Skip to main content

The Consequence Argument and an Ontology of Dispositions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Powers, Time and Free Will

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 451))

  • 302 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper I discuss naturalistic, transcendentalist and ethical approaches to the problem of free will. After a brief introduction to the libertarian/compatibilist debate, I show in what sense the notion of determinism and indeterminism on which it is based presupposes a philosophical position on the nature of laws of nature. After introducing van Inwagen’s consequent argument, I argue that Humean attempt to solve it fails it because the humean approach to laws is untenable and because the laws of nature do not depend on us in the sense advocated by humeans. In the last part of the paper, I claim that and ontology of dispositions opens the way to what is most important in human freedom, namely the ability to act in a certain way as in virtue centered morality, and in the capability approach already defended by Sen and Nussbaum.

This work has been supported by the Italian Ministry of Education, University and Research through the PRIN 2017 program “The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image” prot. 2017ZNWW7F_004.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The literature on the best system analysis is immense. Usually Mill and Ramsey are considered the originators of the account. More recently, the view has been expanded and articulated in particular by Lewis 1973, 1983, 1986 and 1994. By doing injustice to many important contributors, here I will just list Loewer (1996) and, more recently, Callender and Cohen (2009). For of one of the most complete accounts of Lewisian’s approach to chance, see Hoefer (2019).

  2. 2.

    The expression is Dennett’s (1983).

  3. 3.

    In a sense, Sen’s capability approach presupposes that freedom to achieve well-being is the fundamental notion of freedom (Sen, 1985). See also Nussbaum, M. (1988).

  4. 4.

    An intellect which at a certain moment would know all forces that set nature in motion, and all positions of all items of which nature is composed…nothing would be uncertain … . (Laplace, 1951, p. 4, my italics)

  5. 5.

    This conception of laws as axiomatic systems combining simplicity and strength has been famously advanced by Lewis (1973, p. 73)

  6. 6.

    See Esfeld 2020, p. 65.

  7. 7.

    For an irreducibly stochastic interpretation of quantum theory, see Ghirardi, Rimini and Weber (1986).

  8. 8.

    For a recent treatment, see Dürr, Goldstein, and Zanghì, Nino (2013). Whether the probabilities of Bohmian mechanics are epistemic, see Hoefer (2019).

  9. 9.

    This example is Kane’s.

  10. 10.

    Assuming that the evolution of the process of coin tossing is indeterministic, which is not.

  11. 11.

    Balaguer 2010, p. 73. There are some differences with Kane’s notion of self-forming actions on which I cannot enter.

  12. 12.

    For an opposite position, see Stanford (2006).

  13. 13.

    For the usefulness of inconsistent science, see Vickers (2013).

  14. 14.

    See also Weinert (1995).

  15. 15.

    “Scientific determinism is the doctrine that the state of any physical system at any given future instant of time can be predicted … by deducing the prediction from theories… .”(Popper 1982, p. 36)

  16. 16.

    Here I ignore the difference between stable determinism and chaotic determinism.

  17. 17.

    The claim that the algebraic approach is sufficient to regard quantum field theory as axiomatized is not uncontroversial.

  18. 18.

    Newton (1726), Law 1, 416.

  19. 19.

    For a more articulated justification of these five points, see Dorato (2005).

  20. 20.

    For the current purpose, there is need to enter into details to distinguish among these notions.

  21. 21.

    The antireductionist camp also includes views claiming that laws are contingent relations of necessity between properties, explaining the repeatable character of regularities (see Armstrong, 1983; Dretske, 1977; Tooley, 1977) Within this conception, laws exist, so that it cannot be used to attack the consequence argument

  22. 22.

    Quantum mechanics requires a more detailed treatment, since quantum measurements typically do not reveal preexisting values of the measured system.

  23. 23.

    I owe this objection to Carl Hoefer.

  24. 24.

    See among other text, Buchanan A, Brock D, Daniels N, Wikler D (2000).

  25. 25.

    Frankfurt distinguishes between first order desires and first order will: “it is having second order volitions, and not having second-order desires generally, that I regard as essential to being a person (Frankfurt 1982 in Watson p. 86). Smith et al. prefer to naturalize the concept of will by identifying it with a concept of a desire than that is stronger than any other desire that a persona may have in a certain moment “I say that to be a value means to be that which we desire to desire. Then to be a value-to be good, near enough-means to be that which we are disposed, under ideal conditions, to desire” (Smith et al. 1989, p. 116). I treat ‘will’ and ‘desire’ as interchangeable.

  26. 26.

    Via complex but effective “spiritual exercises”, Hadot (1995) shows how effective stoic teaching was in learning to want what we don’t want.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (2010). Free will as an open scientific problem. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H., & Mele, A. R. (2002). Humean compatibilism. Mind, 111, 201–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2005). The dispositionalist conception of laws. Foundations of Science, 10, 353–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1913). On the constitution of atoms and molecules. Philosophical Magazines, 26(6), 1–25, 476–502, 857–875.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradie, M., & Harms, W. (2020). Evolutionary epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/epistemology-evolutionary/

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. (2005). Physical relativity. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., Brock, D., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1966). Philosophical foundations of physics. Basics Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrol, I. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. (2016). Laws of nature. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2016 ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/laws-of-nature/

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1976). Persons and objects. Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. In L. Foster & J. W. Swanson (Eds.), Experience and theory (pp. 79–101). University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demerest, H. (2012). Do counterfactuals ground the laws of nature? A critique of Lange. Philosophy of Science, 79, 333–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1983). Free will. The varieties of free worth wanting. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2003). Freedom evolves. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2005). The software of the universe. Ashgate

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2007). Dispositions, relational properties and the quantum world. In M. Kistler & B. Gnassonou (Eds.), Dispositions and causal powers (pp. 249–270). Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2020). Bohr meets Rovelli: A dispositionalist account of the quantum limits of knowledge. Quantum Studies Mathematics and Foundations. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40509-020-00220-y. ISSN: 2196-5609 (Print) 2196-5617.

  • Dorato, M., & Esfeld, M. (2010). GRW as an ontology of dispositions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41, 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Quantum physics without quantum philosophy. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1986). A primer on determinism. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. (2007). Issues in the philosophy of cosmology. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Philosophy of physics (Part B) (p. 1183, 1286). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2020). Science and human freedom. Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2022). Super-Humeanism and mental causation. In A. Marmodoro, C. Austin, & A. Roselli (Eds.), Time, laws and free will. Springer (this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., & Deckert, D. (2017). A minimalist ontology of the natural world. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1982). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will (pp. 81–95). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., Rimini, A., & Weber, T. (1986). Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physical Review D, 34, 470–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1999). Science without laws. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a way of life. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. B. S. (1927). Possible worlds and other essays. Chatto and Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2016). Causal determinism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/determinism-causal/

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2019). Chance in the world. A Humean guide to objective chance. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2016). How physics makes us free. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1966). The significance fo free will. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2009). Free will, physics, biology, and the brain. In N. Murphy, G. F. R. Ellis, & T. O’Connor (Eds.), Downward causation and the neurobiology of free will. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). The essential tension. Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1989). Laws and lawmakers. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P. S. (1951). In F. W. Truscott & F. L. Emory (Eds.), A philosophical essay on probabilities (Translated into English from the original French) (6th ed.). Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L., & Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 449–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986a). Are we free to break the laws? In Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 291–298). Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986b). Philosophical papers (Vol. II). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M., & Johnston, M. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, London, Supplementary volume, Vol. 63, pp. 89–111+113–137+139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24, 101–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). Metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1942). Science and technology in a democratic order. Journal of Legal and Political Sociology, 1, 115–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. (1971). Chance and necessity: An essay on the natural philosophy of modern Biology. A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1726). Mathematical principles of natural philosophy (I. B. Cohen & A. Whitman, Trans.). University of California Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2008). Must evidence underdetermine theory? In M. Carrier, D. Howard, & J. Kourany (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice: Science and values revisited (pp. 17–44). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1988). Nature, functioning and capability: Aristotle on political distribution. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Supplementary volume), 6, 145–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1992). Human functioning and social justice. In defense of Aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory, 20(2), 202–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M., & Sen, A. (1993). The quality of life. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ornstein, D. S. (1974). Ergodic theory, randomness, and dynamical systems. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1994). Shadows of the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1982). The open universe. Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1959). The key property of physical laws – Inaccuracy. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Current issues in the philosophy of science – Proceedings of Section L of the American Association for the Advancement of Sciences. Holt Rinehart and Winston, 1961, pp. 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis. University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1962). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Frontiers of science and philosophy (pp. 35–78). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1985). Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey lectures 1984. Journal of Philosophy, 82(4), 169–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M., Lewis, M., & Johnston, M. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, London, Supplementary volume, Vol. 63, pp. 89–111+113–137+139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1993). The transcendental character of determinism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18(1):242–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 667–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, P. (2013). Understanding inconsistent science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, B. (2002). Humeanism without Humean supervenience: A projectivist account of laws and possibilities. Philosophical Studies, 107, 191–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, M. D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinert, F. (Ed.). (1995). Laws of nature. Essays on the Philosophical, Scientific and Historical Dimension. Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mauro Dorato .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Dorato, M. (2022). The Consequence Argument and an Ontology of Dispositions. In: Austin, C.J., Marmodoro, A., Roselli, A. (eds) Powers, Time and Free Will. Synthese Library, vol 451. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-92486-7_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics