the inside out. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 50, 201–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. (2000). Moral responsibility and unavoidable action. Philosophical Studies, 97, 195–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (2005). A contemporary introduction to free will. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (2011). The causal closure of physics and free will. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2022). A dynamic B theory of time. In Powers, time and free will. Springer. (this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Koperski, J. (2015). The physics of theism. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R. (2013). Time and freedom. In H. Dyke & A. Bardon (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of time. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (1991). Time and eternity. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (2018). Presentism, Atemporality, and Time’s way. Faith and Philosophy, 35, 173–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, M. (2007). Compatibilism and special relativity. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 433–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, M. (2005). The labyrinth of time. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmodoro, A. (2017). Aristotelian powers at work: Reciprocity without symmetry in causation. In J. D. Jacobs (Ed.), Causal powers. Oxford University Pres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (2007). The mind in nature. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2009). Truth and freedom. Philosophical Review, 118, 29–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2011). Foreknowledge and freedom. Philosophical Review, 120, 567–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T., & Franklin, C. (2020). Free will. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/freewill/

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander, L. N. (1995). Part II: Time and identity. In Q. Smith & L. N. Oaklander (Eds.), Time, change and freedom. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander, L. N. (1998). Freedom and the new theory of time. In R. Le Poidevin (Ed.), Questions of time and tense. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petkov, V. (2005). Relativity and the nature of Spacetime. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Time and physical geometry. The Journal of Philosophy, 64, 240–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. C. (1998). Temporal parts unmotivated. Philosophical Review, 107, 225–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietdijk, C. W. (1966). A rigorous proof of determinism derived from the special theory of relativity. Philosophy of Science, 33, 341–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roselli, A. (2022). Dispositional essentialism in the eternalist block. In Powers, time and free will. Springer. (this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rychter, P. (2015). Classical compatibilism and temporal ontology. In A. Buckareff, C. Moya, & S. Rosell (Eds.), Agency, freedom, and responsibility. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sattig, T. (2006). The language and reality of time. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shabo, S. (2010). Uncompromising source Incompatibilism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 349–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2015). Objective becoming. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2018). Causation, explanation, and the metaphysics of aspect. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (1999). Alternative possibilities and moral responsibility: The flicker of freedom. The Journal of Ethics, 3, 299–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (2003). Moral responsibility without alternative possibilities. In M. McKenna & D. Widerker (Eds.), Moral responsibility and alternative possibilities: Essays on the importance of alternative possibilities. Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallant, J. (2019). Causation in a timeless world? Inquiry, 62, 300–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Timpe, K. (2013). Free will (2nd ed.). Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timpe, K. (2017). Leeway vs Sourcehood conceptions of free will. In K. Timpe, M. Griffith, & N. Levy (Eds.), The Routledge companion to free will. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tognazzi, N. (2011). Understanding source Incompatibilism. The Modern Schoolman, 88, 73–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2015). Metaphysics (4th ed.). Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, N. E. (2019). The powers metaphysic. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2000). Does libertarian freedom require alternative possibilities? Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 231–224.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ben Page .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Page, B. (2022). Libertarian Freedom in an Eternalist World?. In: Austin, C.J., Marmodoro, A., Roselli, A. (eds) Powers, Time and Free Will. Synthese Library, vol 451. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-92486-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics