Skip to main content

In Defense of the No-Miracles Argument

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 332 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 445))

Abstract

Both semantic realism and epistemic realism inhere in Putnam’s no-miracles argument (NMA). Laudan’s objection to realism is compatible with both semantic and epistemic realism. To reject the NMA for the reason that the success of science does not cry out for explanation is to violate the basic rule for evaluating an argument. Some antirealists reject inference to the best explanation, but they use it themselves to establish their own philosophical hypotheses. It is incoherent for antirealists to appeal to evolutionary theory and a psychological hypothesis as a way to discredit realism. Realism is not an ad hoc hypothesis because it explains not only the phenomenon that it was designed to explain but also another phenomenon. It is circular to explain success in terms of empirical adequacy. Surrealism inadequately attributes the success of a scientific theory to the behavior of observables. Predictive similarity is an unsatisfactory explanans for explaining success.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A theory has manipulative power when it helps us intervene in natural processes.

  2. 2.

    I drop “approximately” hereafter for the sake of brevity.

References

  • Akins, K. (1996). Of sensory systems and the ‘aboutness’ of mental states. The Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 337–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bromberger, S. (1966). Why-questions. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Mind and cosmos: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy (pp. 86–111). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859/1993). The portable Darwin. In P. Graham (Ed.), Duncan Porter and Paris: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986). Unnatural attitudes: Realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind, 95(378), 149–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61(1–2), 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost-Arnold, G. (2010). The no-miracles argument: Inference to an unacceptable explanation. Philosophy of Science, 77(1), 35–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., & Beddor, B. (2016). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/reliabilism/

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, R. (2001). Are realism and instrumentalism methodologically indifferent? Philosophy of Science, 68(Proceedings), S25–S37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1888/1978). A treatise of human nature. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), : Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2010). Default privilege and bad lots: Underconsideration and explanatory inference. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24(1), 91–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1999). Review. A novel defense of scientific realism. J. Leplin. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(1), 181–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., & van Fraassen, B. (1997). A defense of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive inference: Reply to Psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(188), 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism. In J. Cushing, C. Delaney, & G. Gutting (Eds.), Science and reality (pp. 83–105). University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1987). Surrealism. Mind, 97(384), 519–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2003). Explaining the success of a scientific theory. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 891–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2005). Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63(2), 167–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2016). Scientific realism. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science (pp. 564–584). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2017). Epistemic selectivity, historical threats, and the non-epistemic tenets of scientific realism. Synthese, 194(9), 3203–3219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2018). Four challenges to epistemic scientific realism. Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science, 9(1), 146–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2012). Why the ultimate argument for scientific realism ultimately fails. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43(1), 132–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209–3226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2020). The relativity of theory: Key positions and arguments in the contemporary scientific realism/antirealism debate. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229–252). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (2017). Strict empiricism versus explanation in science. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 71–93). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (2017). Cognitive illusions and nonrealism: Objections and replies. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 151–163). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2001). Scientific realism vs. scientific antirealism. PhD dissertation. University of Arizona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2003). Ontological order in scientific explanation. Philosophical Papers, 32(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2011). Coherence of our best scientific theories. Foundations of Science, 16(1), 21–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2014a). On the evolutionary defense of scientific antirealism. Axiomathes, 24(2), 263–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2014b). The doxastic requirement of scientific explanation and understanding. Prolegomena, 13(2), 279–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2015a). Against motivational efficacy of beliefs. Coactivity: Philosophy Communication, 23(1), 86–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2015b). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2016a). Extensional scientific realism vs. intensional scientific realism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 59, 46–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2016b). Realism versus surrealism. Foundations of Science, 21(4), 603–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2017a). Scientific antirealists have set fire to their own houses. Prolegomena, 16(1), 23–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2017b). Defense of epistemic reciprocalism. Filosofija. Sociologija, 28(1), 56–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2017c). Problems with using evolutionary theory in philosophy. Axiomathes, 27(3), 321–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2017d). The unificatory power of scientific realism. Disputatio, 9(44), 59–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2018). Justifying the special theory of relativity with unconceived methods. Axiomathes, 28(1), 53–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2019a). The descriptive and normative versions of scientific realism and pessimism. Filozofia: Journal for Philosophy, 74(4), 278–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2019b). In defense of realism and selectivism from Lyons’s objections. Foundations of Science, 24(4), 605–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2019c). Scientific realism and the future development of science. Diametros: An Online Journal of Philosophy, 60, 61–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2019d). Surrealism is not an alternative to scientific realism. Logos & Episteme: An International Journal of Epistemology, 10(4), 379–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2020). Critiques of axiological realism and surrealism. Acta Analytica, 35(1), 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1996). Scientific realism and the ‘pessimistic induction.’ Philosophy of Science, 63(Proceedings), S306–S314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2011). Making contact with molecules: On Perrin and Achinstein. In G. Morgan (Ed.), Philosophy of science matters: The philosophy of Peter Achinstein (pp. 177–190). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quoidbach, J., Gilbert, D., & Wilson, T. (2013). The end of history illusion. Science, 339(6115), 96–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2017). Realism, progress and the historical turn. Foundations of Science, 22(1), 201–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2000). An antirealist explanation of the success science. Philosophy of Science, 67(2), 266–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2007). A selectionist explanation for the success and failures of science. Erkenntnis, 67(1), 81–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2008). The argument from under consideration as grounds for anti-realism: A defence. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(3), 317–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2010). Selection and predictive success. Erkenntnis, 72(3), 365–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2012). Epistemic privilege and the success of science. Noûs, 46(3), 375–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2013). The pessimistic induction and the exponential growth of science reassessed. Synthese, 190(18), 4321–4330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2015). Pessimistic inductions: Four varieties. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(1), 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Park, S. (2022). In Defense of the No-Miracles Argument. In: Embracing Scientific Realism. Synthese Library, vol 445. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-87813-9_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics