Skip to main content

On the Structure and Stock Issues of Legislative Justification (in Parliamentary Debates)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Exploring the Province of Legislation

Part of the book series: Legisprudence Library ((LEGIS,volume 9))

Abstract

Within a lawmaking process, parliamentary debates are ideally supposed to be a major place for advancing and discussing legislative arguments. If taken seriously, this ideal expectation urges the question of whether MPs can actually justify their enactments by arguing, i.e. by giving and exchanging reasons for and against legislation, and how we could possibly ascertain the quality of their argumentation. This chapter suggests a structural account of statutory justification (as contained in debate minutes) which might be used to assess legislative deliberations in parliament. After some preliminary remarks, I introduce the gist of a legisprudential approach to the analysis and evaluation of parliamentary debate of bills. A key aspect of this approach concerns the implicit structure of justification underlying legislative deliberation, a structure that may be conceived of as a special variant of value-based teleological argument. In order to grasp it, I will sketch a basic model of legislative teleology (which loosely draws on the principle of proportionality). This model serves as a basis for two evaluation tools that can help us to inspect the legisprudential quality of parliamentary debate: an argument scheme, i.e. an inferential structure capturing the essentials of legislative justification; and a set of critical questions or stock issues that elected lawmakers should tackle when debating bills. Both tools, in turn, can eventually be utilised to further evaluate parliamentary debates in terms of deliberative thoroughness and of plausibility of legislative reasons.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course, this is not the only similarity between both areas: parallels between legislators (legislatures, lawmaking processes) and judges (courts, trials) are almost a classic topic in legal thinking (cf. e.g. Horack 1937, 1938).

  2. 2.

    On the intertwinement between norm justification and norm application, see e.g. Alexy (1995), pp. 52 ff., critically commenting on K. Gunther’s controversial contradistinction between these practices.

  3. 3.

    Conduction is taken here as a form of arguing where a ‘conclusion is drawn from both positive and negative considerations’ (Wellman 1971, p. 57). Cf. Govier (2010), p. 352 ff. and Fairclough (2018), pp. 297 ff. As to the implications of legislative dissensus for statutory interpretation, see e.g. Nourse (2016), pp. 64 ff. or Sehl (2019), pp. 151 ff.

  4. 4.

    Cf. e.g. Gartz (2015), pp. 45–46: ‘Die Begründungs des Gesetzes umfasst alles Dokumentierte, also sowohl Hinweise im Gesetz, als auch in allen Materialien, die über angenommene Tatsachen, Regelungsanlässe, Absichten, Intentionen, Zielvorstellungen und Motivationen Auskunft geben’.

  5. 5.

    Whether legisprudence neglects the public or civic side of legislative justification (Bello-Hutt 2021, p. 200) is debatable; cf. e.g. Oliver-Lalana (2005a), pp. 254–255.

  6. 6.

    Among many others, see e.g. Waldron (2006), as well as Mill (2001), pp. 54 ff.

  7. 7.

    Pound (1908, pp. 405–406) already counselled to be ‘more cautious in criticizing the legislature,’ noting that ‘crudity and carelessness have too often characterized […] lawmaking both legislative and judicial’ and ‘do not inhere necessarily in the one any more than in the other.’ In the same vein, Cohen (1956, p. 389) challenged four notions that ‘seem to dominate the account of the legislative process: (1) that those in control of it will respond only to the interests of dominant private pressure groups; (2) that […] argument and persuasion serve no useful function; (3) that force (power of the stronger) is the only real arbiter of group conflicts; and (4) that […] rational criteria for dealing with conflicts between competing private group interests are unavailable. Because these views furnish the basis for much of the current attitude towards the practice of legislative law’, one should ‘determine whether they are products of a mind’s eye in focus, or whether they suffer from distortion and exaggeration.’ As to legislative debates, however, Cohen (1952, pp. 35–36) was rather sceptical. Cf. Luce (1922), p. 316: ‘the common charge that nearly all of debate is a waste of time, useless garrulity, vain mouthing, is based on a complete misconception of both the purpose and the nature of legislative argument.’

  8. 8.

    With some adaptations, my approach is largely based on Atienza’s (1997, 1992) multi-level model of legislative rationality—with an eye on the works of A. La Spina, J. Habermas, K. Tuori, L. Wintgens, or J. Waldron, among others.

  9. 9.

    On the symmetry between making and construing statutes, see recently e.g. Krell (2018, p. 132), recalling that legisprudence, ‘when filtered through judging, [...] becomes statutory interpretation’.

  10. 10.

    On legislative rights review and constitutional interpretation by MPs, see e.g. Hiebert (2012), Fisher (1985), Pickerill (2004), Tushnet (2009) or, more recently, Jackson (2016) and Appleby and Olijnyk (2018).

  11. 11.

    Similarly, Agne (2011), pp. 161–162; cf. also Walton (1998), p. 245: ‘An answer to a question can be locally irrelevant to the question it was a reply to’ but may have ‘global relevance to the ultimate conclusion at issue’.

  12. 12.

    As noted, debate minutes are regarded here as a distillate or concentrate of a larger process of legislative justification This means that reconstruction and analysis require connecting MPs’ deliberation to the rest of justificatory materials within or even surrounding the lawmaking proceedings, inasmuch as these are directly or indirectly resorted to in parliamentary speeches. Insofar as debates are a non-self-sufficient source of legislative justification, their evaluation must also take external information and evidence into account (Sect. 5).

  13. 13.

    For an overview, see Bächtiger (2014, 2018), Quirk and Bendix (2011) or Bächtiger et al. (2018). See also Bächtiger and Beste (2017), Mucciaroni and Quirk (2006, 2010), Steiner et al. (2004), Tschentscher et al. (2010), Steiner (2012), Lord (2013) or Lord and Tamvaki (2013). On the argumentative turn in public policy analysis, see Hansson and Hirsch Hadorn (2016), or Fischer and Forester (1993).

  14. 14.

    See especially Ihnen (2012, 2017), Fairclough (2016, 2018) and Fairclough and Fairclough (2012).

  15. 15.

    With at least two felicitous exceptions coming from the fields of pragmadialectics (Ihnen 2017) and political discourse analysis (Fairclough 2016, 2018). C. Ihnen has suggested a specific set of critical questions to evaluate the sufficiency of the justification of government bills as discussed in the first reading on the floor of the Chilean congress. Her questions cover, inter alia, moral, political, constitutional, and feasibility aspects—yet, the pragmatic argumentation scheme she uses remains unspecific. On her part, I. Fairclough combines critical discourse analysis and argumentation theory to develop a specific deliberation scheme, but her critical questions only indirectly include legisprudential items. On the evaluative use of schemes and critical questions, see below Sects. 3.2 and 4.

  16. 16.

    A theory built on the participant perspective, i.e. on the internal point of view of lawmakers who take their job seriously (Oliver-Lalana and Wintgens 2019).

  17. 17.

    To name but only two shortcomings: the proposal is designed for a generic or standard context of legislation (a good evaluation method should adapt to a variety of contexts, but this requires a typology of laws and legislative scenarios I lack); and it is limited to the moment of enactment, i.e. it assumes an ex ante perspective on legislation (whereas evaluation should incorporate retrospective elements, for one key tenet of legisprudence is that legislative justification must be seen as an ongoing practice: see Wintgens 2012, pp. 267 ff. and 302–303).

  18. 18.

    Figure 1 above displays first-order reasons only, but usually these reasons are, in turn, claims sustained by (i.e. conclusions resulting from) second-order reasons and considerations. MPs themselves may exhaust or saturate this second-order justification, but they can also offer it by implicitly or explicitly referring to external materials. In this connection, the richer or deeper the justification is, the greater the informative value of legislative argumentation—also for the purposes of constitutional and statutory interpretation: cf. already Freund (1926, p. 316), noting that ‘congressional debates sometimes throw a valuable light on the legal aspects of legislation’.

  19. 19.

    Cf. e.g. Brest (1975), Tushnet (2009), or Mendes da Rocha (2010).

  20. 20.

    See Johnson (2000), and, for legal contexts, Atienza (2006) or Weinberger (1989), pp. 381 ff.

  21. 21.

    I am using ‘dialectical’ in a loose sense covering also indirect argumentative interchanges during the whole debate series—hence the word ‘deliberative’ in parentheses. The term ‘thoroughness’ might be replaced with ‘correctness’ if the latter is not understood as ‘substantial’ plausibility but as ‘dialectical’ correctness.

  22. 22.

    Cf. e.g. Mendes da Rocha (2010, pp. 132–133), stressing the gradability of legislative deliberation quality.

  23. 23.

    See e.g. Hirst v. UK (No. 2), ECtHR 6 Dec 2005, para 79; or Alajos Kiss v. Hungary, ECtHR 20 May 2010, para 41.

  24. 24.

    But I do not think that this ‘internal’ justification can straightforwardly be described as balancing (see Atienza 2019, p. 202, suggesting that ‘perhaps it may even be said that balancing is something like the internal justification scheme of legislative argumentation’, i.e. ‘the legislative counterpart of judicial syllogism’).

  25. 25.

    Legislation is ‘teleological, purposive creation of law’, ‘goal-directed social behaviour’; ‘when the lawgiver makes an evaluative decision, this means that he regards a certain final result as worth advancing, i.e. as good’, ‘wants certain final states to be realized’ and ‘deems lawmaking as a means for achieving them. The talk about evaluative decisions can thus […] be rendered into the language of teleology’ (Aarnio 1983, pp. 245–247). Cf. Weinberger (1989), p. 278 ff. On the teleological nature of legislation, Zitelmann (1904), pp. 7 ff. and, recently, Zamboni (2017) or Kornhauser (2018).

  26. 26.

    The intricacies of legislative balancing cannot be discussed here (see e.g. Sieckmann 2016, 2019). Elsewhere (Oliver-Lalana 2021) I have characterised legislative balancing as a threefold legisprudential duty. Roughly, lawmakers must first weigh arguments justifying the occasion for legislative intervention against those for legislative inaction, i.e. for maintaining the pre-existing legal framework; second, they must weigh arguments justifying the choice of the modality of intervention amongst a pool of regulatory options; and third, they must evaluate the proportionality of the proposed statutory content in the light of a comparative assessment of alternative contents.

  27. 27.

    ‘An argument scheme is an abstract characterization of the way in which in a particular type of argumentation a premise used in support of a standpoint is related to that standpoint in order to bring about a transfer of acceptance from that premise to the standpoint. Depending on the kind of relationship that is established in the argument scheme, specific kinds of evaluative questions—usually referred to as critical questions—are appropriate to evaluate the argumentation. The critical questions that are associated with an argument scheme capture the specific pragmatic rationale for bringing about the transition of acceptance from the premise to the standpoint. Thus the argument scheme that is used in a specific type of argumentation defines, as it were, how the ‘internal organization’ of the argumentation is to be judged’ (van Eemeren et al. 2014, p. 19).

  28. 28.

    In the field of public policy argumentation and advocacy, one finds approaches that come close to this evaluative use of argument schemes and critical questions: cf. e.g. Rybacki and Rybacki (1996), pp. 191 ff. or Dalton and Butler (2015), pp. 25 ff., 42 ff.

  29. 29.

    Cf. Cohen (1952), pp. 34–35: introducing a bill ‘involves a complex of at least three distinct elements’: ‘first of all, that the author of the proposal assumes the existence of a fact situation, the correction of which is sought on the legislative level; secondly, that the method advanced for dealing with the situation is believed to be an appropriate method or means for bringing about an immediate end or goal; thirdly, that the immediate end sought would be instrumental in achieving an even higher or more inclusive end or goal. These constituent elements—the present fact situation, the means-ends hypothesis, the instrumental value judgment, together constitute the very essence of a legislative proposal. […] [A] bill would be defective and thus vulnerable to attack if the assumptions which underlie any one or all of the three constituent elements would be found wanting. In the same way, a judicial decision would be defective when a law would be applied to an erroneous set of facts—when, for example; a criminal statute making it unlawful to take the life of another human would be applied with full sanction to one who really did not commit the act. In the legislative realm, what would result would be a non-realization of a value goal; in the judicial, it would be a denial of justice’. Cf. however Linde (1976), pp. 222 ff.

  30. 30.

    This is an amended version of the list of CQs presented in Oliver-Lalana (2018). Here I dispense with distinctions (and related argumentation-theoretical discussions) about different ways of questioning arguments, and simply connect questions to premises or sub-premises. Let me just remark that objections may not only affect individual premises but also the very conclusion, showing that it is untenable and should therefore be abandoned. In legislative debates, CQs normally come up not as questions but as objections or as counterarguments (undercutters or rebuttals)—yet, they may also be formulated as genuine questions, i.e. as simple requests for reasons or justification for one of the premises.

  31. 31.

    These CQs are inspired by the sequential model of proportionality, but do not preclude resorting to other accounts of proportionality, particularly as far as social rights are concerned (cf. Clérico 2018, pp. 32 ff., or Bernal 2017, pp. 497 ff.).

  32. 32.

    Actually, once we have a scheme for legislative justification and a matching set of critical questions, a legisprudential approach could further profit from the wide range of analysis, evaluation, and modelling possibilities that argumentation and discourse analysis scholars derive from these tools.

  33. 33.

    In argumentation theory, there is discussion about what the arguer’s dialectical obligations are and when they can be said to have been discharged (see e.g. Johnson 2000, pp. 332–333, Johnson 2003, p. 49; cf. Blair 2012, pp. 3 ff.). Nor is it clear how strong the burden of proof should be for bill proponents (cf. Walton 2015, pp. 215 ff).

  34. 34.

    Critical questions are iterative and remain open until the end of debate. By the same token, MPs can improve their knowledge on the legislative scenario until the final voting. Cf. Walton (2015), pp. 180–181.

  35. 35.

    On adequacy as a criterion for dialectical correctness, see e.g. Johnson (2003), p. 49; cf. also van Eemeren et al. (2014), pp. 385 ff., Blair (2012), pp. 87 ff.; on the pertinence criterion, see e.g. Santibáñez (2011), pp. 453 ff.

  36. 36.

    In legisprudential terms, the mere occurrence of fallacious moves needs not necessarily lead to a negative appraisal of deliberations: rather, the true problem arises when fallacies are not corrected or go unchallenged (Laehn 2004).

  37. 37.

    Even if amendments are the price to be paid in return for parliamentary support, or if they are the result of secret bargaining or informal negotiation between parliamentary parties or party leaders, MPs will normally offer some public justification when debating the bill.

  38. 38.

    An evaluator may well use CQs directly to assess, on her own, the substantial correctness or plausibility of each of the premises of the scheme. But before proceeding to this layer of evaluation, one should first consider what MPs have actually justified and how.

  39. 39.

    Actually, Mucciaroni and Quirk (2006, 2010) combine an epistemic with a dialectic or deliberative assessment. After rating ‘effect claims’ as supported, partially supported or unsupported, they establish debate intelligence by calculating claim rebuttals, concessions and reassertions. Cf. also Esterling’s (2011) approach to the evaluation of the plausibility of expert testimony in parliamentary hearings.

  40. 40.

    When there is a lack of clear evidence as to the correctness or reliability of legislative premises, one could focus on whether the process by which they have been arrived at meets basic criteria of methodological quality. For example, the German Federal Constitutional Court sometimes assesses the plausibility of legislative diagnoses and prognoses by inspecting whether these were made with due care and prove ‘as reliable as possible’, thereby requiring lawmakers to carry out a ‘sufficient’, ‘essentially complete’ or even ‘as complete as possible’ fact-finding, not to overlook any ‘weighty’ or ‘relevant’ fact; and to ‘exhaust’ the ‘available’ knowledge sources and to ‘make use of’ all materials ‘within reach’ (see Oliver-Lalana 2016b and 2017).

  41. 41.

    On the representativeness of legislative argumentation, see e.g. Mendes da Rocha (2010) and, more recently, Valentini (2019). Cf. also Oliver-Lalana (2005a, b). On the double logics, ‘discursive’ and ‘positional’, of parliamentary deliberations, see Schäffer (2017), pp. 419 ff.

  42. 42.

    See Dryzek and Niemeyer (2008).

  43. 43.

    A converging criterion could be authenticity, i.e. one could look to whether legislative decisions are actually justified on behalf of all citizens and promote the general good, or, rather, are the result of legislative capture and (spurious) special interests. Quality discourse indexes (the most detailed instruments developed so far to evaluate parliamentary deliberations) include specific indicators to measure this aspect, depending on the type of interests conveyed through MPs’ arguments: ‘Do speakers cast their justifications in terms of common good conceptions or of narrow group/constituency interests?’ (Tschentscher et al. 2010, p. 26); ‘How far do representatives justify their views with reference to notions of the public good that cover different publics, including (a) their constituents, (b) the public of the polity as a whole, or (c) all affected individuals?’ (Lord 2013, p. 252). Cf. also Steiner et al. (2004), p. 58 and Steiner (2012), p. 270.

  44. 44.

    See above Sect. 4.

References

  • Aarnio A (1983) Towards a theory of legislation and its role in societal change. Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence. Akateeminen Kirjakauppa, Helsinki, pp 245–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Agne H (2011) Answering questions in parliament during budget debates. Parliam Aff 64:153–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1995) Recht, Vernunft, Diskurs. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Google Scholar 

  • Appleby G, Olijnyk A (2018) Constitutional deliberation in the legislative process. In: Levy R et al (eds) The Cambridge handbook of deliberative constitutionalism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 88–100

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M (1992) Practical reason and legislation. Ratio Juris 5:269–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M (1997) Contribución a una teoría de la legislación. Civitas, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M (2006) El derecho como argumentación. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza M (2019) Legislation and argumentation: towards a model for the analysis of legislative reasoning. In: Oliver-Lalana AD (ed) Conceptions and misconceptions of legislation. Springer, Cham, pp 176–206

    Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger A (2014) Debate and deliberation in legislatures. In: Martin S et al (eds) The Oxford handbook of legislative studies. OUP, Oxford, pp 145–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger A (2018) A preface to studying deliberation empirically. In: Bächtiger A et al (eds) The Oxford handbook on deliberative democracy. OUP, Oxford, pp 657–662

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger A, Beste S (2017) Deliberative citizens, (non) deliberative politicians: a rejoinder. prospects and limits of deliberative democracy (Daedalus - Special Issue), pp 106–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger A, Bendix W, Quirk P (2018) Institutional deliberation. In: Bächtiger A et al (eds) The Oxford handbook on deliberative democracy. OUP, Oxford, pp 273–299

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bello-Hutt D (2021) Deliberative, republican, and egalitarian institutional alternatives for popular constitutionalism. Revista Derecho del Estado 48:183–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernal C (2017) The constitutional adjudication of positive social and economic rights by means of the proportionality analysis. In: Borowski M et al (eds) Rechtsphilosophie und Grundrechtstheorie. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 497–521

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair A (2012) Groundwork in the theory of argumentation. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brest P (1975) The conscientious legislator’s guide to constitutional interpretation. Stanford Law Rev 27:585–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clérico L (2018) Proportionality in social rights adjudication: making it workable. In: Duarte D, Sampaio JS (eds) Proportionality in law. Springer, Cham, pp 25–48

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (1952) Hearing on a bill: legislative folklore. Minnesota Law Rev 37:34–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (1956) Good man and the role of reason in legislative law. Cornell Law Rev 41(3):386–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalton P, Butler JR (2015) Public policy argumentation and debate. P. Lang, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek JS, Niemeyer S (2008) Discursive representation. Am Polit Sci Rev 102(4):481–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duxbury N (2013) Elements of legislation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Esterling K (2011) ‘Deliberative disagreement’ in U.S. health policy committee hearings. Legis Stud Q 63:169–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough I (2016) Evaluating policy as argument. Crit Discourse Stud 13:57–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough I (2018) Conductive argumentation in the UK fracking debate. Proceedings of the 2nd European Conference on Argumentation. Studies in Logic and Argumentation II. College Publications, London, pp 297–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough I, Fairclough N (2012) Political discourse analysis. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Freund E (1926) Standards of American legislation. An estimate of restrictive and constructive factors. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher L (1985) Constitutional interpretation by members of congress. North Carolina Law Rev 63:707–747

    Google Scholar 

  • Gartz H (2015) Begründungspflicht des Gesetzgeber. Das verfassungsrechtliche Verhandlungsgebot. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier T (2010) A practical study of argument, 10th edn. Wadsworth, Belmont

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO, Hirsch Hadorn G (eds) (2016) The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiebert J (2012) Parliamentary engagement with the Charter: rethinking the idea of legislative rights review. Supreme Court Law Rev 58:87–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Horack FE (1937) The common law of legislation. Iowa Law Rev 23:41–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Horack FE (1938) Do legislators think like judges? State Gov 11(9):163–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihnen C (2012) Pragmatic argumentation in lawmaking debates. Sic Sat, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihnen C (2017) La argumentación por consecuencias en el debate legislativo chileno: preguntas críticas para evaluar su suficiencia. Onomázein 37:218–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson V (2016) Pro-constitutional representation. William Mary Law Rev 57:1717–1788

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson RH (2000) Manifest rationality: a pragmatic theory of argument. Erlbaum, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson RH (2003) The dialectical tier revisited. In: van Eemeren FH et al (eds) Anyone who has a view. Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 41–53

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser LA (2018) Choosing ends and choosing means: teleological reasoning in law. In: Bongiovanni G et al (eds) Handbook of legal reasoning and argumentation. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 387–412

    Google Scholar 

  • Krell MR (2018) Judging as Soccer: jurisprudence, legisprudence, and metaphor. Elon Law Rev 10(1):125–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Laehn T (2004) Legislative Deliberation and the Rhetorical Foundations of Democracy: A Preface to an Assessment of the Quality of Senate Deliberation. Available at https://www.drake.edu/media/departmentsoffices/dussj/2006-2003documents/LegislativeLaehn.pdf. Accessed 1 Feb 2021

  • Linde H (1976) Due process of lawmaking. Nebraska Law Rev 55:197–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord C (2013) No representation without justification? J Eur Public Policy 20:243–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord C, Tamvaki D (2013) The politics of justification? Applying the ‘Discourse Quality Index’ to the study of the European Parliament. Eur Polit Sci Rev 5:27–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce R (1922) The science of legislation I – Legislative procedure. Houghton Mifflin Company, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes da Rocha M (2010) Representação, deliberação e estudos legislativos. Revista Brasileira de Ciéncias Sociais 74:121–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (2001) Representative Government [1861]. Batoche Books, Kitchener

    Google Scholar 

  • Mucciaroni G, Quirk P (2006) Deliberative choices. Debating public policy in congress. The Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Mucciaroni G, Quirk P (2010) Rhetoric and reality: going beyond discourse ethics in assessing legislative deliberation. Legisprudence 4:35–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nourse V (2016) Misreading law, misreading democracy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2005a) Legitimacy through rationality. In: Wintgens L (ed) The theory and practice of legislation. Essays in legisprudence. Ashgate, Aldershot, pp 239–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2005b) Über die Begründungsfähigkeit der legislativen Argumentation. In: Sieckmann J (ed) Verfassung und Argumentation. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 129–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2013) Rational lawmaking and legislative reasoning in parliamentary debates. In: Wintgens L, Oliver-Lalana AD (eds) The rationality and justification of legislation. Springer, Cham, pp 135–184

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2014) Normas y razones: un estudio sobre argumentación legislativa. In: Grández P, Morales F (eds) La argumentación jurídica en el Estado Constitucional. Palestra, Lima, pp 491–528

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2016a) Legislative argumentation and the rule of law. In: Feteris E et al (eds) Legal argumentation and the rule of law. Eleven International Publishing, The Hague, pp 159–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2016b) El control judicial del proceso de justificación legislativa y la teoría de los principios formales. In: Portocarrero J (ed) Ponderación y discrecionalidad. Universidad Externado, Bogotá, pp 311–376

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2017) Zur gerichtlichen Prüfung des Verfahrens legislativer Begründung – einige methodische Bemerkungen. In: Borowski M et al (eds) Rechtsphilosophie und Grundrechtstheorie. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 717–750

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2018) Migliori e peggiori argomentazioni legislative. In: Ferraro F, Zorzetto S (eds) La motivazione delle leggi. Giapichelli, Torino, pp 67–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD (2021) Thou shalt balance. In: Sieckmann J (ed) Proportionality, balancing, and rights. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver-Lalana AD, Wintgens L (2019) Legisprudence. In: Sellers M, Kirste S (eds) Encyclopedia of the philosophy of law and social philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickerill JM (2004) Constitutional deliberation in congress. Duke University Press, Durham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pound R (1908) Common law and legislation. Harv Law Rev 21:383–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quirk P, Bendix W (2011) Deliberation in congress. The Oxford handbook of the American congress. OUP, Oxford, pp 550–574

    Google Scholar 

  • Radbruch G (1929) Einführung in die Rechtswissenschaft. Quelle & Meyer, Leipzig (Gesamtausgabe. Rechtsphilosophie I. CF Müller, Heidelberg, 1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rybacki KC, Rybacki DJ (1996) Advocacy and opposition. An introduction to argumentation, 3rd edn. Allyn and Bacon, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Santibáñez C (2011) Pertinencia. In: Vega L, Olmos P (eds) Compendio de lógica, argumentación y retórica. Trotta, Madrid, pp 453–455

    Google Scholar 

  • Saward M (2006) The representative claim. Contemp Polit Theory 5:97–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schäffer A (2017) Deliberation in representative institutions: an analytical framework for a systemic approach. Aust J Polit Sci 52(3):419–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sehl M (2019) Was will der Gesetzgeber? Ziel und Methode rationaler Argumentation mit Gesetzenmaterialien. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2016) Rational lawmaking, proportionality and balancing. In: Meßerschmidt K, Oliver-Lalana AD (eds) Rational lawmaking under review. Springer, Cham, pp 349–372

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2019) Legislation as balancing. In: Oliver-Lalana AD (ed) Conceptions and misconceptions of legislation. Springer, Cham, pp 133–152

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner J (2012) The foundations of deliberative democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner J et al (2004) Deliberative politics in action. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tschentscher A et al (2010) Deliberation in parliaments. Legisprudence 4:13–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (2009) Is congress capable of conscientious, responsible constitutional interpretation? Boston Univ Law Rev 89:499–509

    Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati N (2000) Representation as advocacy: a study of democratic deliberation. Polit Theory 28(6):758–786

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini C (2019) The legislative assembly and representative deliberation. Am J Jurisprud 64(1):105–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH et al (2014) Handbook of argumentation theory. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2006) Principles of legislation. In: Bauman W, Kahana T (eds) The least examined branch: the role of legislatures in the constitutional state. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 15–32

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (1998) The new dialectic: conversational contexts of argument. University of Toronto Press, Toronto

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (2007) Evaluating practical reasoning. Synthese 157:197–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (2015) Goal-based reasoning for argumentation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberger O (1989) Rechtslogik [1970], 2nd edn. Duncker und Humblot, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman C (1971) Challenge and response. Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale

    Google Scholar 

  • Wintgens LJ (2012) Legisprudence. Practical reason in legislation. Ashgate, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1971) Legal decision and its justification. In: Hubien H (ed) Le raisonnement juridique, Brussel

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamboni M (2017) Goals and measures of legislation. In: Xanthaki H, Karpen U (eds) Legislation in Europe. Bloomsbury, Oxford, pp 96–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Zitelmann E (1904) Die Kunst der Gesetzgebung. Von Zaehn & Jaensch, Dresden

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For inspiring comments and insightful criticism I am indebted to the participants in seminars and lectures at the universities of Zaragoza, Málaga, A Coruña, Alicante and Milano, as well as in the Legisprudence Workshop held at the 29th IVR World Congress in Luzern. A special word of gratitude goes for Francesco Ferraro, Silvia Zorzetto, Manuel Atienza, José Luis Díez Ripollés, and José Antonio Seoane. The preparation of this chapter was supported by the Spanish Ministry of Science (Project RTI2018-095843-B-I00, MCIU/AEI/FEDER-UE) and the University of Zaragoza’s Legal Sociology Lab (Research Group Strategy of the Government of Aragon).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to A. Daniel Oliver-Lalana .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Oliver-Lalana, A.D. (2022). On the Structure and Stock Issues of Legislative Justification (in Parliamentary Debates). In: Ferraro, F., Zorzetto, S. (eds) Exploring the Province of Legislation. Legisprudence Library, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-87262-5_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-87262-5_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-87261-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-87262-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics