Skip to main content

Dispositional Essentialism in the Eternalist Block

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Powers, Time and Free Will

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 451))

Abstract

The connection between the metaphysics of time and the metaphysics of powers is a relatively new debate in the philosophical literature. Friebe (Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 33, 77–89, 2017, Backmann (Inquiry, 62, 979–1007, 2018), Donati (No time for powers, Phd Dissertation, University of Nottingham, 2018) have argued that dispositional essentialism may encounter some problems when combined with (in their words) ‘static’ views of time, such as Eternalism. I believe this is a challenge that it is important to address. I will first briefly present (the standard version of) the four main metaphysics of time; I will then present and discuss the main objections moved to the combination of powers ontologies and the metaphysics of time; finally, I will argue that these objections fail, and that the alleged incompatibility results merely from a misconception of the staticity of Eternalism, on the one hand, and of the productiveness of powers on the other; in particular, I will show how the ‘incompatibility argument’ is either false or trivial.

I am grateful for the feedback received on earlier versions of this paper presented (online) at the 2021 Conference of the Society for the Metaphysics of Science The research leading to this publication was supported by the Leverhulme Trust as part of the project Part-whole relations within the fundamental potentialities in nature (RPG-2018-079).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In a ‘predicatory’ sense, whatever we say in our natural language about an object defines a property: an object has the property of being such that ‘x’. However, we might have good reasons to think that such a predicative property is not necessarily a full-fledged component of our ontology; powers are ‘ontic dispositional properties’ in the sense that are ontological components of the world (see e.g. Bird, 2016 for the difference between predicatory and ontic use of the term property).

  2. 2.

    In order for a dispositional property to be a power, its dispositionality needs to be a non-reducible, ineliminable part of what that property is. A nice and direct way to understand what powers are, then, would be to say that powers are properties which are essentially dispositional – as in e.g. Shoemaker (1969), Ellis (2001), Heil (2003), Bird (2007), Martin (2007); this might however be controversial, as some power ontologists, such as Molnar (2003), Mumford (2004), prefer to avoid the reference to ‘essences’, and simply claim that the dispositionality of powers is what fixes their identity, instead of representing their essence.

  3. 3.

    See for example Callender 2002, Maudlin 2007, Dainton 2010, Markosian 2014 for an overview of the different positions in the debate. Presentism and Eternalism are, by far, the most popular metaphysics of time; the Growing Block view (Ellis, 2006, 2014) and the Moving Spotlight view (Skow, 2012, 2015), however, are quite discussed in recent literature. There are also other possibilities, such as the Burning Fuse model (Norton, 2015) or various combinations of the main four metaphysics, but it is not relevant for the present purposes. I will consider here the three most popular views: Presentism, Eternalism, and the Growing Block Theory (GBT).

  4. 4.

    There are of course many different ways to be a Presentist – and the same goes with the other metaphysics of time; what I am here presenting is a simplified, standard introduction to these positions to help a potential reader who is not acquainted with this temporal debate.

  5. 5.

    One of the interesting consequences of Presentism, which I will not however discuss here, is that it is difficult to see space and time as different aspects of the same entity ‘spacetime’.

  6. 6.

    Broad’s Growing Block has received more and more attention starting from Tooley (1997) and many physicists are fascinated by the challenge of merging contemporary physics with a Growing Block account of the world, most noticeably George Ellis (see e.g. Ellis, 2006 and 2014).

  7. 7.

    See e.g. Braddon-Mitchell (2004) for a discussion of this topic.

  8. 8.

    I am here simplifying: Craig Callender, for example, consider himself an Eternalist and yet argues in favour of a stronger notion of present (see e.g. Callender, 2002, 2008). Another interesting way to present the debate would be to talk about tense theories and tenseless theories; however, for our present purposes, this would merely lead us astray, as I am already going to propose considering the (very similar) opposition between dynamic and static views of time.

  9. 9.

    Shimony, 1993: 284.

  10. 10.

    “For simplicity we consider the flat spacetime of special relativity (Minkowski space). But with little change it could be a curved spacetime of general relativity”. Hartle (2005), p. 103.

  11. 11.

    I am aware of the existence of different models to explain time estimation and duration perception (the most famous are probably the “Internal clock model” and Ian Phillips’ “Mental activity model”); but this querelle is not relevant here, since everything I need to claim is that – whichever model we choose to represent our internal temporal processing – more images, even if visually identical, are at least numerically distinct; that our brain is able to distinguish between one picture and the successive acquisition of ten identical pictures.

  12. 12.

    The situation is complicated a little by the fact that there are different models to account for our temporal phenomenology (the three main models of our temporal understanding are the Extensionalist, the Retentionalist and the Cinematist); the accumulation of experiences, however, is something that these models have in common. Whichever model we choose to describe our temporal phenomenology, our ‘dynamical feeling’ in front of the same painting is described by the continuous acquisition of data.

  13. 13.

    Dynamists might well argue that this awareness is impossible without the feeling of an objective flow of time, or that the nature of this awareness is unclear, or similar arguments; but I find this line of thought quite promising for Eternalists that want to explain our subjective temporal experience. As the present purposes have more to do with metaphysics than phenomenology, however, this debate is here not crucial.

  14. 14.

    See e.g. Bird (2007), Esfeld (2008).

  15. 15.

    There are different possible terminologies in the literature for metaphysics which contain irreducible dispositional properties, each of which has different implications (some philosophers, for example, want to avoid the reference to essences, etc.). For reasons of simplicity, I will here use “dispositional essentialism” as a synonym of “powers metaphysic”.

  16. 16.

    Backmann (2018) mentions Groff (2013), Mumford (2009), and Ellis (2002) as paradigmatic cases of full-fledged powers metaphysics.

  17. 17.

    Causally inert properties, known in literature as ‘categorical’, are typically understood as geometrical/structural properties like shape and size (as well as any irreducible qualitative properties). Neo-Humeans take all properties to be causally inert categorical properties, lacking modal or causal characteristics; therefore, whatever causal or modal fact obtains in the world, it does so because it is determined by the limited base of categorical properties. An ontology in which all fundamental properties are categorical is known in literature as categorical monism; categorical monism is a key aspect of the neo-humean ontology, which eschews any fundamental property whose essence is at all powerful.

  18. 18.

    It is well-known the fact that in QM there seem to be ‘spooky actions at a distance’, as Einstein used to say. Entangled particles seem to be showing that Quantum information could travel faster than light; I take this into consideration in the next sentence.

References

  • Backmann, M. (2018). No time for powers. Inquiry, 62(9–10), 979–1007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2016). Overpowering: How the powers ontology has overreached itself. Mind, 125(498), 341–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2004). How do we know it is now now? Analysis, 64(283), 199–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific Thought. Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2002). Time, reality and experience. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2008). The common now. Philosophical Issues, 18, 339–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2010). Time and space (2nd ed.). Acumen Publishing Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2006). The ontology of spacetime (pp. 111–127). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donati, D. (2018). No time for powers, Phd Dissertation, University of Nottingham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2006). The irrelevance of the presentism/Eternalism debate for the ontology of Minkowski Spacetime. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 93–109). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2012). Presentism/eternalism and endurantism/perdurantism: Why the unsubstantiality of the first debate implies that of the second. Philosophia Naturalis, 49(1), 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature. A guide to the new essentialism. Mc Gill-Queen’s University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. (2006). Physics in the real universe. General Relativity and Gravitation, 38, 1797–1824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. (2014). The evolving block universe and the meshing together of times. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1326, 26–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2008). Naturphilosophie als Metaphysik der Natur. M. Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friebe, C. (2017). Metaphysics of laws and ontology of time, Theoria: An international. Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 33(1), 77–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groff, R. (2013). Whose powers? Which agency? In Powers and capacities in philosophy, edited by Ruth Groff and John Greco (pp. 207–227). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hartle, J. (2005). The physics of now. American Journal of Physics, 73, 101–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2014). A defence of presentism. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 1(3), 47–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (2007). The mind in nature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, U. (2005). The presentist’s dilemma. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 122(3), 213–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2009). Powers and persistence. In L. Honnefelder, E. Runggaldier, & B. S. de Gruyter (Eds.), Unity and time in metaphysics (pp. 223–236).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2015). The burning fuse model of unbecoming in time. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52(part A), 103–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, D. (1972). The myth of the passage of time. In J. T. Fraser, F. Haber, & G. Muller (Eds.), The study of time (pp. 110–121). Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1996). Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savitt, S. (2006). Presentism and eternalism in perspective. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 111–127). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savitt, S. (2017). Being and becoming in modern physics. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spacetime-become

  • Shimony. (1993). Search for a naturalistic world view (p. 1993). Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1969). Time without change. The Journal of Philosophy, 66(12), 363–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2012). One second per second. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2), 377–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2015). Objective becoming. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1997). Time, tense and causation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, N. (2019). The powers metaphysic. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wuthrich, C. (2012). Demarcating presentism. In H. de Regt, S. Hartmann, & S. Okasha (Eds.), EPSA philosophy of science: Amsterdam 2009. The European philosophy of science association proceedings (pp. 441–450). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Roselli, A. (2022). Dispositional Essentialism in the Eternalist Block. In: Austin, C.J., Marmodoro, A., Roselli, A. (eds) Powers, Time and Free Will. Synthese Library, vol 451. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-92486-7_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics