Skip to main content

Dialectical System of Qiyās al-dalāla and Qiyās al-shabah

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Arsyad al-Banjari’s Insights on Parallel Reasoning and Dialectic in Law

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 25))

  • 70 Accesses

Abstract

As already discussed, correlational inferences by indication (qiyās al-dalāla) and resemblance (qiyās al-shabah), sometimes broadly referred to as arguments by analogy (or better by the Latin denomination arguments a pari), are put into action when there is absence of knowledge of the occasioning factor grounding the application of a given ruling. These forms of qiyās relate the branch-case to the root-case by developing a parallel reasoning based on some kind of similarity. However, though both qiyās al-dalāla and qiyās al-shabah are based on establishing resemblance, the notion of resemblance deployed by qiyās al-dalāla is quite different from that one deployed by qiyās al-shabah. Thus, before developing a dialogical framework for these forms of correlational inferences, we should first examine the notion of resemblance employed by each of these forms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    al-Shīrāzī (1987, p. 37).

  2. 2.

    al-Ghazālī (1971, pp. 441–444) calls this kind of inference al-istidlāl bi al-khāṣṣiya (inference by particularity). Young (2017, p. 94 and n. 31) has a different interpretation of this type of qiyas.

  3. 3.

    See al-Shīrāzī (2003, p. 112); and al-Baghdādī (1421H, p. 520).

  4. 4.

    al-Shīrāzī (1988, p. 860)

  5. 5.

    al-Shīrāzī (1988, pp. 809–810).

  6. 6.

    In plain words, ruling * is dependent upon ruling which applies to cases of the type \( \mathcal{A} \). See the explanation of hypotheticals with multiple hypotheses in the appendix to the present book.

  7. 7.

    Recall that, as mentioned in I.3.1.2, the expression “right(x)” stands for the operator that selects the right proof-object of a disjunction.

  8. 8.

    This move can be seen as related to Averroes’ notion of ibdāl or substitution of the general by the particular (see Bou Akl, 2019, pp. 50–62). However, as discussed in our preface, al-Shīrāzī’s general conception of qiyās (not only of the kind al-dalāla) goes the other way around: while examining the form of the substituted instance, the general substitutional form comes to the fore.

  9. 9.

    An alternative reconstruction would stress the fact that both the root- and the branch-case are identical in relation to the rulings, and then conclude by substitution. However, this option makes the distinction between qiyās al-dalāla and qiyās al-shabah less clear-cut.

  10. 10.

    Recall that the injection right(b): \( \mathcal{C} \)(f)∨\( \mathcal{C}{}^{\circ} \)(f) yields b: \( \mathcal{C} \)(f).

  11. 11.

    However, in other parts of Young’s book there is a discussion of this point but not in relation to that example, such as Young (2017, pp. 94–95 and p. 105).

  12. 12.

    al-Shīrāzī (2003, p. 100).

  13. 13.

    Cf. Young’s explanation (2017, pp. 117–118).

  14. 14.

    al-Shīrāzī (2003, p. 100). al-Ghazālī (1971, pp. 446) calls this form al-istidlāl bi al-naẓīr.

  15. 15.

    See al-Shīrāzī (1407 H/1986, p. 81).

  16. 16.

    In fact, like the term khaṣīṣa in the first type, al-Shīrāzī does not employ the term naẓīr in the Mulakhkhaṣ, however, he does use it in the Ma‘ūna and in the al-Luma‘.

  17. 17.

    This again involves the process of grasping the universal by examining the particular.

  18. 18.

    See Fyzee (1964, p. 154).

  19. 19.

    Dhimmī is a historical term referring to non-Muslim citizens of an Islamic state.

  20. 20.

    See the explanation of hypotheticals with multiple hypotheses in the appendix to the present book.

  21. 21.

    Notice that in the case of khaṣīṣa both steps have the same objective, namely establishing a formation rule that makes it apparent that one of the rulings is a specification of the other.

  22. 22.

    See al-Shīrāzī (2003, p. 209). Cf. al-Shīrāzī (2016, fol. 5a).

  23. 23.

    Cf. al-Shīrāzī (2003, p. 101).

  24. 24.

    This is different to the main conceptions of analogy nowadays where the properties on both sides (the target case and the known case) might be similar rather than exactly the same – see e.g. Bartha (2010) – we come back to this issue at the end chapter of the present book.

  25. 25.

    More precisely, within the framework of CTT real definitions establish what something is in relation to some canonical element of the set, and thus if two entities are definitionally equal a true proposition establishing the identity of both can be asserted. However, the inverse is not assured – see Ranta (1994, p. 52).

  26. 26.

    See al-Shīrāzī (1407 H/1986, p. 81). Cf. Young (2017, p. 118).

  27. 27.

    In the following sections we present only a simplified and adapted form of the Dialogical Framework, called Immanent Reasoning – see Rahman et al. (2018). The main original papers are collected in Lorenzen and Lorenz (1978) – see too Lorenz (2010a, b), Felscher (1985), Krabbe (2006). For an account of recent developments see Rahman and Keiff (2005), Keiff (2009), Rahman and Tulenheimo (2009), Rückert (2011), Clerbout (2014a, b). The most recent work links dialogical logic and Constructive Type Theory, see Clerbout and Rahman (2015) and Rahman et al. (2017).

  28. 28.

    Cf. Rahman and Rückert (2001, pp. 113–116).

  29. 29.

    For a formal formulation see Clerbout (2014a, b).

  30. 30.

    This last clause is known as the Last Duty First condition, and is the clause which makes dialogical games suitable for Intuitionistic Logic, hence the name of this rule.

  31. 31.

    This, rule, as extensively discussed in Sect. 2.2.1 is one of the most salient characteristics of dialogical logic. In previous literature on dialogical logic this rule has been called the copy-cat rule or Socratic rule and it introduces a kind of asymmetry in the distribution of roles. Clearly, if the ultimate grounds of a dialogical thesis are elementary statements and if this is implemented by the use of the copy-cat rule, then the development of a dialogue is in this sense necessarily asymmetric. Indeed, if both contenders were restricted by the copy-cat rule no elementary statement can ever be uttered. Thus, we implement the copy-cat rule by designating one player, called the Proponent, whose utterances of elementary statements are restricted by this rule. It is the win of the Proponent that provides the dialogical notion of validity.

  32. 32.

    For more details see structural rules for Immanent Reasoning SR5 in Rahman et al. (2019, Chapter IV); Rahman et al. (2018).

  33. 33.

    For more details see structural rules for Immanent Reasoning in Rahman et al. (2019, Chapter IV); Rahman et al. (2018).

  34. 34.

    See al-Shīrāzī (1987, pp. 116–117)

  35. 35.

    Al-Bājī (2001, p. 202) provides two different opinions of legal theorist (uṣūliyyūn) concerning farq. Some legal theorist, such as Abū al-Ḥasan b. al-Quṣṣār, say that farq does not require a counterexample (i.e. a new root-case competing the root-case proposed by the Proponent)– that is to say, it is enough for the Opponent to distinguish the root-case from the branch-case in relation to a specific property which is a specification of the proposed property (let us call Ꝓ*) in order to invalidate the Proponent’s analogy. While the others, including al-Bājī, argue that farq requires a counterexample that shares with the branch-case that specific property Ꝓ*. With that said, the Opponent proposes another analogy competing the Proponent’s analogy. In fact, so far as we understood, al-Bājī speaks of farq within the frame of mu‘āraḍa, whereas al-Quṣṣār, perhaps, describes farq in general. Therefore, we distinguish two forms of farq, namely farq and mu‘āraḍa-farq.

References

  • al-Baghdādī, A.. (1421 H). Al-Faqīh wa al-Mutafaqqih (A. al-Raḥmān, Ed.). Dār ibn Jauzī.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Bājī, A. S. (2001). Kitāb al-Minhāj fī Tartīb al-Ḥijāj (‘A. Turkī, Ed.). Dār al-Gharb al-Islāmī.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Ghazālī, A. H. (1971). Shifā’ al-Ghalīl (A. Al-Kabīsī, Ed.). Maṭba‘a al-Irshād.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Shīrāzī, A. I.. (1407 H/1986). Mulakhkhaṣ fī al-Jadal fī Uṣūl al-Fiqh (M. Y. Ā. J. Niyāzī, Ed.). MA thesis, Umm al-Qura University.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Shīrāzī, A. I.. (1987). Al-Maʿūna fī al-Jadal. (ʻA. Al-Ṣafāh, Ed.). Manshūrāt Markaz al-Makhṭūṭāt wa-al-Turāth.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Shīrāzī, A. I. (1988). Sharḥ al-Lumaʻ fī Uṣūl al-Fiqh (ʻA. Turkī, Ed.). Dār al-Gharb al-Islāmī.

    Google Scholar 

  • al-Shīrāzī, A. I.. (2003). Al-Lumaʿ fī Uṣūl al-Fiqh. Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyah.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. (2010). By parallel reasoning; The construction and evaluation of analogical arguments. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bou Akl, Z. (2019). Averroes on juridical reasoning. In P. Adamson (Ed.), Interpreting Averroes: Critical essays (pp. 45–63). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N. (2014a). First-order dialogical games and tableaux. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(4), 785–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N. (2014b). Étude sur quelques sémantiques dialogiques: Concepts fondamentaux et éléments de métathéorie. College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N., & Rahman, S. (2015). Linking game-theoretical approaches with constructive type theory: Dialogical strategies as CTT-demonstrations. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Felscher. (1985). Dialogues as a foundation for intuitionistic logic. In D. Gabbay, & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 3, pp. 341–372).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fyzee, A. A. (1964). Outlines of Muhammadan law. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keiff, L. (2009). Dialogical logic (E. N. Zalta, Ed.). Retrieved from The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-dialogical

  • Krabbe, E. C. (2006). Dialogue logic. In D. Gabbay & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic (Vol. 7, pp. 665–704). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (2010a). Logic, language and method: On polarities in human experiences. De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (2010b). Philosophische Variationen: Gesammelte Aufsätze unter Einschluss gemeinsam mit Jürgen Mittelstrass greschriebener Arbeiten zu Platon und Leibniz. De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenzen, P., & Lorenz, K. (1978). Dialogische Logik. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., & Keiff, L. (2005). On how to be a dialogician. In D. Vanderveken (Ed.), Logic, thought and action (pp. 359–408). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., & Rückert, H. (Eds.). (2001). New perspectives in dialogical logic (Special volume synthese 127). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., & Tulenheimo, T. (2009). From games to dialogues and back: Towards a general frame for validity. In O. Majer, A. Pietarinen, & T. Tulenheimo (Eds.), Games: Unifying logic, language and philosophy (pp. 153–208). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., Clerbout, N., & Redmond, J. (2017). Interacción e Igualdad La interpretación dialógica de la Teoría Constructiva de Tipos Interaction and equality dialogical interpretation of constructive type theory. Critica, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosov, UNAM, 49(145), 49–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., McConaughey, Z., Klev, A., & Clerbout, N. (2018). Immanent reasoning or equality in action. A plaidoyer for the play level. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., Iqbal, M., & Soufi, Y. (2019). Inference by parallel reasoning in Islamic jurisprudence. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ranta, A. (1994). Type-theoretical grammar. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rückert, H. (2011). Dialogues as a dynamic framework for logic. College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, W. E. (2017). The dialectical forge; Juridical disputation and the evolution of Islamic law. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Iqbal, M. (2022). Dialectical System of Qiyās al-dalāla and Qiyās al-shabah. In: Arsyad al-Banjari’s Insights on Parallel Reasoning and Dialectic in Law. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 25. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-91676-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics